fbpx
Wikipedia

The Laws of Thought

An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities by George Boole, published in 1854, is the second of Boole's two monographs on algebraic logic. Boole was a professor of mathematics at what was then Queen's College, Cork (now University College Cork), in Ireland.

Review of the contents

The historian of logic John Corcoran wrote an accessible introduction to Laws of Thought[1] and a point by point comparison of Prior Analytics and Laws of Thought.[2] According to Corcoran, Boole fully accepted and endorsed Aristotle's logic. Boole's goals were “to go under, over, and beyond” Aristotle's logic by:

  1. Providing it with mathematical foundations involving equations;
  2. Extending the class of problems it could treat from assessing validity to solving equations, and;
  3. Expanding the range of applications it could handle — e.g. from propositions having only two terms to those having arbitrarily many.

More specifically, Boole agreed with what Aristotle said; Boole's ‘disagreements’, if they might be called that, concern what Aristotle did not say. First, in the realm of foundations, Boole reduced the four propositional forms of Aristotle's logic to formulas in the form of equations—by itself a revolutionary idea. Second, in the realm of logic's problems, Boole's addition of equation solving to logic—another revolutionary idea—involved Boole's doctrine that Aristotle's rules of inference (the “perfect syllogisms”) must be supplemented by rules for equation solving. Third, in the realm of applications, Boole's system could handle multi-term propositions and arguments whereas Aristotle could handle only two-termed subject-predicate propositions and arguments. For example, Aristotle's system could not deduce “No quadrangle that is a square is a rectangle that is a rhombus” from “No square that is a quadrangle is a rhombus that is a rectangle” or from “No rhombus that is a rectangle is a square that is a quadrangle”.

Boole's work founded the discipline of algebraic logic. It is often, but mistakenly, credited as being the source of what we know today as Boolean algebra. In fact, however, Boole's algebra differs from modern Boolean algebra: in Boole's algebra A+B cannot be interpreted by set union, due to the permissibility of uninterpretable terms in Boole's calculus. Therefore, algebras on Boole's account cannot be interpreted by sets under the operations of union, intersection and complement, as is the case with modern Boolean algebra. The task of developing the modern account of Boolean algebra fell to Boole's successors in the tradition of algebraic logic (Jevons 1869, Peirce 1880, Jevons 1890, Schröder 1890, Huntington 1904).

Uninterpretable terms

In Boole's account of his algebra, terms are reasoned about equationally, without a systematic interpretation being assigned to them. In places, Boole talks of terms being interpreted by sets, but he also recognises terms that cannot always be so interpreted, such as the term 2AB, which arises in equational manipulations. Such terms he classes uninterpretable terms; although elsewhere he has some instances of such terms being interpreted by integers.

The coherences of the whole enterprise is justified by Boole in what Stanley Burris has later called the "rule of 0s and 1s", which justifies the claim that uninterpretable terms cannot be the ultimate result of equational manipulations from meaningful starting formulae (Burris 2000). Boole provided no proof of this rule, but the coherence of his system was proved by Theodore Hailperin, who provided an interpretation based on a fairly simple construction of rings from the integers to provide an interpretation of Boole's theory (Hailperin 1976).

Boole’s 1854 definition of the universe of discourse

In every discourse, whether of the mind conversing with its own thoughts, or of the individual in his intercourse with others, there is an assumed or expressed limit within which the subjects of its operation are confined. The most unfettered discourse is that in which the words we use are understood in the widest possible application, and for them the limits of discourse are co-extensive with those of the universe itself. But more usually we confine ourselves to a less spacious field. Sometimes, in discoursing of men we imply (without expressing the limitation) that it is of men only under certain circumstances and conditions that we speak, as of civilized men, or of men in the vigour of life, or of men under some other condition or relation. Now, whatever may be the extent of the field within which all the objects of our discourse are found, that field may properly be termed the universe of discourse. Furthermore, this universe of discourse is in the strictest sense the ultimate subject of the discourse.

