fbpx
Wikipedia

Pyrrhonism

Pyrrhonism is an Ancient Greek school of philosophical skepticism which rejects dogma and advocates the suspension of judgement over the truth of all beliefs. It was founded by Aenesidemus in the first century BCE, and said to have been inspired by the teachings of Pyrrho and Timon of Phlius in the fourth century BCE.[1] Pyrrhonism is best known today through the surviving works of Sextus Empiricus, writing in the late second century or early third century CE.[2] The publication of Sextus' works in the Renaissance ignited a revival of interest in Skepticism and played a major role in Reformation thought and the development of early modern philosophy.

History edit

Pyrrhonism is named after Pyrrho of Elis, a Greek philosopher in the 4th century BCE who was credited by the later Pyrrhonists with forming the first comprehensive school of skeptical thought. However, ancient testimony about the philosophical beliefs of the historical Pyrrho is minimal, and often contradictory:[1] his teachings were recorded by his student Timon of Phlius, but those works have been lost, and only survive in fragments quoted by later authors, and based on testimonies of later authors such as Cicero, Pyrrho's own philosophy as recorded by Timon may have been much more dogmatic than that of the later school who bore his name.[1] While Pyrrhonism would become the dominant form of skepticism in the early Roman period, in the Hellenistic period, the Platonic Academy was the primary advocate of skepticism until the mid-first century BCE,[3] when Pyrrhonism as a philosophical school was founded by Aenesidemus.[1][4]

Philosophy edit

The goal of Pyrrhonism is ataraxia,[5] an untroubled and tranquil condition of soul that results from a suspension of judgement, a mental rest owing to which we neither deny nor affirm anything.

Pyrrhonists dispute that the dogmatists – which includes all of Pyrrhonism's rival philosophies – claim to have found truth regarding non-evident matters, and that these opinions about non-evident matters (i.e., dogma) are what prevent one from attaining eudaimonia. For any of these dogmas, a Pyrrhonist makes arguments for and against such that the matter cannot be concluded, thus suspending judgement, and thereby inducing ataraxia.

Pyrrhonists can be subdivided into those who are ephectic (engaged in suspension of judgment), aporetic (engaged in refutation)[6] or zetetic (engaged in seeking).[7] An ephectic merely suspends judgment on a matter, "balancing perceptions and thoughts against one another,"[8] It is a less aggressive form of skepticism, in that sometimes "suspension of judgment evidently just happens to the sceptic".[9] An aporetic skeptic, in contrast, works more actively towards their goal, engaging in the refutation of arguments in favor of various possible beliefs in order to reach aporia, an impasse, or state of perplexity,[10] which leads to suspension of judgement.[9] Finally, the zetetic claims to be continually searching for the truth but to have thus far been unable to find it, and thus continues to suspend belief while also searching for reason to cease the suspension of belief.

Modes edit

Although Pyrrhonism's objective is ataraxia, it is best known for its epistemological arguments. The core practice is through setting argument against argument. To aid in this, the Pyrrhonist philosophers Aenesidemus and Agrippa developed sets of stock arguments known as "modes" or "tropes."

The ten modes of Aenesidemus edit

Aenesidemus is considered the creator of the ten tropes of Aenesidemus (also known as the ten modes of Aenesidemus)—although whether he invented the tropes or just systematized them from prior Pyrrhonist works is unknown. The tropes represent reasons for suspension of judgment. These are as follows:[11]

  1. Different animals manifest different modes of perception;
  2. Similar differences are seen among individual men;
  3. For the same man, information perceived with the senses is self-contradictory
  4. Furthermore, it varies from time to time with physical changes
  5. In addition, this data differs according to local relations
  6. Objects are known only indirectly through the medium of air, moisture, etc.
  7. These objects are in a condition of perpetual change in colour, temperature, size and motion
  8. All perceptions are relative and interact one upon another
  9. Our impressions become less critical through repetition and custom
  10. All men are brought up with different beliefs, under different laws and social conditions

According to Sextus, superordinate to these ten modes stand three other modes: that based on the subject who judges (modes 1, 2, 3 & 4), that based on the object judged (modes 7 & 10), that based on both subject who judges and object judged (modes 5, 6, 8 & 9), and superordinate to these three modes is the mode of relation.[12]

The five modes of Agrippa edit

These "tropes" or "modes" are given by Sextus Empiricus in his Outlines of Pyrrhonism. According to Sextus, they are attributed only "to the more recent skeptics" and it is by Diogenes Laërtius that we attribute them to Agrippa.[13] The five tropes of Agrippa are:

  1. Dissent – The uncertainty demonstrated by the differences of opinions among philosophers and people in general.
  2. Infinite regress – All proof rests on matters themselves in need of proof, and so on to infinity.
  3. Relation – All things are changed as their relations become changed, or, as we look upon them from different points of view.
  4. Assumption – The truth asserted is based on an unsupported assumption.
  5. Circularity – The truth asserted involves a circularity of proofs.

