fbpx
Wikipedia

Telicity

In linguistics, telicity (/tˈlɪsɪti/; from Greek τέλος 'end, goal') is the property of a verb or verb phrase that presents an action or event as having a specific endpoint. A verb or verb phrase with this property is said to be telic; if the situation it describes is not heading for any particular endpoint, it is said to be atelic.

Testing for telicity in English edit

One common way to gauge whether an English verb phrase is telic is to see whether such a phrase as in an hour, in the sense of "within an hour", (known as a time-frame adverbial) can be applied to it. Conversely, a common way to gauge whether the phrase is atelic is to see whether such a phrase as for an hour (a time-span adverbial) can be applied to it.[1][2][3][4]

Defining the relevant notion of "completeness" edit

Having endpoints edit

One often encounters the notion that telic verbs and verb phrases refer to events that have endpoints, and that atelic ones refer to events or states that don't have endpoints. The notion of having endpoints applies to events in the world rather than the expressions that refer to them. This is the most criticized property of this definition.[5] In fact, every event or state in the world begins and ends at some point, except, perhaps, for states that can be described as "the existence of the universe." Certainly, John's being angry has a beginning, and, unless John is somehow eternally angry, it also has an endpoint. Thus, it is doubtful that one can define telic expressions by means of properties of the events or states that they refer to (a very similar problem arises with the notion that mass nouns refer to things that can't be counted). Thus, recent attempts at making the notion explicit focus on the way that telic expressions refer to, or present events or states.

Put differently, one can simply define telic verbs and verb phrases as referring to events conceptualized or presented as having endpoints, and atelic verbs and verb phrases as those conceptualized or presented as lacking endpoints.

This type of exercise can serve as a reminder of the futility of trying to link linguistic semantics to the real world without considering the intermediary agent of human cognition.

Tending towards a goal edit

According to Garey (1957), who introduced the term "telic",[6]telic verbs are verbs expressing an action tending towards a goal envisaged as realized in a perfective tense, but as contingent in an imperfective tense; atelic verbs, on the other hand, are verbs which do not involve any goal nor endpoint in their semantic structure, but denote actions that are realized as soon as they begin.[7]

Quantization and cumulativity edit

Perhaps the most commonly assumed definition of telicity nowadays[when?][citation needed] is the algebraic definition proposed by Manfred Krifka. Krifka defines telic expressions as ones that are quantized. Atelic ones can be defined in terms of cumulative reference. An expression 'P' can be said to be quantized if and only if it satisfies the following implication, for any choice of x and y:

If x can be described by 'P', and y can also be described by 'P', then x is not a (mereological) proper part of y.

Suppose, for example, that John built two houses. Then each of the two building events can be described as built a house. But the building of the one house isn't, and indeed cannot be thought of a proper part of the building of the second. This contrasts with states describable as, say, walk around aimlessly. If John walked around aimlessly for two hours, then there will be many proper parts of that, that last, say 10 minutes, or 1 hour, etc. which also can be described as walk around aimlessly. Thus, for walk around aimlessly, there will be many choices of x and y, such that both can be described as walk around aimlessly, where x is a proper part of y. Hence, build a house is correctly characterized as telic and walk around aimlessly as atelic by this definition. Quantization can also be used in the definition of count nouns.

An expression 'P' is said to have cumulative reference if and only if, for any choice of x and y, the following implication holds:

If x can be described as 'P', and y can also be described as 'P', then the mereological sum of x and y can also be described as 'P'.

For example, if there is an event of John walking around from 1pm to 2pm, and another event of his walking around from 2pm to 3pm, then there is, by necessity, a third event which is the sum of the other two, which is also an event of walking around. This doesn't hold for expressions like "built a house." If John built a house from time 1 to time 2, and then he built another house from time 2 to time 3, then the sum of these two events (from time 1 to time 3) is not an event that can be described by "built a house." Cumulativity can also be used in the characterization of mass nouns, and in the characterization of the contrast between prepositions like "to" and "towards," i.e. "towards" has cumulative reference to (sets of) paths, while "to" does not.[8]

As an aspect edit

Telicity or telic aspect has been read as a grammatical aspect lately, indicating a reached goal or action completed as intended. Languages that contrast telic and atelic actions are Pirahã and Finnic languages such as Finnish and Estonian; Czech and Hungarian also have perfective prefixes pre- and meg-, respectively, which are additionally telic.

In Finnish, the telicity is mandatorily marked on the object: the accusative is telic, and the partitive is used to express atelicity. More accurately, the accusative case is used of objects that are completely affected by the situation as presented by the speaker, whereas using partitive implies that the object is only partially affected in the situation or that the situation is framed so that the object continues to be affected outside it. The terms telic and atelic are not traditionally used in Finnish grammatical description; instead, it is customary to speak of resultative and irresultative sentences.

