fbpx
Wikipedia

Argument (linguistics)

In linguistics, an argument is an expression that helps complete the meaning of a predicate,[1] the latter referring in this context to a main verb and its auxiliaries. In this regard, the complement is a closely related concept. Most predicates take one, two, or three arguments. A predicate and its arguments form a predicate-argument structure. The discussion of predicates and arguments is associated most with (content) verbs and noun phrases (NPs), although other syntactic categories can also be construed as predicates and as arguments. Arguments must be distinguished from adjuncts. While a predicate needs its arguments to complete its meaning, the adjuncts that appear with a predicate are optional; they are not necessary to complete the meaning of the predicate.[2] Most theories of syntax and semantics acknowledge arguments and adjuncts, although the terminology varies, and the distinction is generally believed to exist in all languages. Dependency grammars sometimes call arguments actants, following Lucien Tesnière (1959).

The area of grammar that explores the nature of predicates, their arguments, and adjuncts is called valency theory. Predicates have a valence; they determine the number and type of arguments that can or must appear in their environment. The valence of predicates is also investigated in terms of subcategorization.

Arguments and adjuncts edit

The basic analysis of the syntax and semantics of clauses relies heavily on the distinction between arguments and adjuncts. The clause predicate, which is often a content verb, demands certain arguments. That is, the arguments are necessary in order to complete the meaning of the verb. The adjuncts that appear, in contrast, are not necessary in this sense. The subject phrase and object phrase are the two most frequently occurring arguments of verbal predicates.[3] For instance:

Jill likes Jack.
Sam fried the meat.
The old man helped the young man.

Each of these sentences contains two arguments (in bold), the first noun (phrase) being the subject argument, and the second the object argument. Jill, for example, is the subject argument of the predicate likes, and Jack is its object argument. Verbal predicates that demand just a subject argument (e.g. sleep, work, relax) are intransitive, verbal predicates that demand an object argument as well (e.g. like, fry, help) are transitive, and verbal predicates that demand two object arguments are ditransitive (e.g. give, lend).

When additional information is added to our three example sentences, one is dealing with adjuncts, e.g.

Jill really likes Jack.
Jill likes Jack most of the time.
Jill likes Jack when the sun shines.
Jill likes Jack because he's friendly.

The added phrases (in bold) are adjuncts; they provide additional information that is not necessary to complete the meaning of the predicate likes. One key difference between arguments and adjuncts is that the appearance of a given argument is often obligatory, whereas adjuncts appear optionally. While typical verb arguments are subject or object nouns or noun phrases as in the examples above, they can also be prepositional phrases (PPs) (or even other categories). The PPs in bold in the following sentences are arguments:

Sam put the pen on the chair.
Larry does not put up with that.
Bill is getting on my case.

We know that these PPs are (or contain) arguments because when we attempt to omit them, the result is unacceptable:

*Sam put the pen.
*Larry does not put up.
*Bill is getting.

Subject and object arguments are known as core arguments; core arguments can be suppressed, added, or exchanged in different ways, using voice operations like passivization, antipassivization, applicativization, incorporation, etc. Prepositional arguments, which are also called oblique arguments, however, do not tend to undergo the same processes.

Psycholinguistic (argument vs adjuncts) edit

Psycholinguistic theories must explain how syntactic representations are built incrementally during sentence comprehension. One view that has sprung from psycholinguistics is the argument structure hypothesis (ASH), which explains the distinct cognitive operations for argument and adjunct attachment: arguments are attached via the lexical mechanism, but adjuncts are attached using general (non-lexical) grammatical knowledge that is represented as phrase structure rules or the equivalent.

