fbpx
Wikipedia

Whig history

Whig history (or Whig historiography) is an approach to historiography that presents history as a journey from an oppressive and benighted past to a "glorious present".[1] The present described is generally one with modern forms of liberal democracy and constitutional monarchy: it was originally a satirical term for the patriotic grand narratives praising Britain's adoption of constitutional monarchy and the historical development of the Westminster system.[2] The term has also been applied widely in historical disciplines outside of British history (e.g. in the history of science) to describe "any subjection of history to what is essentially a teleological view of the historical process".[3] When the term is used in contexts other than British history, "whig history" (lowercase) is preferred.[3]

In the British context, whig historians emphasize the rise of constitutional government, personal freedoms and scientific progress.[4][5] The term is often applied generally (and pejoratively) to histories that present the past as the inexorable march of progress towards enlightenment. The term is also used extensively in the history of science to refer to historiography that focuses on the successful chains of theories and experiments that led to present-day theories, while ignoring failed theories and dead ends.[6]

Whig history laid the groundwork for modernization theory and the resulting deployment of development aid around the world after World War II, which has sometimes been criticized as destructive to its recipients.[7][8][page needed]

Terminology edit

The British historian Herbert Butterfield coined the term "Whig history" in his short but influential book The Whig Interpretation of History (1931).[9] It takes its name from the British Whigs, advocates of the power of Parliament, who opposed the Tories, advocates of the power of the king.[10]

Butterfield's usage of the term was not in relation to the British or American Whig parties or Whiggism, but rather took aim at "the nineteenth-century school of historiography that praised all progress and habitually associated Protestantism with liberal views of liberty".[11] The terms "whig" and "whiggish" are now used broadly, becoming "universal descriptors for all progressive narratives".[2]

When H. A. L. Fisher in 1928 gave a Raleigh lecture, he implied that the "whig historians" really were Whigs (i.e. associated with the Whig party or its Liberal successor) and had written centrist histories that were "good history despite their enthusiasm for Gladstonian or Liberal Unionist causes"; on introduction the term was mostly approbatory, unlike Butterfield's later use, since Fisher applauded Macaulay's "instructive and illuminating" history.[12] By the time Butterfield wrote his Whig Interpretation, he may have been beating a dead horse: P. B. M. Blaas, in his 1978 book Continuity and Anachronism, argued that whig history itself had lost all vitality by 1914.[13] Subsequent generations of academic historians have rejected Whig history because of its presentist and teleological assumption that history is driving toward some sort of goal.

The Whig Interpretation of History edit

Butterfield's purpose with writing his 1931 book was to criticise oversimplified narratives (or "abridgements") which interpreted past events in terms of the present for the purposes of achieving "drama and apparent moral clarity".[2] Butterfield especially noted:

It is part and parcel of the whig interpretation of history that it studies the past with reference to the present.[14]

Butterfield argued that this approach to history compromised the work of the historian in several ways. The emphasis on the inevitability of progress leads to the mistaken belief that the progressive sequence of events becomes "a line of causation", tempting the historian to go no further to investigate the causes of historical change.[15] The focus on the present as the goal of historical change leads the historian to a special kind of "abridgement", selecting only those events that seem important from the present point of view.[16]

He also criticised it for modernising the past: "the result [of whig history] is that to many of us [historical figures] seem much more modern than they really were, and even when we have corrected this impression by closer study we find it difficult to keep in mind the differences between their world and ours".[17]

Whig history is also criticised as having an overly dualist view with heroes on the side of liberty and freedom against traditionalist villains opposing the inevitability of progress.[18] It also casts an overly negative view of opposing parties to heroes described, taking such parties "to have contributed nothing to the making of the present" and at worst converting them into a "dummy that acts as a better foil to the grand whig virtues".[19] Butterfield illustrated this by criticising views of Martin Luther and the Reformation which "are inclined to write sometimes as though Protestantism in itself was somehow constituted to assist [the process of secularisation]"[20] and misconceptions that the British constitution was created by Whigs opposed by Tories rather than created by compromise and interplay mediated by then-political contingencies.[21]

He also felt that whig history viewed the world in terms of a morality play: that "[the whig historian imagines himself] inconclusive unless he can give a verdict; and studying Protestant and Catholic in the 16th century he feels that loose threads are still left hanging unless he can show which party was in the right".[22]

Butterfield instead advances a view of history stressing the accidental and contingent nature of events rather than some kind of inevitable and structural shift.[23] Moreover, he called upon historians "to evoke a certain sensibility towards the past, the sensibility which studies the past 'for the sake of the past', which delights in the concrete and the complex, which 'goes out to meet the past', which searches for 'unlikenesses between past and present'".[24][failed verification]

A decade later however, if under wartime pressure from the Second World War, Butterfield would note of the Whig interpretation that "whatever it may have done to our history, it has had a wonderful effect on our politics....In every Englishman there is hidden something of a whig that seems to tug at the heart-strings".[25]

Subsequent views edit

Butterfield's formulation has subsequently received much attention and the kind of historical writing he argued against in generalized terms is no longer academically respectable. Despite its polemical success, Butterfield's celebrated book was criticized by David Cannadine as "slight, confused, repetitive and superficial".[26] However, of the English tradition more broadly, Cannadine wrote:

It was fiercely partisan and righteously judgemental, dividing the personnel of the past into the good and the bad. And it did so on the basis of the marked preference for liberal and progressive causes, rather than conservative and reactionary ones ... Whig history was, in short, an extremely biased view of the past: eager to hand out moral judgements, and distorted by teleology, anachronism and present-mindedness.[27]

E. H. Carr in What is history? (1961) gave the book the backhanded compliment of being "a remarkable book in many ways" noting that "though it denounced the whig interpretation over some 130 pages, it did not... name a single whig except Fox, who was no historian, or a single historian save Acton, who was no whig".[28][2]

Michael Bentley analyses Butterfield's whig theory as referring to a canon of 19th-century historians in and of England (such as William Stubbs, James Anthony Froude, E. A. Freeman, J. R. Green, W. E. H. Lecky, Lord Acton, J. R. Seeley, S. R. Gardiner, C. H. Firth and J. B. Bury) that in fact excludes few except Thomas Carlyle.[29] The theory identifies the common factors and Bentley comments:

Carlyle apart, the so-called Whigs were predominantly Christian, predominantly Anglican, thinkers for whom the Reformation supplied the critical theatre of enquiry when considering the origins of modern England. When they wrote about the history of the English constitution, as so many of them did, they approached their story from the standpoint of having Good News to relate[30] ... If they could not have found the grandeur that they developed had they been writing half a century earlier, neither could they have supported their optimism had they lived to endure the barbarisms of the Somme and Passchendaele.[31]

Roger Scruton takes the theory underlying whig history to be centrally concerned with social progress and reaction, with the progressives shown as victors and benefactors.[32] According to Victor Feske, there is too much readiness to accept Butterfield's classic formulation from 1931 as definitive.[33]

British whig history edit

In Britain, whig history is a view of British history that sees it as a "steady evolution of British parliamentary institutions, benevolently watched over by Whig aristocrats, and steadily spreading social progress and prosperity".[4] It described a "continuity of institutions and practices since Anglo-Saxon times that lent to English history a special pedigree, one that instilled a distinctive temper in the English nation (as whigs liked to call it) and an approach to the world [which] issued in law and lent legal precedent a role in preserving or extending the freedoms of Englishmen".[5]

