fbpx
Wikipedia

Idealization (philosophy of science)

In philosophy of science, idealization is the process by which scientific models assume facts about the phenomenon being modeled that are strictly false but make models easier to understand or solve. That is, it is determined whether the phenomenon approximates an "ideal case," then the model is applied to make a prediction based on that ideal case.

If an approximation is accurate, the model will have high predictive power; for example, it is not usually necessary to account for air resistance when determining the acceleration of a falling bowling ball, and doing so would be more complicated. In this case, air resistance is idealized to be zero. Although this is not strictly true, it is a good approximation because its effect is negligible compared to that of gravity.

Idealizations may allow predictions to be made when none otherwise could be. For example, the approximation of air resistance as zero was the only option before the formulation of Stokes' law allowed the calculation of drag forces. Many debates surrounding the usefulness of a particular model are about the appropriateness of different idealizations.

Early use

Galileo used the concept of idealization in order to formulate the law of free fall. Galileo, in his study of bodies in motion, set up experiments that assumed frictionless surfaces and spheres of perfect roundness. The crudity of ordinary objects has the potential to obscure their mathematical essence, and idealization is used to combat this tendency.

The most well-known example of idealization in Galileo's experiments is in his analysis of motion. Galileo predicted that if a perfectly round and smooth ball were rolled along a perfectly smooth horizontal plane, there would be nothing to stop the ball (in fact, it would slide instead of roll, because rolling requires friction). This hypothesis is predicated on the assumption that there is no air resistance.

Other examples

Mathematics

Geometry involves the process of idealization because it studies ideal entities, forms and figures. Perfect circles, spheres, straight lines and angles are abstractions that help us think about and investigate the world.

Science

An example of the use of idealization in physics is in Boyle's Gas Law: Given any x and any y, if all the molecules in y are perfectly elastic and spherical, possess equal masses and volumes, have negligible size, and exert no forces on one another except during collisions, then if x is a gas and y is a given mass of x which is trapped in a vessel of variable size and the temperature of y is kept constant, then any decrease of the volume of y increases the pressure of y proportionally, and vice versa.

In physics, people will often solve for Newtonian systems without friction. While we know that friction is present in actual systems, solving the model without friction can provide insights to the behavior of actual systems where the force of friction is negligible.

Social science

It has been argued by the "Poznań School" (in Poland) that Karl Marx used idealization in the social sciences (see the works written by Leszek Nowak).[1] Similarly, in economic models individuals are assumed to make maximally rational choices.[2] This assumption, although known to be violated by actual humans, can often lead to insights about the behavior of human populations.

In psychology, idealization refers to a defence mechanism in which a person perceives another to be better (or have more desirable attributes) than would actually be supported by the evidence. This sometimes occurs in child custody conflicts. The child of a single parent frequently may imagine ("idealize") the (ideal) absent parent to have those characteristics of a perfect parent. However, the child may find imagination is favorable to reality. Upon meeting that parent, the child may be happy for a while, but disappointed later when learning that the parent does not actually nurture, support and protect as the former caretaker parent had.

A notable proponent of idealization in both the natural sciences and the social sciences was the economist Milton Friedman. In his view, the standard by which we should assess an empirical theory is the accuracy of the predictions that that theory makes. This amounts to an instrumentalist conception of science, including social science. He also argues against the criticism that we should reject an empirical theory if we find that the assumptions of that theory are not realistic, in the sense of being imperfect descriptions of reality. This criticism is wrongheaded, Friedman claims, because the assumptions of any empirical theory are necessarily unrealistic, since such a theory must abstract from the particular details of each instance of the phenomenon that the theory seeks to explain. This leads him to the conclusion that “[t]ruly important and significant hypotheses will be found to have ‘assumptions’ that are wildly inaccurate descriptive representations of reality, and, in general, the more significant the theory, the more unrealistic the assumptions (in this sense).”[3] Consistently with this, he makes the case for seeing the assumptions of neoclassical positive economics as not importantly different from the idealizations that are employed in natural science, drawing a comparison between treating a falling body as if it were falling in a vacuum and viewing firms as if they were rational actors seeking to maximize expected returns.[4]