Argument status determines the cognitive mechanism in which a phrase will be attached to the developing syntactic representations of a sentence. Psycholinguistic evidence supports a formal distinction between arguments and adjuncts, for any questions about the argument status of a phrase are, in effect, questions about learned mental representations of the lexical heads.[citation needed]

Syntactic vs. semantic arguments edit

An important distinction acknowledges both syntactic and semantic arguments. Content verbs determine the number and type of syntactic arguments that can or must appear in their environment; they impose specific syntactic functions (e.g. subject, object, oblique, specific preposition, possessor, etc.) onto their arguments. These syntactic functions will vary as the form of the predicate varies (e.g. active verb, passive participle, gerund, nominal, etc.). In languages that have morphological case, the arguments of a predicate must appear with the correct case markings (e.g. nominative, accusative, dative, genitive, etc.) imposed on them by their predicate. The semantic arguments of the predicate, in contrast, remain consistent, e.g.

Jack is liked by Jill.
Jill's liking Jack
Jack's being liked by Jill
the liking of Jack by Jill
Jill's like for Jack

The predicate 'like' appears in various forms in these examples, which means that the syntactic functions of the arguments associated with Jack and Jill vary. The object of the active sentence, for instance, becomes the subject of the passive sentence. Despite this variation in syntactic functions, the arguments remain semantically consistent. In each case, Jill is the experiencer (= the one doing the liking) and Jack is the one being experienced (= the one being liked). In other words, the syntactic arguments are subject to syntactic variation in terms of syntactic functions, whereas the thematic roles of the arguments of the given predicate remain consistent as the form of that predicate changes.

The syntactic arguments of a given verb can also vary across languages. For example, the verb put in English requires three syntactic arguments: subject, object, locative (e. g. He put the book into the box). These syntactic arguments correspond to the three semantic arguments agent, theme, and goal. The Japanese verb oku 'put', in contrast, has the same three semantic arguments, but the syntactic arguments differ, since Japanese does not require three syntactic arguments, so it is correct to say Kare ga hon o oita ("He put the book"). The equivalent sentence in English is ungrammatical without the required locative argument, as the examples involving put above demonstrate. For this reason, a slight paraphrase is required to render the nearest grammatical equivalent in English: He positioned the book or He deposited the book.

Distinguishing between arguments and adjuncts edit

Arguments vs. adjuncts edit

A large body of literature has been devoted to distinguishing arguments from adjuncts.[4] Numerous syntactic tests have been devised for this purpose. One such test is the relative clause diagnostic. If the test constituent can appear after the combination which occurred/happened in a relative clause, it is an adjunct, not an argument, e.g.

Bill left on Tuesday. → Bill left, which happened on Tuesday. – on Tuesday is an adjunct.
Susan stopped due to the weather. → Susan stopped, which occurred due to the weather. – due to the weather is an adjunct.
Fred tried to say something twice. → Fred tried to say something, which occurred twice. – twice is an adjunct.

The same diagnostic results in unacceptable relative clauses (and sentences) when the test constituent is an argument, e.g.

Bill left home. → *Bill left, which happened home. – home is an argument.
Susan stopped her objections. → *Susan stopped, which occurred her objections. – her objections is an argument.
Fred tried to say something. → *Fred tried to say, which happened something. – something is an argument.

This test succeeds in identifying prepositional arguments as well:

We are waiting for Susan. → *We are waiting, which is happening for Susan. – for Susan is an argument.
Tom put the knife in the drawer. → *Tom put the knife, which occurred in the drawer. – in the drawer is an argument.
We laughed at you. → *We laughed, which occurred at you. – at you is an argument.

The utility of the relative clause test is, however, limited. It incorrectly suggests, for instance, that modal adverbs (e.g. probably, certainly, maybe) and manner expressions (e.g. quickly, carefully, totally) are arguments. If a constituent passes the relative clause test, however, one can be sure that it is not an argument.

Obligatory vs. optional arguments edit

A further division blurs the line between arguments and adjuncts. Many arguments behave like adjuncts with respect to another diagnostic, the omission diagnostic. Adjuncts can always be omitted from the phrase, clause, or sentence in which they appear without rendering the resulting expression unacceptable. Some arguments (obligatory ones), in contrast, cannot be omitted. There are many other arguments, however, that are identified as arguments by the relative clause diagnostic but that can nevertheless be omitted, e.g.

a. She cleaned the kitchen.
b. She cleaned. – the kitchen is an optional argument.
a. We are waiting for Larry.
b. We are waiting. – for Larry is an optional argument.
a. Susan was working on the model.
b. Susan was working. – on the model is an optional argument.