Paul Rapin de Thoyras's history of England, published in 1723, became "the classic Whig history" for the first half of the eighteenth century.[34][verification needed] Rapin claimed that the English had preserved their ancient constitution against the absolutist tendencies of the Stuarts. However, Rapin's history lost its place as the standard history of England in the late 18th century and early 19th century to that of David Hume.[citation needed]

William Blackstone's Commentaries on the Laws of England (1765–1769) reveals many Whiggish traits.[citation needed]

According to Arthur Marwick, however, Henry Hallam was the first whig historian, publishing Constitutional History of England in 1827, which "greatly exaggerated the importance of 'parliaments' or of bodies [whig historians] thought were parliaments" while tending "to interpret all political struggles in terms of the parliamentary situation in Britain [during] the nineteenth century, in terms, that is, of Whig reformers fighting the good fight against Tory defenders of the status quo".[35]

David Hume edit

In The History of England (1754–1761), Hume challenged whig views of the past and the whig historians in turn attacked Hume; but they could not dent his history. In the early 19th century, some whig historians came to incorporate Hume's views, dominant for the previous fifty years. These historians were members of the New Whigs around Charles James Fox (1749–1806) and Lord Holland (1773–1840) in opposition until 1830 and so "needed a new historical philosophy".[36] Fox himself intended to write a history of the Glorious Revolution of 1688, but only managed the first year of James II's reign. A fragment was published in 1808. James Mackintosh then sought to write a Whig history of the Glorious Revolution, published in 1834 as the History of the Revolution in England in 1688.

Thomas Babington Macaulay edit

Hume still dominated English historiography, but this changed when Thomas Babington Macaulay entered the field, utilising Fox and Mackintosh's work and manuscript collections. Macaulay's History of England was published in a series of volumes from 1848 to 1855.[35] It proved an immediate success, replacing Hume's history and becoming the new orthodoxy.[37] As if to introduce a linear progressive view of history, the first chapter of Macaulay's History of England proposes:

The history of our country during the last hundred and sixty years is eminently the history of physical, of moral, and of intellectual improvement.[38][4]

While Macaulay was a popular and celebrated historian of the whig school, his work did not feature in Butterfield's 1931 Whig Interpretation of History.[28] According to Ernst Breisach, "his style captivated the public as did his good sense of the past and firm whiggish convictions".[39]

William Stubbs edit

William Stubbs (1825–1901), the constitutional historian and influential teacher of a generation of historians, was the author of the extremely influential Constitutional History of England (published between 1873–78)[40] and became a crucial figure in the later survival and respectability of whig history. According to Reba Soffer,

Stubbs was a true believer who concealed his biases, even from himself, behind the façade of a dispassionate historian translating original documents into magisterial prose. His rhetorical gifts often obscured his combination of high church Anglicanism, whig history, and civic responsibility. In the Church of England, Stubbs saw the original model for the development and maintenance of English liberties.[41]

Stubb's history began with an imagined Anglo-Saxon past into which representative parliamentary institutions emerged and fought for control with the absolutist crown in various stages (including overreaches in during the English Civil War) before uniting in "nation, church, peers and people" in the Glorious Revolution.[42] This view of events was substantially challenged: Maitland discovered in 1893 that the early "parliaments" had "no hint of operating as a representative body but resembled instead a meeting of the King's Council, called to meet the king's purposes; it passed no 'legislation', but rather considered petitions or 'bills' as though acting as an ultimate court of justice".[43] Albert Pollard, writing in 1920, also shot through much of Stubbs' ideas on the representative and law-making powers of early English parliaments, pulling the emergence of a semi-independent House of Commons to the 1620s.[44]

Robert Hebert Quick edit

Political history was the usual venue for whig history in Great Britain, but it also appears in other areas. Robert Hebert Quick (1831–1891) was one of the leaders of the Whig school of the history of education, along with G. A. N. Lowndes. In 1898, Quick explained the value of studying the history of educational reform, arguing that the great accomplishments of the past were cumulative and comprised the building blocks that “would raise us to a higher standing-point from which we may see much that will make the right road clearer to us”.[45]

End of whig history edit

Frederic William Maitland is "now universally recognised as the first practitioner of the modern discipline of history", using "medieval law as a tool to prise open the mind of medieval men".[46] Blaas, in Continuity and Anachronism (1978) discerns new methods in the work of J. H. Round, F. W. Maitland and A. F. Pollard; Bentley believes that their work "contained the origins of much twentieth-century [historical] thinking in England".[47] Marwick also positively mentions Gardiner, Seeley, Lord Acton, and T. F. Tout as transforming the teaching and study of history at British universities into a recognisable modern form.[48]

The First World War, however, did substantial damage to whig history's fundamental assumption of progress and improvement:

Accelerated by the sceptical power of a new breed of historian epitomized in the brilliance of F. W. Maitland, whiggery had begun its turn downwards (we are told) and met its Waterloo on the Somme[49] ... [T]win thrusts—on the one hand cultural despair in face of a dead civilization, on the other a determination to make history say something different for the post-war generation—worked between them to put whig susceptibilities between a rock and a hard place.[50]

Bentley also speculates that 19th-century British historiography took the form of an indirect social history which "attempted to embrace society by absorbing it into the history of the state", a project gravely disrupted by the First World War and renewed questions on "the pretensions of the state as an avatar of social harmony".[51] He, however, notes that whig history has not died "outside the academy" and lives on partially in criticism of history as something published in "a row of small-minded monographs written by authors calling themselves 'doctor', whose life-experience and sense of English culture extended no further than taking cups of tea in the Institute of Historical Research".[52]

Later instances and criticism edit

In science edit

It has been argued that the historiography of science is "riddled with Whiggish history".[53][verification needed] Like other whig histories, whig history of science tends to divide historical actors into "good guys" who are on the side of truth (as is now known), and "bad guys" who opposed the emergence of these truths because of ignorance or bias.[54] Science is seen as emerging from "a series of victories over pre-scientific thinking".[25] From this whiggish perspective, Ptolemy would be criticized because his astronomical system placed the Earth at the center of the universe while Aristarchus would be praised because he placed the Sun at the center of the Solar System. This kind of evaluation ignores historical background and the evidence that was available at a particular time: Did Aristarchus have evidence to support his idea that the Sun was at the center? Were there good reasons to reject Ptolemy's system before the sixteenth century?

The writing of Whig history of science is especially found in the writings of scientists[55] and general historians,[56] while this whiggish tendency is commonly opposed by professional historians of science. Nicholas Jardine describes the changing attitude to whiggishness this way:[57]

By the mid-1970s, it had become commonplace among historians of science to employ the terms "Whig" and "Whiggish", often accompanied by one or more of "hagiographic", "internalist", "triumphalist", even "positivist", to denigrate grand narratives of scientific progress. At one level there is, indeed, an obvious parallel with the attacks on Whig constitutional history in the opening decades of the century. For, as P. B. M. Blaas has shown, those earlier attacks were part and parcel of a more general onslaught in the name of an autonomous, professional and scientific history, on popular, partisan and moralising historiography. Similarly, ... For post-WWII champions of the newly professionalized history of science the targets were quite different. Above all, they were out to establish a critical distance between the history of science and the teaching and promotion of the sciences. In particular, they were suspicious of the grand celebratory and didactic narratives of scientific discovery and progress that had proliferated in the inter-war years.