According to the mode deriving from dispute, we find that undecidable dissension about the matter proposed has come about both in ordinary life and among philosophers. Because of this we are not able to choose or to rule out anything, and we end up with suspension of judgement. In the mode deriving from infinite regress, we say that what is brought forward as a source of conviction for the matter proposed itself needs another such source, which itself needs another, and so ad infinitum, so that we have no point from which to begin to establish anything, and suspension of judgement follows. In the mode deriving from relativity, as we said above, the existing object appears to be such-and-such relative to the subject judging and to the things observed together with it, but we suspend judgement on what it is like in its nature. We have the mode from hypothesis when the Dogmatists, being thrown back ad infinitum, begin from something which they do not establish but claim to assume simply and without proof in virtue of a concession. The reciprocal mode occurs when what ought to be confirmatory of the object under investigation needs to be made convincing by the object under investigation; then, being unable to take either in order to establish the other, we suspend judgement about both.[14]

With reference to these five tropes, that the first and third are a short summary of the earlier Ten Modes of Aenesidemus.[13] The three additional ones show a progress in the Pyrrhonist system, building upon the objections derived from the fallibility of sense and opinion to more abstract and metaphysical grounds. According to Victor Brochard "the five tropes can be regarded as the most radical and most precise formulation of skepticism that has ever been given. In a sense, they are still irresistible today."[15]

Criteria of action edit

Pyrrhonist decision making is made according to what the Pyrrhonists describe as the criteria of action holding to the appearances, without beliefs in accord with the ordinary regimen of life based on:

  1. the guidance of nature, by which we are naturally capable of sensation and thought
  2. the compulsion of the passions by which hunger drives us to food and thirst makes us drink
  3. the handing down of customs and laws by which we accept that piety in the conduct of life is good and impiety bad
  4. instruction in techne[16]

Skeptic sayings edit

The Pyrrhonists devised several sayings (Greek ΦΩΝΩΝ) to help practitioners bring their minds to suspend judgment.[17] Among these are:

  • Not more, nothing more (a saying attributed to Democritus[18])
  • Non-assertion (aphasia)
  • Perhaps, it is possible, maybe
  • I withhold assent
  • I determine nothing (Montaigne created a variant of this as his own personal motto, "Que sais-je?" – "what do I know?")
  • Everything is indeterminate
  • Everything is non-apprehensible
  • I do not apprehend
  • To every argument an equal argument is opposed

Texts edit

Except for the works of Sextus Empiricus, the texts of ancient Pyrrhonism have been lost. There is a summary of the Pyrrhonian Discourses by Aenesidemus, preserved by Photius, and a brief summary of Pyrrho's teaching by Aristocles, quoting Pyrrho's student Timon preserved by Eusebius:

'The things themselves are equally indifferent, and unstable, and indeterminate, and therefore neither our senses nor our opinions are either true or false. For this reason then we must not trust them, but be without opinions, and without bias, and without wavering, saying of every single thing that it no more is than is not, or both is and is not, or neither is nor is not.[19]

Influence edit

In Ancient Greek philosophy edit

 
Skeptics in Raphael's School of Athens painting. Pyrrho is #4 and Timon #5

Pyrrhonism is often contrasted with Academic skepticism, a similar but distinct form of Hellenistic philosophical skepticism.[9][20][21] While early Academic skepticism was influenced in part by Pyrrho,[22] it grew more and more dogmatic until Aenesidemus broke with the Academics to revive Pyrrhonism in the first century BCE, denouncing the Academy as "Stoics fighting against Stoics.[23]" Some later Pyrrhonists, such as Sextus Empiricus, go so far as to claim that Pyrrhonists are the only real skeptics, dividing all philosophy into the dogmatists, the Academics, and the skeptics.[20] Dogmatists claim to have knowledge, Academic skeptics claim that knowledge is impossible, while Pyrrhonists assent to neither proposition, suspending judgment on both.[9][20][24] The second century Roman historian Aulus Gellius describes the distinction as "...the Academics apprehend (in some sense) the very fact that nothing can be apprehended, and they determine (in some sense) that nothing can be determined, whereas the Pyrrhonists assert that not even that seems to be true, since nothing seems to be true.[25][21]"