The relative clause diagnostic would identify the constituents in bold as arguments. The omission diagnostic here, however, demonstrates that they are not obligatory arguments. They are, rather, optional. The insight, then, is that a three-way division is needed. On the one hand, one distinguishes between arguments and adjuncts, and on the other hand, one allows for a further division between obligatory and optional arguments.

Arguments and adjuncts in noun phrases edit

Most work on the distinction between arguments and adjuncts has been conducted at the clause level and has focused on arguments and adjuncts to verbal predicates. The distinction is crucial for the analysis of noun phrases as well, however. If it is altered somewhat, the relative clause diagnostic can also be used to distinguish arguments from adjuncts in noun phrases, e.g.

Bill's bold reading of the poem after lunch
*bold reading of the poem after lunch that was Bill'sBill's is an argument.
Bill's reading of the poem after lunch that was boldbold is an adjunct
*Bill's bold reading after lunch that was of the poemof the poem is an argument
Bill's bold reading of the poem that was after lunchafter lunch is an adjunct

The diagnostic identifies Bill's and of the poem as arguments, and bold and after lunch as adjuncts.

Representing arguments and adjuncts edit

The distinction between arguments and adjuncts is often indicated in the tree structures used to represent syntactic structure. In phrase structure grammars, an adjunct is "adjoined" to a projection of its head predicate in such a manner that distinguishes it from the arguments of that predicate. The distinction is quite visible in theories that employ the X-bar schema, e.g.

 

The complement argument appears as a sister of the head X, and the specifier argument appears as a daughter of XP. The optional adjuncts appear in one of a number of positions adjoined to a bar-projection of X or to XP.

Theories of syntax that acknowledge n-ary branching structures and hence construe syntactic structure as being flatter than the layered structures associated with the X-bar schema must employ some other means to distinguish between arguments and adjuncts. In this regard, some dependency grammars employ an arrow convention. Arguments receive a "normal" dependency edge, whereas adjuncts receive an arrow edge.[5] In the following tree, an arrow points away from an adjunct toward the governor of that adjunct:

 

The arrow edges in the tree identify four constituents (= complete subtrees) as adjuncts: At one time, actually, in congress, and for fun. The normal dependency edges (= non-arrows) identify the other constituents as arguments of their heads. Thus Sam, a duck, and to his representative in congress are identified as arguments of the verbal predicate wanted to send.

Relevant theories edit

Argumentation theory focuses on how logical reasoning leads to end results through an internal structure built of premises, a method of reasoning and a conclusion. There are many versions of argumentation that relate to this theory that include: conversational, mathematical, scientific, interpretive, legal, and political.

Grammar theory, specifically functional theories of grammar, relate to the functions of language as the link to fully understanding linguistics by referencing grammar elements to their functions and purposes.

A variety of theories exist regarding the structure of syntax, including generative grammar, categorial grammar, and dependency grammar.

Modern theories of semantics include formal semantics, lexical semantics, and computational semantics. Formal semantics focuses on truth conditioning. Lexical Semantics delves into word meanings in relation to their context and computational semantics uses algorithms and architectures to investigate linguistic meanings.

The concept of valence is the number and type of arguments that are linked to a predicate, in particular to a verb. In valence theory verbs' arguments include also the argument expressed by the subject of the verb.