More recently, some scholars have argued that Whig history is essential to the history of science. At one level, "the very term 'the history of science' has itself profoundly Whiggish implications. One may be reasonably clear what 'science' means in the 19th century and most of the 18th century. In the 17th century 'science' has very different meaning. Chemistry, for example, was then inextricably mixed up with alchemy. Before the 17th century dissecting out such a thing as 'science' in anything like the modern sense of the term involves profound distortions."[58] The science historians' rejection of whiggishness has been criticised by some scientists for failing to appreciate "the temporal depth of scientific research".[59]

In economics edit

Retrospectives on modern macroeconomics are generally whiggish histories. For example, the popularisation of mathematical models by Paul Samuelson's Foundations of Economic Analysis, when viewed by economists trained in a mathematical framework becomes "an important milestone on the road to the mathematization of economics" in a story told by the victorious.[60] Yet "those who do not agree that such mathematization is a good thing could argue that the mathematical developments... represent a regression rather than a progression".[61] The introduction of rational expectations similarly carries implicit hindsight bias: people who disagree on the reality of agents making decisions in the manner assumed (e.g. behavioral economics) "would not necessarily rejoice in [rational expectations'] present ascendancy".[61]

Burrow views Marxist history, with its "[supposed] anticipated terminus from which it derives its moral and political point", as "characteristically whig".[25]

In philosophy edit

One very common example of Whig history is the work of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel, to whom is often ascribed a teleological view of history with an inexorable trajectory in the direction of progress.[62]

Marxists have had varied views on Whig history. The traditional inheritance of Hegel, interpreted through the Engels' articulation of historical materialism, implied that history progressed from a "primitive communism", through slave societies, feudal societies, capitalism, and finally to socialism and communism. However, contemporary Marxists, such as Ellen Meiksins Wood, have aggressively challenged those assumptions as deterministic and ahistorical.[63] Walter Benjamin criticized conception of history which assumed a necessarily progressive or teleological course, though he did not employ the term "Whig history". "The danger affects both the content of the [progressive] tradition and its receivers. The same threat hangs over both: that of becoming a tool of the ruling classes. In every era the attempt must be made anew to wrest tradition away from a conformism that is about to overpower it."[64]

In Canadian history edit

Regarding Canada, Allan Greer argues:

The interpretive schemes that dominated Canadian historical writing through the middle decades of the twentieth century were built on the assumption that history had a discernible direction and flow. Canada was moving towards a goal in the nineteenth century; whether this endpoint was the construction of a transcontinental, commercial, and political union, the development of parliamentary government, or the preservation and resurrection of French Canada, it was certainly a Good Thing. Thus the rebels of 1837 were quite literally on the wrong track. They lost because they had to lose; they were not simply overwhelmed by superior force, they were justly chastised by the God of History.[65]

In the emergence of intelligent life edit

In The Anthropic Cosmological Principle (1986), John D. Barrow and Frank J. Tipler identify whiggishness with a teleological principle of convergence in history to liberal democracy. This is in line with what Barrow and Tipler call the "anthropic principle".[66]

In general history and biography edit

James A. Hijiya points out the persistence of whiggish history in history textbooks.[67] In the debate over Britishness, David Marquand praised the whig approach on the grounds that "ordered freedom and evolutionary progress have been among the hallmarks of modern British history, and they should command respect".[68]