Against this instrumentalist conception, which judges empirical theories on the basis of their predictive success, the social theorist Jon Elster has argued that an explanation in the social sciences is more convincing when it ‘opens the black box’ — that is to say, when the explanation specifies a chain of events leading from the independent variable to the dependent variable. The more detailed this chain, argues Elster, the less likely it is that the explanation specifying that chain is neglecting a hidden variable that could account for both the independent variable and the dependent variable.[5] Relatedly, he also contends that social-scientific explanations should be formulated in terms of causal mechanisms, which he defines as “frequently occurring and easily recognizable causal patterns that are triggered under generally unknown conditions or with indeterminate consequences.”[6] All this informs Elster's disagreement with rational-choice theory in general and Friedman in particular. On Elster's analysis, Friedman is right to argue that criticizing the assumptions of an empirical theory as unrealistic is misguided, but he is mistaken to defend on this basis the value of rational-choice theory in social science (especially economics). Elster presents two reasons for why this is the case: first, because rational-choice theory does not illuminate “a mechanism that brings about non-intentionally the same outcome that a superrational agent could have calculated intentionally”, a mechanism “that would simulate rationality”; and second, because rational-choice explanations do not provide precise, pinpoint predictions, comparable to those of quantum mechanics. When a theory can predict outcomes that precisely, then, Elster contends, we have reason to believe that theory is true.[7] Accordingly, Elster wonders whether the as-if assumptions of rational-choice theory help explain any social or political phenomenon.[7]

Limits on use

While idealization is used extensively by certain scientific disciplines, it has been rejected by others.[8] For instance, Edmund Husserl recognized the importance of idealization but opposed its application to the study of the mind, holding that mental phenomena do not lend themselves to idealization.[9]

Although idealization is considered one of the essential elements of modern science, it is nonetheless the source of continued controversy in the literature of the philosophy of science.[8] For example, Nancy Cartwright suggested that Galilean idealization presupposes tendencies or capacities in nature and that this allows for generalization beyond what is the ideal case.[10]

There is continued philosophical concern over how Galileo's idealization method assists in the description of the behavior of individuals or objects in the real world. Since the laws created through idealization (such as the ideal gas law) describe only the behavior of ideal bodies, these laws can only be used to predict the behavior of real bodies when a considerable number of factors have been physically eliminated (e.g. through shielding conditions) or ignored. Laws that account for these factors are usually more complicated and in some cases have not yet been developed.

See also

References

  1. ^ About the Poznań School, see F. Coniglione, Realtà ed astrazione. Scuola polacca ed epistemologia post-positivista, Catania:CUECM 1990
  2. ^ B. Hamminga, N.B. De Marchi (Eds.), Idealization VI: Idealization in Economics, Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, Vol. 38, Rodopi:Atlanta-Amsterdam 1994
  3. ^ Friedman, Milton (1953). "The Methodology of Positive Economics". Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. p. 14.
  4. ^ Friedman, Milton (1953). "The Methodology of Positive Economics". Essays in Positive Economics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. pp. 18, 21–22.
  5. ^ Elster, Jon (2015). Explaining Social Behavior: More Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 23–25.
  6. ^ Elster, Jon (2015). Explaining Social Behavior: More Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 26.
  7. ^ a b Elster, Jon (2015). Explaining Social Behavior: More Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 18.
  8. ^ a b Chuang Liu (2004), "Laws and Models in a Theory of Idealization", Synthese, 138 (3): 363–385, CiteSeerX 10.1.1.681.4412, doi:10.1023/b:synt.0000016425.36070.37, S2CID 18998321
  9. ^ Klawiter A (2004). Why did Husserl not become the Galileo of the Science of Consciousness? 2017-05-20 at the Wayback Machine.
  10. ^ Cartwright N (1994) Nature's capacities and their measurement. pp. 186–191.

Further reading

  • William F, Barr, A Pragmatic Analysis of Idealization in Physics, Philosophy of Science, Vol. 41, No. 1, pg 48, Mar. 1974.
  • Krzysztof Brzechczyn, (ed.), Idealization XIII: Modeling in History, Amsterdam-New York: Rodopi, 2009.
  • Nancy Cartwright, How the Laws of Physics Lie, Clarendon Press:Oxford 1983
  • Francesco Coniglione, Between Abstraction and Idealization: Scientific Practice and Philosophical Awareness, in F. Coniglione, R. Poli and R. Rollinger (Eds.), Idealization XI: Historical Studies on Abstraction, Atlanta-Amsterdam:Rodopi 2004, pp. 59–110.
  • Craig Dilworth, The Metaphysics of Science: An Account of Modern Science in Terms of Principles, Laws and Theories, Springer:Dordrecht 2007 (2a ed.)
  • Andrzej Klawiter, Why Did Husserl Not Become the Galileo of the Science of Consciousness?, in F. Coniglione, R. Poli and R. Rollinger, (Eds.), Idealization XI: Historical Studies on Abstraction, Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, Vol. 82, Rodopi:Atlanta-Amsterdam 2004, pp. 253–271.
  • Mansoor Niaz, The Role of Idealization in Science and Its Implications for Science Education, Journal of Science Education and Technology, Vol. 8, No. 2, 1999, pp. 145–150.
  • Leszek Nowak, The Structure of Idealization. Towards a Systematic Interpretation of the Marxian Idea of Science, Dordrecht:Reidel 1980
  • Leszek Nowak and Izabella Nowakowa, Idealization X: The Richness of Idealization, Amsterdam / Atlanta: Rodopi 2000.