History of argument linguistics edit

The notion of argument structure was first conceived in the 1980s by researchers working in the government–binding framework to help address controversies about arguments.[6]

Importance edit

The distinction between arguments and adjuncts is crucial to most theories of syntax and grammar. Arguments behave differently from adjuncts in numerous ways. Theories of binding, coordination, discontinuities, ellipsis, etc. must acknowledge and build on the distinction. When one examines these areas of syntax, what one finds is that arguments consistently behave differently from adjuncts and that without the distinction, our ability to investigate and understand these phenomena would be seriously hindered. There is a distinction between arguments and adjuncts which is not really noticed by many in everyday language. The difference is between obligatory phrases versus phrases which embellish a sentence. For instance, if someone says "Tim punched the stuffed animal", the phrase stuffed animal would be an argument because it is the main part of the sentence. If someone says, "Tim punched the stuffed animal with glee", the phrase with glee would be an adjunct because it just enhances the sentence and the sentence can stand alone without it.[7]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Most grammars define the argument in this manner, i.e. it is an expression that helps complete the meaning of a predicate (a verb). See for instance Tesnière (1969: 128).
  2. ^ Concerning the completion of a predicates meaning via its arguments, see for instance Kroeger (2004:9ff.).
  3. ^ Geeraerts, Dirk; Cuyckens, Hubert (2007). The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Linguistics. Oxford University Press US. ISBN 978-0-19-514378-2.
  4. ^ For instance, see the essays on valency theory in Ágel et al. (2003/6).
  5. ^ See Eroms (2000) and Osborne and Groß (2012) in this regard.
  6. ^ Levin, Beth (2013-05-28). "Argument Structure". Linguistics. doi:10.1093/obo/9780199772810-0099. ISBN 978-0-19-977281-0. Retrieved 2019-03-05.
  7. ^ Damon Tutunjian; Julie E. Boland. "Do we need a distinction between arguments and adjuncts? Evidence from psycholinguistic studies of comprehension" (PDF). University of Michigan.

References edit

  • Ágel, V., L. Eichinger, H.-W. Eroms, P. Hellwig, H. Heringer, and H. Lobin (eds.) 2003/6. Dependency and valency: An international handbook of contemporary research. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
  • Eroms, H.-W. 2000. Syntax der deutschen Sprache. Berlin: de Gruyter.
  • Kroeger, P. 2004. Analyzing syntax: A lexical-functional approach. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.
  • Osborne, T. and T. Groß 2012. Constructions are catenae: Construction Grammar meets dependency grammar. Cognitive Linguistics 23, 1, 163–214.
  • Tesnière, L. 1959. Éléments de syntaxe structurale. Paris: Klincksieck.
  • Tesnière, L. 1969. Éléments de syntaxe structurale. 2nd edition. Paris: Klincksieck.