Historian Edward J. Larson in his book Summer for the Gods: The Scopes Trial and America's Continuing Debate Over Science and Religion (1997) challenged a whiggish view of the Scopes trial. The book won the Pulitzer Prize for History in 1998.[69]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Blackburn, Simon (1 January 2008). "Whig view of history". The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/acref/9780199541430.001.0001. ISBN 978-0-19-954143-0. Retrieved 1 March 2022.
  2. ^ a b c d Cronon 2012.
  3. ^ a b Burrow 2008, p. 473.
  4. ^ a b c Marwick 2001, p. 74.
  5. ^ a b Bentley 2006, p. 20.
  6. ^ Mayr 1990.
  7. ^ Gardner & Lewis 2015.
  8. ^ Ferguson 1990.
  9. ^ Butterfield, Sir Herbert (1981). The Whig Interpretation of History. University of New South Wales Library. OCLC 218992532.
  10. ^ Torr 2000, p. 52–53.
  11. ^ Sewell 2005.
  12. ^ Bentley 2006, p. 171.
  13. ^ Bentley 2006, p. 95. Bentley however argues against Blaas' conclusion: Blaas' historiography is mostly focused on parliamentary history, which "pre-dates significant changes in whig typologies... sometimes by several decades [as in] the case of imperial historiography"; in contrast to what Blaas' assumes, there was no strong connection between whig historians and the Liberal party; new pre-1914 archival information also is now available.
  14. ^ Butterfield 1965, p. 11.
  15. ^ Butterfield 1965, p. 12.
  16. ^ Butterfield 1965, pp. 24–25.
  17. ^ Butterfield 1965, p. 34.
  18. ^ Hart 1965, p. 39.
  19. ^ Butterfield 1965, p. 35.
  20. ^ Butterfield 1965, p. 37.
  21. ^ Butterfield 1965, p. 41.
  22. ^ Butterfield 1965, p. 65.
  23. ^ Butterfield 1965, pp. 68–69.
  24. ^ Wilson & Ashplant 2009, p. 10.
  25. ^ a b c Burrow 2008, p. 474.
  26. ^ Cannadine 1993, p. 203.
  27. ^ Cannadine 1993, p. 197.
  28. ^ a b Carr 1990, p. 41.
  29. ^ Bentley 2005, p. 65.
  30. ^ Bentley 2005, p. 66.
  31. ^ Bentley 2005, p. 67.
  32. ^ Scruton 2007, p. 735.
  33. ^ Feske 1996, p. 2.
  34. ^ Trevor-Roper 1979, p. 10.
  35. ^ a b Marwick 2001, pp. 74–75.
  36. ^ Trevor-Roper 1979, p. 12.
  37. ^ Trevor-Roper 1979, pp. 25–26.
  38. ^ Macaulay, Thomas Babington (1848). "Chapter I" . The History of England from the Accession of James II . Vol. 1. p. 14 – via Wikisource.
  39. ^ Breisach, E. (2007). Historiography: Ancient, Medieval, and Modern, Third Edition. ACLS Humanities E-Book. University of Chicago Press. p. 251. ISBN 978-0-226-07283-8. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
  40. ^ Bentley 2006, pp. 23 et seq.
  41. ^ Reba N. Soffer (1994). Discipline and Power: The University, History, and the Making of an English Elite, 1870–1930. Stanford University Press. pp. 87–88. ISBN 978-0-8047-2383-1.
  42. ^ Bentley 2006, p. 32.
  43. ^ Bentley 2006, p. 33.
  44. ^ Bentley 2006, p. 37.
  45. ^ McCulloch, Gary (2011). The Struggle for the History of Education. Foundations and Futures of Education. Taylor & Francis. p. 28. ISBN 978-1-136-81124-1. Retrieved 25 April 2021. Indeed, he concluded, 'the great thinkers would raise us to a higher standing-point from which we may see much that will make the right road clearer to us, and lead us to press forward in it with good heart and hope' (Quick 1868/1902, p. 526).
  46. ^ Marwick 2001, p. 77. Quotation marks omitted.
  47. ^ Bentley 2006, p. 96.
  48. ^ Marwick 2001, pp. 77–78. Contra Butterfield, who mentions Acton et al negatively.
  49. ^ Bentley 2006, p. 7.
  50. ^ Bentley 2006, p. 104.
  51. ^ Bentley 2005, p. 71. Bentley speculates that "for men such as Stubbs, the attraction of law and constitutional practice lay in their ability to reflect the lives of thousands of anonymous people and thus provide access to those who could never be reached via direct oral testimony".
  52. ^ Bentley 2006, p. 8.
  53. ^ McIntire, C. T. (2004). Herbert Butterfield: Historian as Dissenter. Yale University Press. p. 205. ISBN 978-0-300-09807-5.
  54. ^ Schuster, John Andrew (1995). "The Problem of 'Whig History' in the History of Science" (PDF). The Scientific Revolution: An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Science. Department of Science & Technology Studies, University of Wollongong. ISBN 978-0-86418-337-8.
  55. ^ Bowler & Morus 2005, p. 2. "The conventional stories of the past that appear in the introductory chapters of science textbooks are certainly a form of Whiggism. Historians take great delight in exposing the artificially constructed nature of these stories, and some scientists find the results uncomfortable".
  56. ^ Alder 2002, p. 301. "The history of science—as composed by both ex-scientists and general historians—has largely consisted of Whig history, in which the scientific winners write the account in such a way as to make their triumph an inevitable outcome of the righteous logic of their cause".
  57. ^ Jardine, Nick (1 June 2003). "Whigs and Stories: Herbert Butterfield and the Historiography of Science". History of Science. 41 (2): 127–128. Bibcode:2003HisSc..41..125J. doi:10.1177/007327530304100201. ISSN 0073-2753. S2CID 160281821.
  58. ^ Hyman, Anthony (1 October 1996). "Whiggism in the History of Science and the Study of the Life and Work of Charles Babbage". The Babbage Pages. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
  59. ^ Harrison, Edward (September 1987). "Whigs, prigs and historians of science". Nature. 329 (6136): 213–214. Bibcode:1987Natur.329..213H. doi:10.1038/329213a0. ISSN 1476-4687. S2CID 4347987.
  60. ^ Torr 2000, pp. 56–57.
  61. ^ a b Torr 2000, p. 57.
  62. ^ Pinkard, Terry (2017). Does History Make Sense?. Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-97880-5.
  63. ^ Wood, Ellen Meiksins (2016). Democracy or Capitalism: Renewing Historical Materialism. United States: Verso Books. pp. 108–181. ISBN 978-1784782443.
  64. ^ Benjamin, Walter (1968). Illuminations (2nd ed.). United States: Mariner Books. pp. 198–199. ISBN 978-1328470232. OCLC 1179424430.
  65. ^ Greer, Allan (6 April 2016). "1837–38: Rebellion Reconsidered". The Canadian Historical Review. 76 (1): 3. ISSN 1710-1093. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
  66. ^ Barrow, John D.; Tipler, Frank J. (1986). The Anthropic Cosmological Principle (1st ed.). Oxford University Press. pp. 9–11, 135. ISBN 978-0-19-282147-8. LCCN 87028148.
  67. ^ Hijiya, James A. (1994). "Why the West Is Lost". The William and Mary Quarterly. 51 (2): 284. doi:10.2307/2946864. ISSN 0043-5597. JSTOR 2946864.
  68. ^ Marquand, David (2009). "'Bursting with Skeletons': Britishness after Empire". In Gamble, Andrew; Wright, Tony (eds.). Britishness: Perspectives on the British Question. John Wiley & Sons. p. 15. ISBN 978-1-4051-9269-9.
  69. ^ Ladouceur, Ronald P. (1 September 2008). "Ella Thea Smith and the Lost History of American High School Biology Textbooks". Journal of the History of Biology. 41 (3): 435–471. doi:10.1007/s10739-007-9139-3. ISSN 1573-0387. PMID 19244720. S2CID 25320197.

Sources edit

  • Bentley, Michael (2005) [1999]. Modern Historiography: An Introduction. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-134-63192-6.
  • Bentley, Michael (2006). Modernizing England's Past: English Historiography in the Age of Modernism, 1870-1970. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-84178-8.
  • Bowler, Peter J; Morus, Iwan Rhys (2005). Making Modern Science: A Historical Survey (1st ed.). University of Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-06861-9. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
  • Burrow, John (2008). A History of Histories. Allen Lane. ISBN 978-0-307-26852-5. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
  • Butterfield, Herbert (1965) [1931]. The Whig Interpretation of History. New York: WW Norton and Company.
  • Cannadine, David (1993). G. M. Trevelyan: A Life in History. W.W. Norton. p. 208. ISBN 978-0-393-03528-5.
  • Carr, Edward Hallett (1990) [1961]. What is history? (2nd ed.). London: Penguin Books. p. 41.
  • Cronon, William (1 September 2012). "Two Cheers for the Whig Interpretation of History". Perspectives on History. American Historical Association. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
  • Ferguson, James (1990). The Anti-Politics Machine: "Development," Depoliticization, and Bureaucratic Power in Lesotho. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 9780521373821.
  • Feske, Victor (1996). From Belloc to Churchill: Private Scholars, Public Culture, and the Crisis of British Liberalism, 1900–1939. University of North Carolina Press. p. 2. ISBN 978-0-8078-4601-8.
  • Gardner, Katy; Lewis, David (2015). Anthropology and development: challenges for the twenty-first century. Pluto Press.
  • Hart, Jenifer (1965). "Nineteenth-Century Social Reform: A Tory Interpretation of History". Past & Present. 31 (31): 39–61. doi:10.1093/past/31.1.39. ISSN 0031-2746. JSTOR 650101. According to its critics, a whig interpretation of history requires human heroes and villains in the story.
  • Kramer, Lloyd; Maza, Sara (2002). A Companion to Western Historical Thought. Wiley Blackwell Companions to World History. Wiley. ISBN 978-0-631-21714-5. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
    • Alder, Ken. "The History of Science, or, an Oxymoronic Theory of Relativistic Objectivity". In Kramer & Maza (2002).
  • Marwick, Arthur (2001). The New Nature of History: Knowledge, Evidence, Language. Lyceum Books. ISBN 978-0-925065-61-2.
  • Mayr, Ernst (1990). "When is Historiography Whiggish?". Journal of the History of Ideas. 51 (2): 301–309. doi:10.2307/2709517. ISSN 0022-5037. JSTOR 2709517.
  • Scruton, Roger (2007). "Palgrave Macmillan Dictionary of Political Thought" (PDF). text-translator.com (3 ed.). Palgrave Macmillan. p. 735.
  • Sewell, Keith C (2005). "Butterfield's Critique of the Whig Interpretation". In Sewell, Keith C (ed.). Herbert Butterfield and the Interpretation of History. Studies in Modern History. London: Palgrave Macmillan. pp. 30–47. doi:10.1057/9780230000933_3. ISBN 978-0-230-00093-3. Retrieved 25 April 2021.
  • Trevor-Roper, Hugh (1979) [1849]. Introduction. The History of England. By Macaulay, Thomas Babington. Penguin Classics. ISBN 978-0140431339.
  • Torr, Christopher (2000). "The whig interpretation of history". South African Journal of Economic and Management Sciences. 3 (1): 52–58. doi:10.4102/sajems.v3i1.2598. hdl:10520/AJA10158812_263.
  • Wilson, Adrian; Ashplant, T. G. (11 February 2009). "Whig History and Present-centred History". The Historical Journal. 31 (1): 10. doi:10.1017/S0018246X00011961. ISSN 1469-5103. S2CID 159748098.