Editions

  • Boole (1854). An Investigation of the Laws of Thought. Walton & Maberly.
  • Boole, George (1958[1854]). An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities. Macmillan. Reprinted with corrections, Dover Publications, New York, NY (reissued by Cambridge University Press, 2009, ISBN 978-1-108-00153-3).

See also

References

Citations

  1. ^ George Boole. 1854/2003. The Laws of Thought, facsimile of 1854 edition, with an introduction by J. Corcoran. Buffalo: Prometheus Books (2003). Reviewed by James van Evra in Philosophy in Review.24 (2004) 167–169.
  2. ^ John Corcoran, Aristotle's Prior Analytics and Boole's Laws of Thought, History and Philosophy of Logic, 24 (2003), pp. 261–288.
  3. ^ Page 42: George Boole. 1854/2003. The Laws of Thought. Facsimile of 1854 edition, with an introduction by J. Corcoran. Buffalo: Prometheus Books (2003). Reviewed by James van Evra in Philosophy in Review 24 (2004): 167–169.

Bibliography

  • Burris, S. (2000). The Laws of Boole's Thought. Manuscript.
  • Hailperin, T. (1976/1986). Boole's Logic and Probability. North Holland.
  • Hailperin, T, (1981). Boole's algebra isn't Boolean algebra. Mathematics Magazine 54(4): 172–184. Reprinted in A Boole Anthology (2000), ed. James Gasser. Synthese Library volume 291, Spring-Verlag.
  • Huntington, E.V. (1904). Sets of independent postulates for the algebra of logic. Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 5:288–309.
  • Jevons, W.S. (1869). The Substitution of Similars. Macmillan and Co.
  • Jevons, W.S. (1990). Pure Logic and Other Minor Works. Ed. by Robert Adamson and Harriet A. Jevons. Lennox Hill Pub. & Dist. Co.
  • Peirce, C.S. (1880). On the algebra of logic. In American Journal of Mathematics 3 (1880).
  • Schröder, E. (1890-1905). Algebra der Logik. Three volumes, B.G. Teubner.