Sextus Empiricus also said that the Pyrrhonist school influenced and had substantial overlap with the Empiric school of medicine, but that Pyrrhonism had more in common with the Methodic school in that it "follow[s] the appearances and take[s] from these whatever seems expedient."[26]

Although Julian the Apostate[27] mentions that Pyrrhonism had died out at the time of his writings, other writers mention the existence of later Pyrrhonists. Pseudo-Clement, writing around the same time (c. 300-320 CE) mentions Pyrrhonists in his Homilies[28] and Agathias even reports a Pyrrhonist named Uranius as late as the middle of the 6th century CE.[29]

Similarities between Pyrrhonism and Indian philosophy edit

 
Nagarjuna, a Madhyamaka Buddhist philosopher whose skeptical arguments are similar to those preserved in the work of Sextus Empiricus

According to Diogenes Laërtius, Pyrrho was said to have traveled to India with Alexander the Great's army where Pyrrho was said to have studied with the magi and the gymnosophists,[30] and where he may have been influenced by Buddhist teachings,[31] most particularly the three marks of existence.[32] Scholars who argue for such influence mention the fact that even the ancient author Diogenesis Laërtius states as much, when he wrote that Pyrrho “foregathered with the Indian Gymnosophists and with the Magi. This led him to adopt a most noble philosophy."[31]

According to Christopher I. Beckwith's analysis of the Aristocles Passage, adiaphora (anatta), astathmēta (dukkha), and anepikrita (anicca) are strikingly similar to the Buddhist three marks of existence,[32] indicating that Pyrrho's teaching is based on Buddhism. Beckwith contends that the 18 months Pyrrho spent in India were long enough to learn a foreign language, and that the key innovative tenets of Pyrrho's skepticism were only found in Indian philosophy at the time and not in Greece.[33] Other similarities between Pyrrhonism and Buddhism include a version of the tetralemma among the Pyrrhonist maxims, and more significantly, the idea of suspension of judgement and how that can lead to peace and liberation, ataraxia in Pyrrhonism and nirvana in Buddhism.[34][35]

Furthermore, Buddhist philosopher Jan Westerhoff says "many of Nāgārjuna's arguments concerning causation bear strong similarities to classical sceptical arguments as presented in the third book of Sextus Empiricus's Outlines of Pyrrhonism,"[36] and Thomas McEvilley suspects that Nagarjuna may have been influenced by Greek Pyrrhonist texts imported into India.[37] McEvilley argues for mutual iteration in the Buddhist logico-epistemological traditions between Pyrrhonism and Madhyamika:

An extraordinary similarity, that has long been noticed, between Pyrrhonism and Mādhyamika is the formula known in connection with Buddhism as the fourfold negation (Catuṣkoṭi) and which in Pyrrhonic form might be called the fourfold indeterminacy.[38]

McEvilley also notes a correspondence between the Pyrrhonist and Madhyamaka views about truth, comparing Sextus' account[39] of two criteria regarding truth, one which judges between reality and unreality, and another which we use as a guide in everyday life. By the first criteria, nothing is either true or false, but by the second, information from the senses may be considered either true or false for practical purposes. As Edward Conze[40][verification needed] has noted, this is similar to the Madhyamika Two Truths doctrine, a distinction between "Absolute truth" (paramārthasatya), "the knowledge of the real as it is without any distortion,"[41] and "Truth so-called" (saṃvṛti satya), "truth as conventionally believed in common parlance.[41][42]

 
Map of Alexander the Great's empire and the route he and Pyrrho took to India


However, other scholars, such as Stephen Batchelor[43] and Charles Goodman[44] question Beckwith's conclusions about the degree of Buddhist influence on Pyrrho. Conversely, while critical of Beckwith's ideas, Kuzminsky sees credibility in the hypothesis that Pyrrho was influenced by Buddhism, even if it cannot be safely ascertained with our current information.[31]