Further reading edit

  • Burrow, J. W. (1981). A Liberal Descent: Victorian historians and the English past. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521240796.
  • Burrow, J. W. (1988). Whigs and Liberals. Oxford: Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0198201397.
  • Burrow, J. W. (2000). The Crisis of Reason: European thought, 1848–1914. New Haven: Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0300083903.
  • Butterfield, Herbert (1931). The Whig Interpretation of History. London: Bell.
  • Mayr, Ernst (1990). "When is Historiography Whiggish?". Journal of the History of Ideas. 51 (2): 301–309. doi:10.2307/2709517. ISSN 0022-5037. JSTOR 2709517.

External links edit

  • Text of The Whig Interpretation of History
  • James A. Hijiya, "Why the West is Lost"
  • 2003 article Catholic Whiggery[permanent dead link]

whig, history, whig, historiography, approach, historiography, that, presents, history, journey, from, oppressive, benighted, past, glorious, present, present, described, generally, with, modern, forms, liberal, democracy, constitutional, monarchy, originally,. Whig history or Whig historiography is an approach to historiography that presents history as a journey from an oppressive and benighted past to a glorious present 1 The present described is generally one with modern forms of liberal democracy and constitutional monarchy it was originally a satirical term for the patriotic grand narratives praising Britain s adoption of constitutional monarchy and the historical development of the Westminster system 2 The term has also been applied widely in historical disciplines outside of British history e g in the history of science to describe any subjection of history to what is essentially a teleological view of the historical process 3 When the term is used in contexts other than British history whig history lowercase is preferred 3 In the British context whig historians emphasize the rise of constitutional government personal freedoms and scientific progress 4 5 The term is often applied generally and pejoratively to histories that present the past as the inexorable march of progress towards enlightenment The term is also used extensively in the history of science to refer to historiography that focuses on the successful chains of theories and experiments that led to present day theories while ignoring failed theories and dead ends 6 Whig history laid the groundwork for modernization theory and the resulting deployment of development aid around the world after World War II which has sometimes been criticized as destructive to its recipients 7 8 page needed Contents 1 Terminology 1 1 The Whig Interpretation of History 1 2 Subsequent views 2 British whig history 2 1 David Hume 2 2 Thomas Babington Macaulay 2 3 William Stubbs 2 4 Robert Hebert Quick 2 5 End of whig history 3 Later instances and criticism 3 1 In science 3 2 In economics 3 3 In philosophy 3 4 In Canadian history 3 5 In the emergence of intelligent life 3 6 In general history and biography 4 See also 5 References 5 1 Sources 6 Further reading 7 External linksTerminology editThe British historian Herbert Butterfield coined the term Whig history in his short but influential book The Whig Interpretation of History 1931 9 It takes its name from the British Whigs advocates of the power of Parliament who opposed the Tories advocates of the power of the king 10 Butterfield s usage of the term was not in relation to the British or American Whig parties or Whiggism but rather took aim at the nineteenth century school of historiography that praised all progress and habitually associated Protestantism with liberal views of liberty 11 The terms whig and whiggish are now used broadly becoming universal descriptors for all progressive narratives 2 When H A L Fisher in 1928 gave a Raleigh lecture he implied that the whig historians really were Whigs i e associated with the Whig party or its Liberal successor and had written centrist histories that were good history despite their enthusiasm for Gladstonian or Liberal Unionist causes on introduction the term was mostly approbatory unlike Butterfield s later use since Fisher applauded Macaulay s instructive and illuminating history 12 By the time Butterfield wrote his Whig Interpretation he may have been beating a dead horse P B M Blaas in his 1978 book Continuity and Anachronism argued that whig history itself had lost all vitality by 1914 13 Subsequent generations of academic historians have rejected Whig history because of its presentist and teleological assumption that history is driving toward some sort of goal The Whig Interpretation of History edit Butterfield s purpose with writing his 1931 book was to criticise oversimplified narratives or abridgements which interpreted past events in terms of the present for the purposes of achieving drama and apparent moral clarity 2 Butterfield especially noted It is part and parcel of the whig interpretation of history that it studies the past with reference to the present 14 Butterfield argued that this approach to history compromised the work of the historian in several ways The emphasis on the inevitability of progress leads to the mistaken belief that the progressive sequence of events becomes a line of causation tempting the historian to go no further to investigate the causes of historical change 15 The focus on the present as the goal of historical change leads the historian to a special kind of abridgement selecting only those events that seem important from the present point of view 16 He also criticised it for modernising the past the result of whig history is that to many of us historical figures seem much more modern than they really were and even when we have corrected this impression by closer study we find it difficult to keep in mind the differences between their world and ours 17 Whig history is also criticised as having an overly dualist view with heroes on the side of liberty and freedom against traditionalist villains opposing the inevitability of progress 18 It also casts an overly negative view of opposing parties to heroes described taking such parties to have contributed nothing to the making of the present and at worst converting them into a dummy that acts as a better foil to the grand whig virtues 19 Butterfield illustrated this by criticising views of Martin Luther and the Reformation which are inclined to write sometimes as though Protestantism in itself was somehow constituted to assist the process of secularisation 20 and misconceptions that the British constitution was created by Whigs opposed by Tories rather than created by compromise and interplay mediated by then political contingencies 21 He also felt that whig history viewed the world in terms of a morality play that the whig historian imagines himself inconclusive unless he can give a verdict and studying Protestant and Catholic in the 16th century he feels that loose threads are still left hanging unless he can show which party was in the right 22 Butterfield instead advances a view of history stressing the accidental and contingent nature of events rather than some kind of inevitable and structural shift 23 Moreover he called upon historians to evoke a certain sensibility towards the past the sensibility which studies the past for the sake of the past which delights in the concrete and the complex which goes out to meet the past which searches for unlikenesses between past and present 24 failed verification A decade later however if under wartime pressure from the Second World War Butterfield would note of the Whig interpretation that whatever it may have done to our history it has had a wonderful effect on our politics In every Englishman there is hidden something of a whig that seems to tug at the heart strings 25 Subsequent views edit Butterfield s formulation has subsequently received much attention and the kind of historical writing he argued against in generalized terms is no longer academically respectable Despite its polemical success Butterfield s celebrated book was criticized by David Cannadine as slight confused repetitive and superficial 26 However of the English tradition more broadly Cannadine wrote It was fiercely partisan and righteously judgemental dividing the personnel of the past into the good and the bad And it did so on the basis of the marked preference for liberal and progressive causes rather than conservative and reactionary ones Whig history was in short an extremely biased view of the past eager to hand