argument, linguistics, linguistics, argument, expression, that, helps, complete, meaning, predicate, latter, referring, this, context, main, verb, auxiliaries, this, regard, complement, closely, related, concept, most, predicates, take, three, arguments, predi. In linguistics an argument is an expression that helps complete the meaning of a predicate 1 the latter referring in this context to a main verb and its auxiliaries In this regard the complement is a closely related concept Most predicates take one two or three arguments A predicate and its arguments form a predicate argument structure The discussion of predicates and arguments is associated most with content verbs and noun phrases NPs although other syntactic categories can also be construed as predicates and as arguments Arguments must be distinguished from adjuncts While a predicate needs its arguments to complete its meaning the adjuncts that appear with a predicate are optional they are not necessary to complete the meaning of the predicate 2 Most theories of syntax and semantics acknowledge arguments and adjuncts although the terminology varies and the distinction is generally believed to exist in all languages Dependency grammars sometimes call arguments actants following Lucien Tesniere 1959 The area of grammar that explores the nature of predicates their arguments and adjuncts is called valency theory Predicates have a valence they determine the number and type of arguments that can or must appear in their environment The valence of predicates is also investigated in terms of subcategorization Contents 1 Arguments and adjuncts 1 1 Psycholinguistic argument vs adjuncts 2 Syntactic vs semantic arguments 3 Distinguishing between arguments and adjuncts 3 1 Arguments vs adjuncts 3 2 Obligatory vs optional arguments 3 3 Arguments and adjuncts in noun phrases 4 Representing arguments and adjuncts 5 Relevant theories 6 History of argument linguistics 7 Importance 8 See also 9 Notes 10 ReferencesArguments and adjuncts editThe basic analysis of the syntax and semantics of clauses relies heavily on the distinction between arguments and adjuncts The clause predicate which is often a content verb demands certain arguments That is the arguments are necessary in order to complete the meaning of the verb The adjuncts that appear in contrast are not necessary in this sense The subject phrase and object phrase are the two most frequently occurring arguments of verbal predicates 3 For instance Jill likes Jack Sam fried the meat The old man helped the young man dd Each of these sentences contains two arguments in bold the first noun phrase being the subject argument and the second the object argument Jill for example is the subject argument of the predicate likes and Jack is its object argument Verbal predicates that demand just a subject argument e g sleep work relax are intransitive verbal predicates that demand an object argument as well e g like fry help are transitive and verbal predicates that demand two object arguments are ditransitive e g give lend When additional information is added to our three example sentences one is dealing with adjuncts e g Jill really likes Jack Jill likes Jack most of the time Jill likes Jack when the sun shines Jill likes Jack because he s friendly dd The added phrases in bold are adjuncts they provide additional information that is not necessary to complete the meaning of the predicate likes One key difference between arguments and adjuncts is that the appearance of a given argument is often obligatory whereas adjuncts appear optionally While typical verb arguments are subject or object nouns or noun phrases as in the examples above they can also be prepositional phrases PPs or even other categories The PPs in bold in the following sentences are arguments Sam put the pen on the chair Larry does not put up with that Bill is getting on my case dd We know that these PPs are or contain arguments because when we attempt to omit them the result is unacceptable Sam put the pen Larry does not put up Bill is getting dd Subject and object arguments are known as core arguments core arguments can be suppressed added or exchanged in different ways using voice operations like passivization antipassivization applicativization incorporation etc Prepositional arguments which are also called oblique arguments however do not tend to undergo the same processes Psycholinguistic argument vs adjuncts edit Psycholinguistic theories must explain how syntactic representations are built incrementally during sentence comprehension One view that has sprung from psycholinguistics is the argument structure hypothesis ASH which explains the distinct cognitive operations for argument and adjunct attachment arguments are attached via the lexical mechanism but adjuncts are attached using general non lexical grammatical knowledge that is represented as phrase structure rules or the equivalent Argument status determines the cognitive mechanism in which a phrase will be attached to the developing syntactic representations of a sentence Psycholinguistic evidence supports a formal distinction between arguments and adjuncts for any questions about the argument status of a phrase are in effect questions about learned mental representations of the lexical heads citation needed Syntactic vs semantic arguments editAn important distinction acknowledges both syntactic and semantic arguments Content verbs determine the number and type of syntactic arguments that can or must appear in their environment they impose specific syntactic functions e g subject object oblique specific preposition possessor etc onto their arguments These syntactic functions will vary as the form of the predicate varies e g active verb passive participle gerund nominal etc In languages that have morphological case the arguments