While discussing Christopher Beckwith's claims in Greek Buddha: Pyrrho's Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia, Jerker Blomqvist states that:

On the other hand, certain elements that are generally regarded as essential features of Buddhism are entirely absent from ancient Pyrrhonism/scepticism. The concepts of good and bad karma must have been an impossibility in the Pyrrhonist universe, if "things" were ἀδιάφορα, 'without a logical self-identity', and, consequently, could not be differentiated from each other by labels such as 'good' and 'bad' or 'just' and 'unjust'. A doctrine of rebirth, reminiscent of the Buddhist one though favored by Plato and Pythagoras, was totally alien to the Pyrrhonists. The ἀταραξία, 'undisturbedness', that the Pyrrhonists promised their followers, may have a superficial resemblance to the Buddhist nirvana, but ἀταραξία, unlike nirvana, did not involve a liberation from a cycle of reincarnation; rather, it was a mode of life in this world, blessed with μετριοπάθεια, 'moderation of feeling' or 'moderate suffering', not with the absence of any variety of pain. Kuzminski, whom Beckwith hails as a precursor of his, had largely ignored the problem with this disparity between Buddhism and Pyrrhonism.[45]

Ajñana, which upheld radical skepticism, may have been a more powerful influence on Pyrrho than Buddhism. The Buddhists referred to Ajñana's adherents as Amarāvikkhepikas or "eel-wrigglers", due to their refusal to commit to a single doctrine.[46] Scholars including Barua, Jayatilleke, and Flintoff, contend that Pyrrho was influenced by, or at the very least agreed with, Indian skepticism rather than Buddhism or Jainism, based on the fact that he valued ataraxia, which can be translated as "freedom from worry".[47][48][49] Jayatilleke, in particular, contends that Pyrrho may have been influenced by the first three schools of Ajñana, since they too valued freedom from worry.[50]

Modern edit

 
Balance scales in equal balance are a modern symbol of Pyrrhonism

The recovery and publication of the works of Sextus Empiricus, particularly a widely influential translation by Henri Estienne published in 1562,[51] ignited a revival of interest in Pyrrhonism.[51] Philosophers of the time used his works to source their arguments on how to deal with the religious issues of their day. Major philosophers such as Michel de Montaigne, Marin Mersenne, and Pierre Gassendi later drew on the model of Pyrrhonism outlined in Sextus Empiricus' works for their own arguments. This resurgence of Pyrrhonism has sometimes been called the beginning of modern philosophy.[51] Montaigne adopted the image of a balance scale for his motto,[52] which became a modern symbol of Pyrrhonism.[citation needed] It has also been suggested that Pyrrhonism provided the skeptical underpinnings that René Descartes drew from in developing his influential method of Cartesian doubt and the associated turn of early modern philosophy towards epistemology.[51] In the 18th century, David Hume was also considerably influenced by Pyrrhonism, using "Pyrrhonism" as a synonym for "skepticism."[53][better source needed].

 
Nietzsche was critical of Pyrrhonian ephectics.

Friedrich Nietzsche, however, criticized the "ephetics" of the Pyrrhonists as a flaw of early philosophers, who he characterized as "shy little blunderer[s] and milquetoast[s] with crooked legs" prone to overindulging "his doubting drive, his negating drive, his wait-and-see ('ephectic') drive, his analytical drive, his exploring, searching, venturing drive, his comparing, balancing drive, his will to neutrality and objectivity, his will to every sine ira et studio: have we already grasped that for the longest time they all went against the first demands of morality and conscience?"[54]