idealization, philosophy, science, philosophy, science, idealization, process, which, scientific, models, assume, facts, about, phenomenon, being, modeled, that, strictly, false, make, models, easier, understand, solve, that, determined, whether, phenomenon, a. In philosophy of science idealization is the process by which scientific models assume facts about the phenomenon being modeled that are strictly false but make models easier to understand or solve That is it is determined whether the phenomenon approximates an ideal case then the model is applied to make a prediction based on that ideal case If an approximation is accurate the model will have high predictive power for example it is not usually necessary to account for air resistance when determining the acceleration of a falling bowling ball and doing so would be more complicated In this case air resistance is idealized to be zero Although this is not strictly true it is a good approximation because its effect is negligible compared to that of gravity Idealizations may allow predictions to be made when none otherwise could be For example the approximation of air resistance as zero was the only option before the formulation of Stokes law allowed the calculation of drag forces Many debates surrounding the usefulness of a particular model are about the appropriateness of different idealizations Contents 1 Early use 2 Other examples 2 1 Mathematics 2 2 Science 2 3 Social science 3 Limits on use 4 See also 5 References 6 Further readingEarly use EditGalileo used the concept of idealization in order to formulate the law of free fall Galileo in his study of bodies in motion set up experiments that assumed frictionless surfaces and spheres of perfect roundness The crudity of ordinary objects has the potential to obscure their mathematical essence and idealization is used to combat this tendency The most well known example of idealization in Galileo s experiments is in his analysis of motion Galileo predicted that if a perfectly round and smooth ball were rolled along a perfectly smooth horizontal plane there would be nothing to stop the ball in fact it would slide instead of roll because rolling requires friction This hypothesis is predicated on the assumption that there is no air resistance Other examples EditMathematics Edit Geometry involves the process of idealization because it studies ideal entities forms and figures Perfect circles spheres straight lines and angles are abstractions that help us think about and investigate the world Science Edit An example of the use of idealization in physics is in Boyle s Gas Law Given any x and any y if all the molecules in y are perfectly elastic and spherical possess equal masses and volumes have negligible size and exert no forces on one another except during collisions then if x is a gas and y is a given mass of x which is trapped in a vessel of variable size and the temperature of y is kept constant then any decrease of the volume of y increases the pressure of y proportionally and vice versa In physics people will often solve for Newtonian systems without friction While we know that friction is present in actual systems solving the model without friction can provide insights to the behavior of actual systems where the force of friction is negligible Social science Edit This section possibly contains original research Please improve it by verifying the claims made and adding inline citations Statements consisting only of original research should be removed May 2019 Learn how and when to remove this template message It has been argued by the Poznan School in Poland that Karl Marx used idealization in the social sciences see the works written by Leszek Nowak 1 Similarly in economic models individuals are assumed to make maximally rational choices 2 This assumption although known to be violated by actual humans can often lead to insights about the behavior of human populations In psychology idealization refers to a defence mechanism in which a person perceives another to be better or have more desirable attributes than would actually be supported by the evidence This sometimes occurs in child custody conflicts The child of a single parent frequently may imagine idealize the ideal absent parent to have those characteristics of a perfect parent However the child may find imagination is favorable to reality Upon meeting that parent the child may be happy for a while but disappointed later when learning that the parent does not actually nurture support and protect as the former caretaker parent had A notable proponent of idealization in both the natural sciences and the social sciences was the economist Milton Friedman In his view the standard by which we should assess an empirical theory is the accuracy of the predictions that that theory makes This amounts to an instrumentalist conception of science including social science He also argues against the criticism that we should reject an empirical theory if we find that the assumptions of that theory are not realistic in the sense of being imperfect descriptions of reality This criticism is wrongheaded Friedman claims because the assumptions of any empirical theory are necessarily unrealistic since such a theory must abstract from the particular details of each instance of the phenomenon that the theory seeks to explain This leads him to the conclusion that t ruly important and significant hypotheses will be found to have assumptions that are wildly inaccurate descriptive representations of reality and in general the more significant the theory the more unrealistic the assumptions in this sense 3 Consistently with this he makes the case for seeing the assumptions of neoclassical positive economics as not importantly different from the idealizations that are employed in natural science drawing a comparison between treating a falling body as if it were falling in a vacuum and viewing firms as if they were rational actors seeking to maximize expected returns 4 Against this instrumentalist