out moral judgements and distorted by teleology anachronism and present mindedness 27 E H Carr in What is history 1961 gave the book the backhanded compliment of being a remarkable book in many ways noting that though it denounced the whig interpretation over some 130 pages it did not name a single whig except Fox who was no historian or a single historian save Acton who was no whig 28 2 Michael Bentley analyses Butterfield s whig theory as referring to a canon of 19th century historians in and of England such as William Stubbs James Anthony Froude E A Freeman J R Green W E H Lecky Lord Acton J R Seeley S R Gardiner C H Firth and J B Bury that in fact excludes few except Thomas Carlyle 29 The theory identifies the common factors and Bentley comments Carlyle apart the so called Whigs were predominantly Christian predominantly Anglican thinkers for whom the Reformation supplied the critical theatre of enquiry when considering the origins of modern England When they wrote about the history of the English constitution as so many of them did they approached their story from the standpoint of having Good News to relate 30 If they could not have found the grandeur that they developed had they been writing half a century earlier neither could they have supported their optimism had they lived to endure the barbarisms of the Somme and Passchendaele 31 Roger Scruton takes the theory underlying whig history to be centrally concerned with social progress and reaction with the progressives shown as victors and benefactors 32 According to Victor Feske there is too much readiness to accept Butterfield s classic formulation from 1931 as definitive 33 British whig history editIn Britain whig history is a view of British history that sees it as a steady evolution of British parliamentary institutions benevolently watched over by Whig aristocrats and steadily spreading social progress and prosperity 4 It described a continuity of institutions and practices since Anglo Saxon times that lent to English history a special pedigree one that instilled a distinctive temper in the English nation as whigs liked to call it and an approach to the world which issued in law and lent legal precedent a role in preserving or extending the freedoms of Englishmen 5 Paul Rapin de Thoyras s history of England published in 1723 became the classic Whig history for the first half of the eighteenth century 34 verification needed Rapin claimed that the English had preserved their ancient constitution against the absolutist tendencies of the Stuarts However Rapin s history lost its place as the standard history of England in the late 18th century and early 19th century to that of David Hume citation needed William Blackstone s Commentaries on the Laws of England 1765 1769 reveals many Whiggish traits citation needed According to Arthur Marwick however Henry Hallam was the first whig historian publishing Constitutional History of England in 1827 which greatly exaggerated the importance of parliaments or of bodies whig historians thought were parliaments while tending to interpret all political struggles in terms of the parliamentary situation in Britain during the nineteenth century in terms that is of Whig reformers fighting the good fight against Tory defenders of the status quo 35 David Hume edit In The History of England 1754 1761 Hume challenged whig views of the past and the whig historians in turn attacked Hume but they could not dent his history In the early 19th century some whig historians came to incorporate Hume s views dominant for the previous fifty years These historians were members of the New Whigs around Charles James Fox 1749 1806 and Lord Holland 1773 1840 in opposition until 1830 and so needed a new historical philosophy 36 Fox himself intended to write a history of the Glorious Revolution of 1688 but only managed the first year of James II s reign A fragment was published in 1808 James Mackintosh then sought to write a Whig history of the Glorious Revolution published in 1834 as the History of the Revolution in England in 1688 Thomas Babington Macaulay edit Hume still dominated English historiography but this changed when Thomas Babington Macaulay entered the field utilising Fox and Mackintosh s work and manuscript collections Macaulay s History of England was published in a series of volumes from 1848 to 1855 35 It proved an immediate success replacing Hume s history and becoming the new orthodoxy 37 As if to introduce a linear progressive view of history the first chapter of Macaulay s History of England proposes The history of our country during the last hundred and sixty years is eminently the history of physical of moral and of intellectual improvement 38 4 While Macaulay was a popular and celebrated historian of the whig school his work did not feature in Butterfield s 1931 Whig Interpretation of History 28 According to Ernst Breisach his style captivated the public as did his good sense of the past and firm whiggish convictions 39 William Stubbs edit William Stubbs 1825 1901 the constitutional historian and influential teacher of a generation of historians was the author of the extremely influential Constitutional History of England published between 1873 78 40 and became a crucial figure in the later survival and respectability of whig history According to Reba Soffer Stubbs was a true believer who concealed his biases even from himself behind the facade of a dispassionate historian translating original documents into magisterial prose His rhetorical gifts often obscured his combination of high church Anglicanism whig history and civic responsibility In the Church of England Stubbs saw the original model for the development and maintenance of English liberties 41 Stubb s history began with an imagined Anglo Saxon past into which representative parliamentary institutions emerged and fought for control with the absolutist crown in various stages including overreaches in during the English Civil War before uniting in nation church peers and people in the Glorious Revolution 42 This view of events was substantially challenged Maitland discovered in 1893 that the early parliaments had no hint of operating as a representative body but resembled instead a meeting of the King s Council called to meet the king s purposes it passed no legislation but rather considered petitions or bills as though acting as an ultimate court of justice 43 Albert Pollard writing in 1920 also shot through much of Stubbs ideas on the representative and law making powers of early English parliaments pulling the emergence of a semi independent House of Commons to the 1620s 44 Robert Hebert Quick edit Political history was the usual venue for whig history in Great Britain but it also appears in other areas Robert Hebert Quick 1831 1891 was one of the leaders of the Whig school of the history of education along with G A N Lowndes In 1898 Quick explained the value of studying the history of educational reform arguing that the great accomplishments of the past were cumulative and comprised the building blocks that would raise us to a higher standing point from which we may see much that will make the right road clearer to us 45 End of whig history edit Frederic William Maitland is now universally recognised as the first practitioner of the modern discipline of history using medieval law as a tool to prise open the mind of medieval men 46 Blaas in Continuity and Anachronism 1978 discerns new methods in the work of J H Round F W Maitland and A F Pollard Bentley believes that their work contained the origins of much twentieth century historical thinking in England 47 Marwick also positively mentions Gardiner Seeley Lord Acton and T F Tout as transforming the teaching and study of history at British universities into a recognisable modern form 48 The First World War however did substantial damage to whig history s fundamental assumption of progress and improvement Accelerated by the sceptical power of a new breed of historian epitomized in the brilliance of F W Maitland whiggery had begun its turn downwards we are told and met its Waterloo on the Somme 49 T win thrusts on the one hand cultural despair in face of a dead civilization on the other a determination to make history say something different for the post war generation worked between them to put whig susceptibilities between a rock and a hard place 50 Bentley also speculates that 19th century British historiography took the form of an indirect social history which attempted to embrace society by absorbing