Contemporary edit

The term "neo-Pyrrhonism" is used to refer to modern Pyrrhonists such as Benson Mates and Robert Fogelin.[55][56]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ a b c d Long, A. A. (12 September 1996). Hellenistic Philosophy: Stoics, Epicureans, Sceptics. Bloomsbury Academic. pp. 75–76. ISBN 978-0-7156-1238-5. Retrieved 15 January 2023.
  2. ^ Popkin, Richard Henry (2003). The history of scepticism : from Savonarola to Bayle. Popkin, Richard Henry, 1923- (Rev. and expanded ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0198026714. OCLC 65192690.
  3. ^ Thorsrud, Harald (2009). Ancient scepticism. Stocksfield [U.K.]: Acumen. pp. 120–121. ISBN 978-1-84465-409-3. OCLC 715184861. Pyrrhonism, in whatever form it might have taken after Timon's death in 230 BCE, was utterly neglected until Aenesidemus brought it back to public attention
  4. ^ Stéphane Marchand, "Sextus Empiricus' Style Of Writing", in New Essays on Ancient Pyrrhonism, p 113
  5. ^ Warren, James (2002). Epicurus and Democritean ethics: An archaeology of ataraxia. Cambridge University Press. p. I. ISBN 0521813697.
  6. ^ Pulleyn, William (1830). The Etymological Compendium, Or, Portfolio of Origins and Inventions. T. Tegg. pp. 353.
  7. ^ Bett, Richard Arnot Home (28 January 2010). The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism. Cambridge University Press. p. 212.
  8. ^ Bett, Richard Arnot Home (28 January 2010). The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism. Cambridge University Press. p. 213.
  9. ^ a b c d Klein, Peter (2015). "Skepticism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. from the original on 25 July 2018. Retrieved 19 March 2021.
  10. ^ McInerny, Ralph (1969). A History of Western Philosophy, Volume 2. Aeterna Press. pp. Chp III. Skeptics and the New Academy, A. Pyrrho of Elis section, para 3–4.
  11. ^   One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domainChisholm, Hugh, ed. (1911). "Aenesidemus". Encyclopædia Britannica. Vol. 1 (11th ed.). Cambridge University Press. pp. 257–258.
  12. ^ Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, pp. 25–27
  13. ^ a b Diogenes Laërtius, ix.
  14. ^ Sextus Empiricus, Pyrrhōneioi hypotypōseis i., from Annas, J., Outlines of Scepticism Cambridge University Press. (2000).
  15. ^ Brochard, V., The Greek Skeptics.
  16. ^ Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book I Chapter 11 Section 23
  17. ^ Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book I Chapter 18
  18. ^ Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book II Chapter 30
  19. ^ Eusebius. "Praeparatio Evangelica Book XIV". Tertullian Project. Retrieved 27 January 2023.
  20. ^ a b c Sextus, Empiricus (1990). Outlines of pyrrhonism. Robert Gregg Bury. Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books. ISBN 0-87975-597-0. OCLC 23367477.
  21. ^ a b Thorsrud, Harald (2009). Ancient scepticism. Stocksfield [U.K.]: Acumen. ISBN 978-1-84465-409-3. OCLC 715184861.
  22. ^ Thorsrud, Harald (2009). Ancient scepticism. Stocksfield [U.K.]: Acumen. p. 45. ISBN 978-1-84465-409-3. OCLC 715184861.
  23. ^ Thorsrud, Harald (2009). Ancient scepticism. Stocksfield [U.K.]: Acumen. pp. 102–103. ISBN 978-1-84465-409-3. OCLC 715184861. Aenesidemus criticized his fellow Academics for being dogmatic...Aenesidemus committed his scepticism to writing probably some time in the early-to-mid first century BCE...leading Aenesidemus to dismiss them as "Stoics fighting against Stoics."