An example of the contrast between resultative and irresultative in Finnish:

Kirjoitin

wrote-1SG

artikkelin.

article-ACC

Kirjoitin artikkelin.

wrote-1SG article-ACC

"I wrote the/an article (and finished it)"

Kirjoitin

wrote-1SG

artikkelia.

article-PTV

Kirjoitin artikkelia.

wrote-1SG article-PTV

"I wrote/was writing the/an article (but did not necessarily finish it)"

The telic sentence necessarily requires finishing the article. In the atelic sentence, it is not expressed whether or not the article is finished. The atelic form expresses ignorance, i.e. atelic is not anti-telic: Kirjoitin artikkelia ja sain sen valmiiksi "I was writing the article-PART and then got it-ACC finished" is correct. What is interpreted as the goal or result is determined by the context, e.g.

  • Ammuin karhun – "I shot the bear (succeeded)"; i.e., "I shot the bear dead". ← implicit purpose
  • Ammuin karhua – "I shot (towards) the bear"; i.e., "I shot at the bear (but it did not die)".

There are many verbs that correspond to only one telicity due to their inherent meaning. The partitive verbs roughly correspond with atelic verbs in Garey's definition, that is, the action normally does not have a result or goal, and it would be logically and grammatically incorrect to place them in the telic aspect. However, even inherently atelic verbs such as rakastaa "to love" can in semantically unusual constructions, where a kind of result is involved, become telic:

Hän

(s)he

rakastaa

love-3SG

minua.

me-PTV

Hän rakastaa minua.

(s)he love-3SG me-PTV

"(s)he loves me"

Hän

(s)he

rakastaa

love-3SG

minut

me-ACC

kuoliaaksi.

dead-TRANSL

Hän rakastaa minut kuoliaaksi.

(s)he love-3SG me-ACC dead-TRANSL

"(s)he loves me to death"

Also, many other stative verbs that are in terms of their meaning inherently atelic, mark their objects in the accusative case, which is the normal case for telic situations:

Tiedän

know-1SG

Pekan

Pekka-GEN

osoitteen.

address-ACC

Tiedän Pekan osoitteen.

know-1SG Pekka-GEN address-ACC

"I know Pekka's address" (not *Tiedän Pekan osoitetta ... address-PART)

Muistan

remember-1SG

sinun

you-GEN

kasvosi.

face-PL.ACC.2SG_POSS

Muistan sinun kasvosi.

remember-1SG you-GEN face-PL.ACC.2SG_POSS

"I remember your face" (not *Muistan sinun kasvojasi ... face-PL.PART-2SG_POSS)

Furthermore, the telicity contrast can act as case government, so that changing the case can change the meaning entirely. For example, näin hänet (I saw him-ACC) means "I saw him", but näin häntä (I saw him-PART) means "I met him (occasionally, sometimes, every now and then)". This is often highly irregular.

The use of a telic object may implicitly communicate that the action takes place in the future. For example,

  • Luen kirjan. "I will read the book"; the action can only be complete in the future.
  • Luen kirjaa. "I am reading a book" or "I will be reading a book"; no indication is given for the time.

Often telicity is superficially similar to the perfective aspect, and one can find descriptions such as "roughly perfective–imperfective". However, lexical pairs of perfective and imperfective verbs are found in Finnish, and this contrast can be superimposed with the telicity contrast.[clarification needed]

References edit

  1. ^ Verkuyl, Henk. 1972. On the compositional nature of aspects. Dordrecht:Reidel.
  2. ^ Dowty, David. 1979. Word meaning and Montague Grammar. Dordrecht: Reidel. ISBN 90-277-1009-0.
  3. ^ Krifka, Manfred 1989. Nominal reference, temporal constitution and quantification in event semantics. In Renate Bartsch, Johan van Benthem and Peter van Emde Boas (eds.), Semantics and Contextual Expression: 75-115. Dordrecht: Foris. ISBN 90-6765-443-4.
  4. ^ Verkuyl, Henk. 1993. A theory of aspectuality: the interaction between temporal and atemporal structure. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-56452-2
  5. ^ Borik, Olga. 2002. Aspect and Reference Time. Oxford University Press. 2006. ISBN 0-19-929129-2. Aspect and reference time. Based on Ph.D. thesis, Utrecht University, 2002.
  6. ^ Lindstedt, Jouko (1985). On the Semantics of Tense and Aspect in Bulgarian. Slavica Helsingiensia, ISSN 0780-3281. Vol. 4. University of Helsinki, Department of Slavonic Languages. p. 155. ISBN 9789514535703. Retrieved 2016-08-04. The term "telic" was first proposed by Howard B. Garey (1957) in a study of aspect in French.
  7. ^ Garey, Howard B. 1957. "Verbal aspects in French." Language 33:91–110.
  8. ^ Zwarts, Joost. 2005. "Prepositional Aspect and the Algebra of Paths." Linguistics and Philosophy 28.6, 739-779.[dead link]