External links

laws, thought, this, article, about, boole, book, logic, overview, axiomatic, rules, various, logicians, philosophers, thought, investigation, laws, thought, which, founded, mathematical, theories, logic, probabilities, george, boole, published, 1854, second, . This article is about Boole s book on logic For overview on the axiomatic rules due to various logicians and philosophers see Law of thought An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities by George Boole published in 1854 is the second of Boole s two monographs on algebraic logic Boole was a professor of mathematics at what was then Queen s College Cork now University College Cork in Ireland Contents 1 Review of the contents 2 Uninterpretable terms 3 Boole s 1854 definition of the universe of discourse 4 Editions 5 See also 6 References 6 1 Citations 6 2 Bibliography 7 External linksReview of the contents EditThe historian of logic John Corcoran wrote an accessible introduction to Laws of Thought 1 and a point by point comparison of Prior Analytics and Laws of Thought 2 According to Corcoran Boole fully accepted and endorsed Aristotle s logic Boole s goals were to go under over and beyond Aristotle s logic by Providing it with mathematical foundations involving equations Extending the class of problems it could treat from assessing validity to solving equations and Expanding the range of applications it could handle e g from propositions having only two terms to those having arbitrarily many More specifically Boole agreed with what Aristotle said Boole s disagreements if they might be called that concern what Aristotle did not say First in the realm of foundations Boole reduced the four propositional forms of Aristotle s logic to formulas in the form of equations by itself a revolutionary idea Second in the realm of logic s problems Boole s addition of equation solving to logic another revolutionary idea involved Boole s doctrine that Aristotle s rules of inference the perfect syllogisms must be supplemented by rules for equation solving Third in the realm of applications Boole s system could handle multi term propositions and arguments whereas Aristotle could handle only two termed subject predicate propositions and arguments For example Aristotle s system could not deduce No quadrangle that is a square is a rectangle that is a rhombus from No square that is a quadrangle is a rhombus that is a rectangle or from No rhombus that is a rectangle is a square that is a quadrangle Boole s work founded the discipline of algebraic logic It is often but mistakenly credited as being the source of what we know today as Boolean algebra In fact however Boole s algebra differs from modern Boolean algebra in Boole s algebra A B cannot be interpreted by set union due to the permissibility of uninterpretable terms in Boole s calculus Therefore algebras on Boole s account cannot be interpreted by sets under the operations of union intersection and complement as is the case with modern Boolean algebra The task of developing the modern account of Boolean algebra fell to Boole s successors in the tradition of algebraic logic Jevons 1869 Peirce 1880 Jevons 1890 Schroder 1890 Huntington 1904 Uninterpretable terms EditIn Boole s account of his algebra terms are reasoned about equationally without a systematic interpretation being assigned to them In places Boole talks of terms being interpreted by sets but he also recognises terms that cannot always be so interpreted such as the term 2AB which arises in equational manipulations Such terms he classes uninterpretable terms although elsewhere he has some instances of such terms being interpreted by integers The coherences of the whole enterprise is justified by Boole in what Stanley Burris has later called the rule of 0s and 1s which justifies the claim that uninterpretable terms cannot be the ultimate result of equational manipulations from meaningful starting formulae Burris 2000 Boole provided no proof of this rule but the coherence of his system was proved by Theodore Hailperin who provided an interpretation based on a fairly simple construction of rings from the integers to provide an interpretation of Boole s theory Hailperin 1976 Boole s 1854 definition of the universe of discourse EditIn every discourse whether of the mind conversing with its own thoughts or of the individual in his intercourse with others there is an assumed or expressed limit within which the subjects of its operation are confined The most unfettered discourse is that in which the words we use are understood in the widest possible application and for them the limits of discourse are co extensive with those of the universe itself But more usually we confine ourselves to a less spacious field Sometimes in discoursing of men we imply without expressing the limitation that it is of men only under certain circumstances and conditions that we speak as of civilized men or of men in the vigour of life or of men under some other condition or relation Now whatever may be the extent of the field within which all the objects of our discourse are found that field may properly be termed the universe of discourse Furthermore this universe of discourse is in the strictest sense the ultimate subject of the discourse George Boole 3 Editions EditBoole 1854 An Investigation of the Laws of Thought Walton amp Maberly Boole George 1958 1854 An Investigation of the Laws of Thought on Which are Founded the Mathematical Theories of Logic and Probabilities Macmillan Reprinted with corrections Dover Publications New York NY reissued by Cambridge University Press 2009 ISBN 978 1 108 00153 3 See also EditAlgebra of conceptsReferences EditCitations Edit George Boole 1854 2003 The Laws of Thought facsimile of 1854 edition with an introduction by J Corcoran Buffalo Prometheus Books 2003 Reviewed by James van Evra in Philosophy in Review 24 2004 167 169 John Corcoran Aristotle s Prior Analytics and Boole s Laws of Thought History and Philosophy of Logic 24 2003 pp 261 288 Page 42 George Boole 1854 2003 The Laws of Thought Facsimile of 1854 edition with an introduction by J Corcoran Buffalo Prometheus Books 2003 Reviewed by James van Evra in Philosophy in Review 24 2004 167 169 Bibliography Edit Burris S 2000 The Laws of Boole s Thought Manuscript Hailperin T 1976 1986 Boole s Logic and Probability North Holland Hailperin T 1981 Boole s algebra isn t Boolean algebra Mathematics Magazine 54 4 172 184 Reprinted in A Boole Anthology 2000 ed James Gasser Synthese Library volume 291 Spring Verlag Huntington E V 1904 Sets of independent postulates for the algebra of logic Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 5 288 309 Jevons W S 1869 The Substitution of Similars Macmillan and Co Jevons W S 1990 Pure Logic and Other Minor Works Ed by Robert Adamson and Harriet A Jevons Lennox Hill Pub amp Dist Co Peirce C S 1880 On the algebra of logic In American Journal of Mathematics 3 1880 Schroder E 1890 1905 Algebra der Logik Three volumes B G Teubner External links EditFull text at Project Gutenberg Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title The Laws of Thought amp oldid 1077329907, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.