of a predicate must appear with the correct case markings e g nominative accusative dative genitive etc imposed on them by their predicate The semantic arguments of the predicate in contrast remain consistent e g Jack is liked by Jill Jill s liking Jack Jack s being liked by Jill the liking of Jack by Jill Jill s like for Jack dd The predicate like appears in various forms in these examples which means that the syntactic functions of the arguments associated with Jack and Jill vary The object of the active sentence for instance becomes the subject of the passive sentence Despite this variation in syntactic functions the arguments remain semantically consistent In each case Jill is the experiencer the one doing the liking and Jack is the one being experienced the one being liked In other words the syntactic arguments are subject to syntactic variation in terms of syntactic functions whereas the thematic roles of the arguments of the given predicate remain consistent as the form of that predicate changes The syntactic arguments of a given verb can also vary across languages For example the verb put in English requires three syntactic arguments subject object locative e g He put the book into the box These syntactic arguments correspond to the three semantic arguments agent theme and goal The Japanese verb oku put in contrast has the same three semantic arguments but the syntactic arguments differ since Japanese does not require three syntactic arguments so it is correct to say Kare ga hon o oita He put the book The equivalent sentence in English is ungrammatical without the required locative argument as the examples involving put above demonstrate For this reason a slight paraphrase is required to render the nearest grammatical equivalent in English He positioned the book or He deposited the book Distinguishing between arguments and adjuncts editArguments vs adjuncts edit This article may be confusing or unclear to readers Please help clarify the article There might be a discussion about this on the talk page January 2013 Learn how and when to remove this template message A large body of literature has been devoted to distinguishing arguments from adjuncts 4 Numerous syntactic tests have been devised for this purpose One such test is the relative clause diagnostic If the test constituent can appear after the combination which occurred happened in a relative clause it is an adjunct not an argument e g Bill left on Tuesday Bill left which happened on Tuesday on Tuesday is an adjunct Susan stopped due to the weather Susan stopped which occurred due to the weather due to the weather is an adjunct Fred tried to say something twice Fred tried to say something which occurred twice twice is an adjunct dd The same diagnostic results in unacceptable relative clauses and sentences when the test constituent is an argument e g Bill left home Bill left which happened home home is an argument Susan stopped her objections Susan stopped which occurred her objections her objections is an argument Fred tried to say something Fred tried to say which happened something something is an argument dd This test succeeds in identifying prepositional arguments as well We are waiting for Susan We are waiting which is happening for Susan for Susan is an argument Tom put the knife in the drawer Tom put the knife which occurred in the drawer in the drawer is an argument We laughed at you We laughed which occurred at you at you is an argument dd The utility of the relative clause test is however limited It incorrectly suggests for instance that modal adverbs e g probably certainly maybe and manner expressions e g quickly carefully totally are arguments If a constituent passes the relative clause test however one can be sure that it is not an argument Obligatory vs optional arguments edit A further division blurs the line between arguments and adjuncts Many arguments behave like adjuncts with respect to another diagnostic the omission diagnostic Adjuncts can always be omitted from the phrase clause or sentence in which they appear without rendering the resulting expression unacceptable Some arguments obligatory ones in contrast cannot be omitted There are many other arguments however that are identified as arguments by the relative clause diagnostic but that can nevertheless be omitted e g a She cleaned the kitchen b She cleaned the kitchen is an optional argument dd a We are waiting for Larry b We are waiting for Larry is an optional argument dd a Susan was working on the model b Susan was working on the model is an optional argument dd The relative clause diagnostic would identify the constituents in bold as arguments The omission diagnostic here however demonstrates that they are not obligatory arguments They are rather optional The insight then is that a three way division is needed On the one hand one distinguishes between arguments and adjuncts and on the other hand one allows for a further division between obligatory and optional arguments Arguments and adjuncts in noun phrases edit Most work on the distinction between arguments and adjuncts has been conducted at the clause level and has focused on arguments and adjuncts to verbal predicates The distinction is crucial for the analysis of noun phrases as well however If it is altered somewhat the relative clause diagnostic can also be used to distinguish arguments from adjuncts in noun phrases e g Bill s bold reading of the poem after lunch bold reading of the poem after lunch that was Bill s Bill s is an argument Bill s reading of the poem after lunch that was bold bold is an adjunct Bill s bold reading after lunch that was of the poem of the poem is an argument Bill s bold reading of the poem that was after lunch after lunch is an adjunct dd dd The diagnostic identifies Bill s and of the poem as arguments and bold