External links edit

  • Krifka, Manfred, "Origins of Telicity". Also in Events and Grammar, Susan Rothstein (ed.), 1998, ISBN 0-7923-4940-7, pp. 197–236

telicity, other, uses, telic, telic, linguistics, telicity, from, greek, τέλος, goal, property, verb, verb, phrase, that, presents, action, event, having, specific, endpoint, verb, verb, phrase, with, this, property, said, telic, situation, describes, heading,. For other uses of telic see Telic In linguistics telicity t iː ˈ l ɪ s ɪ t i from Greek telos end goal is the property of a verb or verb phrase that presents an action or event as having a specific endpoint A verb or verb phrase with this property is said to be telic if the situation it describes is not heading for any particular endpoint it is said to be atelic Contents 1 Testing for telicity in English 2 Defining the relevant notion of completeness 2 1 Having endpoints 2 2 Tending towards a goal 2 3 Quantization and cumulativity 3 As an aspect 4 References 5 External linksTesting for telicity in English editOne common way to gauge whether an English verb phrase is telic is to see whether such a phrase as in an hour in the sense of within an hour known as a time frame adverbial can be applied to it Conversely a common way to gauge whether the phrase is atelic is to see whether such a phrase as for an hour a time span adverbial can be applied to it 1 2 3 4 Defining the relevant notion of completeness editHaving endpoints edit One often encounters the notion that telic verbs and verb phrases refer to events that have endpoints and that atelic ones refer to events or states that don t have endpoints The notion of having endpoints applies to events in the world rather than the expressions that refer to them This is the most criticized property of this definition 5 In fact every event or state in the world begins and ends at some point except perhaps for states that can be described as the existence of the universe Certainly John s being angry has a beginning and unless John is somehow eternally angry it also has an endpoint Thus it is doubtful that one can define telic expressions by means of properties of the events or states that they refer to a very similar problem arises with the notion that mass nouns refer to things that can t be counted Thus recent attempts at making the notion explicit focus on the way that telic expressions refer to or present events or states Put differently one can simply define telic verbs and verb phrases as referring to events conceptualized or presented as having endpoints and atelic verbs and verb phrases as those conceptualized or presented as lacking endpoints This type of exercise can serve as a reminder of the futility of trying to link linguistic semantics to the real world without considering the intermediary agent of human cognition Tending towards a goal edit According to Garey 1957 who introduced the term telic 6 telic verbs are verbs expressing an action tending towards a goal envisaged as realized in a perfective tense but as contingent in an imperfective tense atelic verbs on the other hand are verbs which do not involve any goal nor endpoint in their semantic structure but denote actions that are realized as soon as they begin 7 Quantization and cumulativity edit Perhaps the most commonly assumed definition of telicity nowadays when citation needed is the algebraic definition proposed by Manfred Krifka Krifka defines telic expressions as ones that are quantized Atelic ones can be defined in terms of cumulative reference An expression P can be said to be quantized if and only if it satisfies the following implication for any choice of x and y If x can be described by P and y can also be described by P then x is not a mereological proper part of y dd Suppose for example that John built two houses Then each of the two building events can be described as built a house But the building of the one house isn t and indeed cannot be thought of a proper part of the building of the second This contrasts with states describable as say walk around aimlessly If John walked around aimlessly for two hours then there will be many proper parts of that that last say 10 minutes or 1 hour etc which also can be described as walk around aimlessly Thus for walk around aimlessly there will be many choices of x and y such that both can be described as walk around aimlessly where x is a proper part of y Hence build a house is correctly characterized as telic and walk around aimlessly as atelic by this definition Quantization can also be used in the definition of count nouns An expression P is said to have cumulative reference if and only if for any choice of x and y the following implication holds If x can be described as P and y can also be described as P then the mereological sum of x and y can also be described as P dd For example if there is an event of John walking around from 1pm to 2pm and another event of his walking around from 2pm to 3pm then there is by necessity a third event which is the sum of the other two which is also an event of walking around This doesn t hold for expressions like built a house If John built a house from time 1 to time 2 and then he built another house from time 2 to time 3 then the sum of these two events from time 1 to time 3 is not an event that can be described by built a house Cumulativity can also be used in the characterization of mass nouns and in the characterization of the contrast between prepositions like to and towards i e towards has cumulative reference to sets of paths while to does not 8 As an aspect editThe examples and perspective in this article may not represent a