  24. ^ Popkin, Richard (1995). The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy. Robert Audi. Cambridge. p. 741. ISBN 0-521-40224-7. OCLC 32272442.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  25. ^ Gellius, Aulus (2008). Noctes Atticae. Josef Feix (3. Dr ed.). Paderborn: Schöningh. ISBN 978-3-14-010714-3. OCLC 635311697.
  26. ^ Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism I.237, trans. Etheridge (Scepticism, Man, and God, Wesleyan University Press, 1964, p. 98).
  27. ^ Epistles lxxxix 301C
  28. ^ Pseudo-Clement, Homilies, 13.7
  29. ^ Agathias II 29-32, cited in Jonathan Barnes, Mantissa 2015 p. 652
  30. ^ "Diogenes Laërtius, Lives of Eminent Philosophers Book IX - Chapter 11. PYRRHO (c. 360-270 b.c.)". www.perseus.tufts.edu.
  31. ^ a b c Kuzminski, Adrian (2021). Pyrrhonian Buddhism: A Philosophical Reconstruction. Routledge. ISBN 9781000350074.
  32. ^ a b Beckwith, Christopher I. (2015). Greek Buddha: Pyrrho's Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia (PDF). Princeton University Press. p. 28. ISBN 9781400866328.
  33. ^ Beckwith, Christopher I. (2015). Greek Buddha: Pyrrho's Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia. Princeton University Press. p. 221. ISBN 9781400866328.
  34. ^ Sextus Empricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book 1, Section 19
  35. ^ Hanner, Oren. Buddhism and Scepticism: Historical, Philosophical and Comparative Perspectives. pp. 126–129. ISBN 978-3-89733-518-9.
  36. ^ Jan Westerhoff Nagarjuna's Madhyamaka: A Philosophical Introduction ISBN 0195384962 2009 p93
  37. ^ Thomas McEvilley, The Shape of Ancient Thought 2002 pp499-505
  38. ^ McEvilley, Thomas (2002). The Shape of Ancient Thought. Allworth Communications. ISBN 1-58115-203-5., p.495
  39. ^ Sextus Empiricus, Outlines of Pyrrhonism, II.14–18; Anthologia Palatina (Palatine Anthology), VII. 29–35, and elsewhere
  40. ^ Conze 1959, pp. 140–141
  41. ^ a b Conze (1959: p. 244)
  42. ^ McEvilley, Thomas (2002). The Shape of Ancient Thought. Allworth Communications. ISBN 1-58115-203-5., p. 474
  43. ^ Stephen Batchelor "Greek Buddha: Pyrrho's encounter with early Buddhism in central Asia", Contemporary Buddhism, 2016, pp 195-215
  44. ^ Charles Goodman, "Neither Scythian nor Greek: A Response to Beckwith's Greek Buddha and Kuzminski's "Early Buddhism Reconsidered"", Philosophy East and West, University of Hawai'i Press Volume 68, Number 3, July 2018 pp. 984-1006
  45. ^ says, Unknown. "Greek Buddha: Pyrrho's Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia – Bryn Mawr Classical Review".
  46. ^ Jayatilleke, K.N. Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge. George Allen & Unwin Ltd., London, p. 122.
  47. ^ Barua 1921, p. 299.
  48. ^ Jayatilleke 1963, pp. 129–130.
  49. ^ Flintoff 1980.
  50. ^ Jayatilleke 1963, pp. 130.
  51. ^ a b c d Popkin, Richard Henry (2003). The History of Scepticism : from Savonarola to Bayle (Revised ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 9780198026716. OCLC 65192690.
  52. ^ Sarah Bakewell, How to Live: Or A Life of Montaigne in One Question and Twenty Attempts at an Answer 2011 p 127 ISBN 1590514831
  53. ^ Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion, page 7, section 23.
  54. ^ Friedrich Nietzsche; Maudemarie Clark; Alan J. Swensen (1998). On the Genealogy of Morality. Hackett Publishing. p. 79.
  55. ^ Michael Williams, "Fogelin's Neo-Pyrrhonism", International Journal of Philosophical Studies Volume 7, Issue 2, 1999, p141
  56. ^ Smith, Plínio Junqueira; Bueno, Otávio (7 May 2016). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Skepticism in Latin America. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University – via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