and after lunch as adjuncts Representing arguments and adjuncts editThe distinction between arguments and adjuncts is often indicated in the tree structures used to represent syntactic structure In phrase structure grammars an adjunct is adjoined to a projection of its head predicate in such a manner that distinguishes it from the arguments of that predicate The distinction is quite visible in theories that employ the X bar schema e g nbsp dd The complement argument appears as a sister of the head X and the specifier argument appears as a daughter of XP The optional adjuncts appear in one of a number of positions adjoined to a bar projection of X or to XP Theories of syntax that acknowledge n ary branching structures and hence construe syntactic structure as being flatter than the layered structures associated with the X bar schema must employ some other means to distinguish between arguments and adjuncts In this regard some dependency grammars employ an arrow convention Arguments receive a normal dependency edge whereas adjuncts receive an arrow edge 5 In the following tree an arrow points away from an adjunct toward the governor of that adjunct nbsp dd The arrow edges in the tree identify four constituents complete subtrees as adjuncts At one time actually in congress and for fun The normal dependency edges non arrows identify the other constituents as arguments of their heads Thus Sam a duck and to his representative in congress are identified as arguments of the verbal predicate wanted to send Relevant theories editArgumentation theory Argumentation theory focuses on how logical reasoning leads to end results through an internal structure built of premises a method of reasoning and a conclusion There are many versions of argumentation that relate to this theory that include conversational mathematical scientific interpretive legal and political Grammar theory Grammar theory specifically functional theories of grammar relate to the functions of language as the link to fully understanding linguistics by referencing grammar elements to their functions and purposes Syntax theories A variety of theories exist regarding the structure of syntax including generative grammar categorial grammar and dependency grammar Theories in semantics Modern theories of semantics include formal semantics lexical semantics and computational semantics Formal semantics focuses on truth conditioning Lexical Semantics delves into word meanings in relation to their context and computational semantics uses algorithms and architectures to investigate linguistic meanings Valence theory The concept of valence is the number and type of arguments that are linked to a predicate in particular to a verb In valence theory verbs arguments include also the argument expressed by the subject of the verb History of argument linguistics editThe notion of argument structure was first conceived in the 1980s by researchers working in the government binding framework to help address controversies about arguments 6 Importance editThe distinction between arguments and adjuncts is crucial to most theories of syntax and grammar Arguments behave differently from adjuncts in numerous ways Theories of binding coordination discontinuities ellipsis etc must acknowledge and build on the distinction When one examines these areas of syntax what one finds is that arguments consistently behave differently from adjuncts and that without the distinction our ability to investigate and understand these phenomena would be seriously hindered There is a distinction between arguments and adjuncts which is not really noticed by many in everyday language The difference is between obligatory phrases versus phrases which embellish a sentence For instance if someone says Tim punched the stuffed animal the phrase stuffed animal would be an argument because it is the main part of the sentence If someone says Tim punched the stuffed animal with glee the phrase with glee would be an adjunct because it just enhances the sentence and the sentence can stand alone without it 7 See also editAdjunct Dependency grammar Meaning text theory Phrase structure grammar Predicate grammar Subcategorization frame Theta criterion Theta role ValencyNotes edit Most grammars define the argument in this manner i e it is an expression that helps complete the meaning of a predicate a verb See for instance Tesniere 1969 128 Concerning the completion of a predicates meaning via its arguments see for instance Kroeger 2004 9ff Geeraerts Dirk Cuyckens Hubert 2007 The Oxford Handbook of Cognitive Linguistics Oxford University Press US ISBN 978 0 19 514378 2 For instance see the essays on valency theory in Agel et al 2003 6 See Eroms 2000 and Osborne and Gross 2012 in this regard Levin Beth 2013 05 28 Argument Structure Linguistics doi 10 1093 obo 9780199772810 0099 ISBN 978 0 19 977281 0 Retrieved 2019 03 05 Damon Tutunjian Julie E Boland Do we need a distinction between arguments and adjuncts Evidence from psycholinguistic studies of comprehension PDF University of Michigan References editAgel V L Eichinger H W Eroms P Hellwig H Heringer and H Lobin eds 2003 6 Dependency and valency An international handbook of contemporary research Berlin Walter de Gruyter Eroms H W 2000 Syntax der deutschen Sprache Berlin de Gruyter Kroeger P 2004 Analyzing syntax A lexical functional approach Cambridge UK Cambridge University Press Osborne T and T Gross 2012 Constructions are catenae Construction Grammar meets dependency grammar Cognitive Linguistics 23 1 163 214 Tesniere L 1959 Elements de syntaxe structurale Paris Klincksieck Tesniere L 1969 Elements de syntaxe structurale 2nd edition Paris Klincksieck Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Argument linguistics amp oldid 1203973206, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.