conception which judges empirical theories on the basis of their predictive success the social theorist Jon Elster has argued that an explanation in the social sciences is more convincing when it opens the black box that is to say when the explanation specifies a chain of events leading from the independent variable to the dependent variable The more detailed this chain argues Elster the less likely it is that the explanation specifying that chain is neglecting a hidden variable that could account for both the independent variable and the dependent variable 5 Relatedly he also contends that social scientific explanations should be formulated in terms of causal mechanisms which he defines as frequently occurring and easily recognizable causal patterns that are triggered under generally unknown conditions or with indeterminate consequences 6 All this informs Elster s disagreement with rational choice theory in general and Friedman in particular On Elster s analysis Friedman is right to argue that criticizing the assumptions of an empirical theory as unrealistic is misguided but he is mistaken to defend on this basis the value of rational choice theory in social science especially economics Elster presents two reasons for why this is the case first because rational choice theory does not illuminate a mechanism that brings about non intentionally the same outcome that a superrational agent could have calculated intentionally a mechanism that would simulate rationality and second because rational choice explanations do not provide precise pinpoint predictions comparable to those of quantum mechanics When a theory can predict outcomes that precisely then Elster contends we have reason to believe that theory is true 7 Accordingly Elster wonders whether the as if assumptions of rational choice theory help explain any social or political phenomenon 7 Limits on use EditWhile idealization is used extensively by certain scientific disciplines it has been rejected by others 8 For instance Edmund Husserl recognized the importance of idealization but opposed its application to the study of the mind holding that mental phenomena do not lend themselves to idealization 9 Although idealization is considered one of the essential elements of modern science it is nonetheless the source of continued controversy in the literature of the philosophy of science 8 For example Nancy Cartwright suggested that Galilean idealization presupposes tendencies or capacities in nature and that this allows for generalization beyond what is the ideal case 10 There is continued philosophical concern over how Galileo s idealization method assists in the description of the behavior of individuals or objects in the real world Since the laws created through idealization such as the ideal gas law describe only the behavior of ideal bodies these laws can only be used to predict the behavior of real bodies when a considerable number of factors have been physically eliminated e g through shielding conditions or ignored Laws that account for these factors are usually more complicated and in some cases have not yet been developed See also EditSpherical cowReferences Edit About the Poznan School see F Coniglione Realta ed astrazione Scuola polacca ed epistemologia post positivista Catania CUECM 1990 B Hamminga N B De Marchi Eds Idealization VI Idealization in Economics Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities Vol 38 Rodopi Atlanta Amsterdam 1994 Friedman Milton 1953 The Methodology of Positive Economics Essays in Positive Economics Chicago University of Chicago Press p 14 Friedman Milton 1953 The Methodology of Positive Economics Essays in Positive Economics Chicago University of Chicago Press pp 18 21 22 Elster Jon 2015 Explaining Social Behavior More Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 23 25 Elster Jon 2015 Explaining Social Behavior More Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 26 a b Elster Jon 2015 Explaining Social Behavior More Nuts and Bolts for the Social Sciences Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 18 a b Chuang Liu 2004 Laws and Models in a Theory of Idealization Synthese 138 3 363 385 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 681 4412 doi 10 1023 b synt 0000016425 36070 37 S2CID 18998321 Klawiter A 2004 Why did Husserl not become the Galileo of the Science of Consciousness Archived 2017 05 20 at the Wayback Machine Cartwright N 1994 Nature s capacities and their measurement pp 186 191 Further reading EditWilliam F Barr A Pragmatic Analysis of Idealization in Physics Philosophy of Science Vol 41 No 1 pg 48 Mar 1974 Krzysztof Brzechczyn ed Idealization XIII Modeling in History Amsterdam New York Rodopi 2009 Nancy Cartwright How the Laws of Physics Lie Clarendon Press Oxford 1983 Francesco Coniglione Between Abstraction and Idealization Scientific Practice and Philosophical Awareness in F Coniglione R Poli and R Rollinger Eds Idealization XI Historical Studies on Abstraction Atlanta Amsterdam Rodopi 2004 pp 59 110 Craig Dilworth The Metaphysics of Science An Account of Modern Science in Terms of Principles Laws and Theories Springer Dordrecht 2007 2a ed Andrzej Klawiter Why Did Husserl Not Become the Galileo of the Science of Consciousness in F Coniglione R Poli and R Rollinger Eds Idealization XI Historical Studies on Abstraction Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities Vol 82 Rodopi Atlanta Amsterdam 2004 pp 253 271 Mansoor Niaz The Role of Idealization in Science and Its Implications for Science Education Journal of Science Education and Technology Vol 8 No 2 1999 pp 145 150 Leszek Nowak The Structure of Idealization Towards a Systematic Interpretation of the Marxian Idea of Science Dordrecht Reidel 1980 Leszek Nowak and Izabella Nowakowa Idealization X The Richness of Idealization Amsterdam Atlanta Rodopi 2000 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Idealization philosophy of science amp oldid 1110746056, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.