it into the history of the state a project gravely disrupted by the First World War and renewed questions on the pretensions of the state as an avatar of social harmony 51 He however notes that whig history has not died outside the academy and lives on partially in criticism of history as something published in a row of small minded monographs written by authors calling themselves doctor whose life experience and sense of English culture extended no further than taking cups of tea in the Institute of Historical Research 52 Later instances and criticism editIn science edit It has been argued that the historiography of science is riddled with Whiggish history 53 verification needed Like other whig histories whig history of science tends to divide historical actors into good guys who are on the side of truth as is now known and bad guys who opposed the emergence of these truths because of ignorance or bias 54 Science is seen as emerging from a series of victories over pre scientific thinking 25 From this whiggish perspective Ptolemy would be criticized because his astronomical system placed the Earth at the center of the universe while Aristarchus would be praised because he placed the Sun at the center of the Solar System This kind of evaluation ignores historical background and the evidence that was available at a particular time Did Aristarchus have evidence to support his idea that the Sun was at the center Were there good reasons to reject Ptolemy s system before the sixteenth century The writing of Whig history of science is especially found in the writings of scientists 55 and general historians 56 while this whiggish tendency is commonly opposed by professional historians of science Nicholas Jardine describes the changing attitude to whiggishness this way 57 By the mid 1970s it had become commonplace among historians of science to employ the terms Whig and Whiggish often accompanied by one or more of hagiographic internalist triumphalist even positivist to denigrate grand narratives of scientific progress At one level there is indeed an obvious parallel with the attacks on Whig constitutional history in the opening decades of the century For as P B M Blaas has shown those earlier attacks were part and parcel of a more general onslaught in the name of an autonomous professional and scientific history on popular partisan and moralising historiography Similarly For post WWII champions of the newly professionalized history of science the targets were quite different Above all they were out to establish a critical distance between the history of science and the teaching and promotion of the sciences In particular they were suspicious of the grand celebratory and didactic narratives of scientific discovery and progress that had proliferated in the inter war years More recently some scholars have argued that Whig history is essential to the history of science At one level the very term the history of science has itself profoundly Whiggish implications One may be reasonably clear what science means in the 19th century and most of the 18th century In the 17th century science has very different meaning Chemistry for example was then inextricably mixed up with alchemy Before the 17th century dissecting out such a thing as science in anything like the modern sense of the term involves profound distortions 58 The science historians rejection of whiggishness has been criticised by some scientists for failing to appreciate the temporal depth of scientific research 59 In economics edit Retrospectives on modern macroeconomics are generally whiggish histories For example the popularisation of mathematical models by Paul Samuelson s Foundations of Economic Analysis when viewed by economists trained in a mathematical framework becomes an important milestone on the road to the mathematization of economics in a story told by the victorious 60 Yet those who do not agree that such mathematization is a good thing could argue that the mathematical developments represent a regression rather than a progression 61 The introduction of rational expectations similarly carries implicit hindsight bias people who disagree on the reality of agents making decisions in the manner assumed e g behavioral economics would not necessarily rejoice in rational expectations present ascendancy 61 Burrow views Marxist history with its supposed anticipated terminus from which it derives its moral and political point as characteristically whig 25 In philosophy edit One very common example of Whig history is the work of Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel to whom is often ascribed a teleological view of history with an inexorable trajectory in the direction of progress 62 Marxists have had varied views on Whig history The traditional inheritance of Hegel interpreted through the Engels articulation of historical materialism implied that history progressed from a primitive communism through slave societies feudal societies capitalism and finally to socialism and communism However contemporary Marxists such as Ellen Meiksins Wood have aggressively challenged those assumptions as deterministic and ahistorical 63 Walter Benjamin criticized conception of history which assumed a necessarily progressive or teleological course though he did not employ the term Whig history The danger affects both the content of the progressive tradition and its receivers The same threat hangs over both that of becoming a tool of the ruling classes In every era the attempt must be made anew to wrest tradition away from a conformism that is about to overpower it 64 In Canadian history edit Regarding Canada Allan Greer argues The interpretive schemes that dominated Canadian historical writing through the middle decades of the twentieth century were built on the assumption that history had a discernible direction and flow Canada was moving towards a goal in the nineteenth century whether this endpoint was the construction of a transcontinental commercial and political union the development of parliamentary government or the preservation and resurrection of French Canada it was certainly a Good Thing Thus the rebels of 1837 were quite literally on the wrong track They lost because they had to lose they were not simply overwhelmed by superior force they were justly chastised by the God of History 65 In the emergence of intelligent life edit In The Anthropic Cosmological Principle 1986 John D Barrow and Frank J Tipler identify whiggishness with a teleological principle of convergence in history to liberal democracy This is in line with what Barrow and Tipler call the anthropic principle 66 In general history and biography edit James A Hijiya points out the persistence of whiggish history in history textbooks 67 In the debate over Britishness David Marquand praised the whig approach on the grounds that ordered freedom and evolutionary progress have been among the hallmarks of modern British history and they should command respect 68 Historian Edward J Larson in his book Summer for the Gods The Scopes Trial and America s Continuing Debate Over Science and Religion 1997 challenged a whiggish view of the Scopes trial The book won the Pulitzer Prize for History in 1998 69 See also editChronological snobbery Classical liberalism Ethnocentrism Great man theory Meliorism Moral progress Philosophic Whigs Precursorism Predestination The End of History and the Last Man The Better Angels of Our Nature The Moral ArcReferences edit Blackburn Simon 1 January 2008 Whig view of history The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 acref 9780199541430 001 0001 ISBN 978 0 19 954143 0 Retrieved 1 March 2022 a b c d Cronon 2012 a b Burrow 2008 p 473 a b c Marwick 2001 p 74 a b Bentley 2006 p 20 Mayr 1990 Gardner amp Lewis 2015 Ferguson 1990 Butterfield Sir Herbert 1981 The Whig Interpretation of History University of New South Wales Library OCLC 218992532 Torr 2000 p 52 53 Sewell 2005 Bentley 2006 p 171 Bentley 2006 p 95 Bentley however argues against Blaas conclusion Blaas historiography is mostly focused on parliamentary history which pre dates significant changes in whig typologies sometimes by several decades as in the case of imperial historiography in contrast to what Blaas assumes there was no strong connection between whig historians and the Liberal party new pre 1914 archival information also is now available Butterfield 1965 p 11 Butterfield 1965 p 12 Butterfield 1965 pp 24 25 Butterfield 1965 p 34 Hart 1965 p 39 Butterfield 1965 p 35 Butterfield 1965 p 37 