worldwide view of the subject You may improve this article discuss the issue on the talk page or create a new article as appropriate December 2010 Learn how and when to remove this template message Telicity or telic aspect has been read as a grammatical aspect lately indicating a reached goal or action completed as intended Languages that contrast telic and atelic actions are Piraha and Finnic languages such as Finnish and Estonian Czech and Hungarian also have perfective prefixes pre and meg respectively which are additionally telic In Finnish the telicity is mandatorily marked on the object the accusative is telic and the partitive is used to express atelicity More accurately the accusative case is used of objects that are completely affected by the situation as presented by the speaker whereas using partitive implies that the object is only partially affected in the situation or that the situation is framed so that the object continues to be affected outside it The terms telic and atelic are not traditionally used in Finnish grammatical description instead it is customary to speak of resultative and irresultative sentences An example of the contrast between resultative and irresultative in Finnish Kirjoitinwrote 1SGartikkelin article ACCKirjoitin artikkelin wrote 1SG article ACC I wrote the an article and finished it Kirjoitinwrote 1SGartikkelia article PTVKirjoitin artikkelia wrote 1SG article PTV I wrote was writing the an article but did not necessarily finish it The telic sentence necessarily requires finishing the article In the atelic sentence it is not expressed whether or not the article is finished The atelic form expresses ignorance i e atelic is not anti telic Kirjoitin artikkelia ja sain sen valmiiksi I was writing the article PART and then got it ACC finished is correct What is interpreted as the goal or result is determined by the context e g Ammuin karhun I shot the bear succeeded i e I shot the bear dead implicit purpose Ammuin karhua I shot towards the bear i e I shot at the bear but it did not die There are many verbs that correspond to only one telicity due to their inherent meaning The partitive verbs roughly correspond with atelic verbs in Garey s definition that is the action normally does not have a result or goal and it would be logically and grammatically incorrect to place them in the telic aspect However even inherently atelic verbs such as rakastaa to love can in semantically unusual constructions where a kind of result is involved become telic Han s herakastaalove 3SGminua me PTVHan rakastaa minua s he love 3SG me PTV s he loves me Han s herakastaalove 3SGminutme ACCkuoliaaksi dead TRANSLHan rakastaa minut kuoliaaksi s he love 3SG me ACC dead TRANSL s he loves me to death Also many other stative verbs that are in terms of their meaning inherently atelic mark their objects in the accusative case which is the normal case for telic situations Tiedanknow 1SGPekanPekka GENosoitteen address ACCTiedan Pekan osoitteen know 1SG Pekka GEN address ACC I know Pekka s address not Tiedan Pekan osoitetta address PART Muistanremember 1SGsinunyou GENkasvosi face PL ACC 2SG POSSMuistan sinun kasvosi remember 1SG you GEN face PL ACC 2SG POSS I remember your face not Muistan sinun kasvojasi face PL PART 2SG POSS Furthermore the telicity contrast can act as case government so that changing the case can change the meaning entirely For example nain hanet I saw him ACC means I saw him but nain hanta I saw him PART means I met him occasionally sometimes every now and then This is often highly irregular The use of a telic object may implicitly communicate that the action takes place in the future For example Luen kirjan I will read the book the action can only be complete in the future Luen kirjaa I am reading a book or I will be reading a book no indication is given for the time Often telicity is superficially similar to the perfective aspect and one can find descriptions such as roughly perfective imperfective However lexical pairs of perfective and imperfective verbs are found in Finnish and this contrast can be superimposed with the telicity contrast clarification needed References edit Verkuyl Henk 1972 On the compositional nature of aspects Dordrecht Reidel Dowty David 1979 Word meaning and Montague Grammar Dordrecht Reidel ISBN 90 277 1009 0 Krifka Manfred 1989 Nominal reference temporal constitution and quantification in event semantics In Renate Bartsch Johan van Benthem and Peter van Emde Boas eds Semantics and Contextual Expression 75 115 Dordrecht Foris ISBN 90 6765 443 4 Verkuyl Henk 1993 A theory of aspectuality the interaction between temporal and atemporal structure Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 56452 2 Borik Olga 2002 Aspect and Reference Time Oxford University Press 2006 ISBN 0 19 929129 2 Aspect and reference time Based on Ph D thesis Utrecht University 2002 Lindstedt Jouko 1985 On the Semantics of Tense and Aspect in Bulgarian Slavica Helsingiensia ISSN 0780 3281 Vol 4 University of Helsinki Department of Slavonic Languages p 155 ISBN 9789514535703 Retrieved 2016 08 04 The term telic was first proposed by Howard B Garey 1957 in a study of aspect in French Garey Howard B 1957 Verbal aspects in French Language 33 91 110 Zwarts Joost 2005 Prepositional Aspect and the Algebra of Paths Linguistics and Philosophy 28 6 739 779 dead link External links editKrifka Manfred Origins of Telicity Also in Events and Grammar Susan Rothstein ed 1998 ISBN 0 7923 4940 7 pp 197 236 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Telicity amp oldid 1164021567, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.