Butterfield 1965 p 41 Butterfield 1965 p 65 Butterfield 1965 pp 68 69 Wilson amp Ashplant 2009 p 10 a b c Burrow 2008 p 474 Cannadine 1993 p 203 Cannadine 1993 p 197 a b Carr 1990 p 41 Bentley 2005 p 65 Bentley 2005 p 66 Bentley 2005 p 67 Scruton 2007 p 735 Feske 1996 p 2 Trevor Roper 1979 p 10 a b Marwick 2001 pp 74 75 Trevor Roper 1979 p 12 Trevor Roper 1979 pp 25 26 Macaulay Thomas Babington 1848 Chapter I The History of England from the Accession of James II Vol 1 p 14 via Wikisource Breisach E 2007 Historiography Ancient Medieval and Modern Third Edition ACLS Humanities E Book University of Chicago Press p 251 ISBN 978 0 226 07283 8 Retrieved 25 April 2021 Bentley 2006 pp 23 et seq Reba N Soffer 1994 Discipline and Power The University History and the Making of an English Elite 1870 1930 Stanford University Press pp 87 88 ISBN 978 0 8047 2383 1 Bentley 2006 p 32 Bentley 2006 p 33 Bentley 2006 p 37 McCulloch Gary 2011 The Struggle for the History of Education Foundations and Futures of Education Taylor amp Francis p 28 ISBN 978 1 136 81124 1 Retrieved 25 April 2021 Indeed he concluded the great thinkers would raise us to a higher standing point from which we may see much that will make the right road clearer to us and lead us to press forward in it with good heart and hope Quick 1868 1902 p 526 Marwick 2001 p 77 Quotation marks omitted Bentley 2006 p 96 Marwick 2001 pp 77 78 Contra Butterfield who mentions Acton et al negatively Bentley 2006 p 7 Bentley 2006 p 104 Bentley 2005 p 71 Bentley speculates that for men such as Stubbs the attraction of law and constitutional practice lay in their ability to reflect the lives of thousands of anonymous people and thus provide access to those who could never be reached via direct oral testimony Bentley 2006 p 8 McIntire C T 2004 Herbert Butterfield Historian as Dissenter Yale University Press p 205 ISBN 978 0 300 09807 5 Schuster John Andrew 1995 The Problem of Whig History in the History of Science PDF The Scientific Revolution An Introduction to the History and Philosophy of Science Department of Science amp Technology Studies University of Wollongong ISBN 978 0 86418 337 8 Bowler amp Morus 2005 p 2 The conventional stories of the past that appear in the introductory chapters of science textbooks are certainly a form of Whiggism Historians take great delight in exposing the artificially constructed nature of these stories and some scientists find the results uncomfortable Alder 2002 p 301 The history of science as composed by both ex scientists and general historians has largely consisted of Whig history in which the scientific winners write the account in such a way as to make their triumph an inevitable outcome of the righteous logic of their cause Jardine Nick 1 June 2003 Whigs and Stories Herbert Butterfield and the Historiography of Science History of Science 41 2 127 128 Bibcode 2003HisSc 41 125J doi 10 1177 007327530304100201 ISSN 0073 2753 S2CID 160281821 Hyman Anthony 1 October 1996 Whiggism in the History of Science and the Study of the Life and Work of Charles Babbage The Babbage Pages Retrieved 25 April 2021 Harrison Edward September 1987 Whigs prigs and historians of science Nature 329 6136 213 214 Bibcode 1987Natur 329 213H doi 10 1038 329213a0 ISSN 1476 4687 S2CID 4347987 Torr 2000 pp 56 57 a b Torr 2000 p 57 Pinkard Terry 2017 Does History Make Sense Harvard University Press ISBN 978 0 674 97880 5 Wood Ellen Meiksins 2016 Democracy or Capitalism Renewing Historical Materialism United States Verso Books pp 108 181 ISBN 978 1784782443 Benjamin Walter 1968 Illuminations 2nd ed United States Mariner Books pp 198 199 ISBN 978 1328470232 OCLC 1179424430 Greer Allan 6 April 2016 1837 38 Rebellion Reconsidered The Canadian Historical Review 76 1 3 ISSN 1710 1093 Retrieved 25 April 2021 Barrow John D Tipler Frank J 1986 The Anthropic Cosmological Principle 1st ed Oxford University Press pp 9 11 135 ISBN 978 0 19 282147 8 LCCN 87028148 Hijiya James A 1994 Why the West Is Lost The William and Mary Quarterly 51 2 284 doi 10 2307 2946864 ISSN 0043 5597 JSTOR 2946864 Marquand David 2009 Bursting with Skeletons Britishness after Empire In Gamble Andrew Wright Tony eds Britishness Perspectives on the British Question John Wiley amp Sons p 15 ISBN 978 1 4051 9269 9 Ladouceur Ronald P 1 September 2008 Ella Thea Smith and the Lost History of American High School Biology Textbooks Journal of the History of Biology 41 3 435 471 doi 10 1007 s10739 007 9139 3 ISSN 1573 0387 PMID 19244720 S2CID 25320197 Sources edit Bentley Michael 2005 1999 Modern Historiography An Introduction Routledge ISBN 978 1 134 63192 6 Bentley Michael 2006 Modernizing England s Past English Historiography in the Age of Modernism 1870 1970 Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 84178 8 Bowler Peter J Morus Iwan Rhys 2005 Making Modern Science A Historical Survey 1st ed University of Chicago Press ISBN 978 0 226 06861 9 Retrieved 25 April 2021 Burrow John 2008 A History of Histories Allen Lane ISBN 978 0 307 26852 5 Retrieved 25 April 2021 Butterfield Herbert 1965 1931 The Whig Interpretation of History New York WW Norton and Company Cannadine David 1993 G M Trevelyan A Life in History W W Norton p 208 ISBN 978 0 393 03528 5 Carr Edward Hallett 1990 1961 What is history 2nd ed London Penguin Books p 41 Cronon William 1 September 2012 Two Cheers for the Whig Interpretation of History Perspectives on History American Historical Association Retrieved 25 April 2021 Ferguson James 1990 The Anti Politics Machine Development Depoliticization and Bureaucratic Power in Lesotho Cambridge University Press ISBN 9780521373821 Feske Victor 1996 From Belloc to Churchill Private Scholars Public Culture and the Crisis of British Liberalism 1900 1939 University of North Carolina Press p 2 ISBN 978 0 8078 4601 8 Gardner Katy Lewis David 2015 Anthropology and development challenges for the twenty first century Pluto Press Hart Jenifer 1965 Nineteenth Century Social Reform A Tory Interpretation of History Past amp Present 31 31 39 61 doi 10 1093 past 31 1 39 ISSN 0031 2746 JSTOR 650101 According to its critics a whig interpretation of history requires human heroes and villains in the story Kramer Lloyd Maza Sara 2002 A Companion to Western Historical Thought Wiley Blackwell Companions to World History Wiley ISBN 978 0 631 21714 5 Retrieved 25 April 2021 Alder Ken The History of Science or an Oxymoronic Theory of Relativistic Objectivity In Kramer amp Maza 2002 Marwick Arthur 2001 The New Nature of History Knowledge Evidence Language Lyceum Books ISBN 978 0 925065 61 2 Mayr Ernst 1990 When is Historiography Whiggish Journal of the History of Ideas 51 2 301 309 doi 10 2307 2709517 ISSN 0022 5037 JSTOR 2709517 Scruton Roger 2007 Palgrave Macmillan Dictionary of Political Thought PDF text translator com 3 ed Palgrave Macmillan p 735 Sewell Keith C 2005 Butterfield s Critique of the Whig Interpretation In Sewell Keith C ed Herbert Butterfield and the Interpretation of History Studies in Modern History London Palgrave Macmillan pp 30 47 doi 10 1057 9780230000933 3 ISBN 978 0 230 00093 3 Retrieved 25 April 2021 Trevor Roper Hugh 1979 1849 Introduction The History of England By Macaulay Thomas Babington Penguin Classics ISBN 978 0140431339 Torr Christopher 2000 The whig interpretation of history South African Journal of Economic and Management Sciences 3 1 52 58 doi 10 4102 sajems v3i1 2598 hdl 10520 AJA10158812 263 Wilson Adrian Ashplant T G 11 February 2009 Whig History and Present centred History The Historical Journal 31 1 10 doi 10 1017 S0018246X00011961 ISSN 1469 5103 S2CID 159748098 Further reading editBurrow J W 1981 A Liberal Descent Victorian historians and the English past Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0521240796 Burrow J W 1988 Whigs and Liberals Oxford Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0198201397 Burrow J W 2000 The Crisis of Reason European thought 1848 1914 New Haven Yale University Press ISBN 978 0300083903 Butterfield Herbert 1931 The Whig Interpretation of History London Bell Mayr Ernst 1990 When is Historiography Whiggish Journal of the History of Ideas 51 2 301 309 doi 10 2307 2709517 ISSN 0022 5037 JSTOR 2709517 External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Whig history Text of The Whig Interpretation of History James A Hijiya Why the West is Lost 2003 article Catholic Whiggery permanent dead link Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Whig history amp oldid 1181818552, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.