References edit

  • Barua, Benimadhab (1921). A History of Pre-Buddhistic Indian Philosophy (1st ed.). London: University of Calcutta. p. 468.
  • Flintoff, Everard (1980). "Pyrrho and India". Phronesis. 25 (1). Brill: 88–108. doi:10.1163/156852880X00052. JSTOR 4182084.
  • Jayatilleke, K.N. (1963). (PDF) (1st ed.). London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd. p. 524. Archived from the original (PDF) on 11 September 2015.
  • Thorsrud, Harold. "Ancient Greek Skepticism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Vogt, Katja. "Ancient Skepticism". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

External links edit

pyrrhonism, ancient, greek, school, philosophical, skepticism, which, rejects, dogma, advocates, suspension, judgement, over, truth, beliefs, founded, aenesidemus, first, century, said, have, been, inspired, teachings, pyrrho, timon, phlius, fourth, century, b. Pyrrhonism is an Ancient Greek school of philosophical skepticism which rejects dogma and advocates the suspension of judgement over the truth of all beliefs It was founded by Aenesidemus in the first century BCE and said to have been inspired by the teachings of Pyrrho and Timon of Phlius in the fourth century BCE 1 Pyrrhonism is best known today through the surviving works of Sextus Empiricus writing in the late second century or early third century CE 2 The publication of Sextus works in the Renaissance ignited a revival of interest in Skepticism and played a major role in Reformation thought and the development of early modern philosophy Contents 1 History 2 Philosophy 2 1 Modes 2 1 1 The ten modes of Aenesidemus 2 2 The five modes of Agrippa 2 3 Criteria of action 2 4 Skeptic sayings 3 Texts 4 Influence 4 1 In Ancient Greek philosophy 4 2 Similarities between Pyrrhonism and Indian philosophy 4 3 Modern 4 4 Contemporary 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References 8 External linksHistory editPyrrhonism is named after Pyrrho of Elis a Greek philosopher in the 4th century BCE who was credited by the later Pyrrhonists with forming the first comprehensive school of skeptical thought However ancient testimony about the philosophical beliefs of the historical Pyrrho is minimal and often contradictory 1 his teachings were recorded by his student Timon of Phlius but those works have been lost and only survive in fragments quoted by later authors and based on testimonies of later authors such as Cicero Pyrrho s own philosophy as recorded by Timon may have been much more dogmatic than that of the later school who bore his name 1 While Pyrrhonism would become the dominant form of skepticism in the early Roman period in the Hellenistic period the Platonic Academy was the primary advocate of skepticism until the mid first century BCE 3 when Pyrrhonism as a philosophical school was founded by Aenesidemus 1 4 Philosophy editThe goal of Pyrrhonism is ataraxia 5 an untroubled and tranquil condition of soul that results from a suspension of judgement a mental rest owing to which we neither deny nor affirm anything Pyrrhonists dispute that the dogmatists which includes all of Pyrrhonism s rival philosophies claim to have found truth regarding non evident matters and that these opinions about non evident matters i e dogma are what prevent one from attaining eudaimonia For any of these dogmas a Pyrrhonist makes arguments for and against such that the matter cannot be concluded thus suspending judgement and thereby inducing ataraxia Pyrrhonists can be subdivided into those who are ephectic engaged in suspension of judgment aporetic engaged in refutation 6 or zetetic engaged in seeking 7 An ephectic merely suspends judgment on a matter balancing perceptions and thoughts against one another 8 It is a less aggressive form of skepticism in that sometimes suspension of judgment evidently just happens to the sceptic 9 An aporetic skeptic in contrast works more actively towards their goal engaging in the refutation of arguments in favor of various possible beliefs in order to reach aporia an impasse or state of perplexity 10 which leads to suspension of judgement 9 Finally the zetetic claims to be continually searching for the truth but to have thus far been unable to find it and thus continues to suspend belief while also searching for reason to cease the suspension of belief Modes edit Although Pyrrhonism s objective is ataraxia it is best known for its epistemological arguments The core practice is through setting argument against argument To aid in this the Pyrrhonist philosophers Aenesidemus and Agrippa developed sets of stock arguments known as modes or tropes The ten modes of Aenesidemus edit Aenesidemus is considered the creator of the ten tropes of Aenesidemus also known as the ten modes of Aenesidemus although whether he invented the tropes or just systematized them from prior Pyrrhonist works is unknown The tropes represent reasons for suspension of judgment These are as follows 11 Different animals manifest different modes of perception Similar differences are seen among individual men For the same man information perceived with the senses is self contradictory Furthermore it varies from time to time with physical changes In addition this data differs according to local relations Objects are known only indirectly through the medium of air moisture etc These objects are in a condition of perpetual change in colour temperature size and motion All perceptions are relative and interact one upon another Our impressions become less critical through repetition and custom All men are brought up with different beliefs under different laws and social conditions According to Sextus superordinate to these ten modes stand three other modes that based on the subject who judges modes 1 2 3 amp 4 that based on the object judged modes 7 amp 10 that based on both subject who judges and object judged modes 5 6 8 amp 9 and superordinate to these three modes is the mode of relation 12 The five modes of Agrippa edit These tropes or modes are given by Sextus Empiricus in his Outlines of Pyrrhonism According to Sextus they are attributed only to the more recent skeptics and it is by Diogenes Laertius that we attribute them to Agrippa 13 The five tropes of Agrippa are Dissent The uncertainty demonstrated by the differences of opinions among philosophers and people in general Infinite regress All proof rests on matters themselves in need of proof and so on to infinity Relation All things are changed as their relations become changed or as we look upon them from different points of view Assumption The truth asserted is based on an unsupported assumption Circularity The truth asserted involves a circularity of proofs According to the mode deriving from dispute we find that undecidable dissension about the matter proposed has come about both in ordinary life and among philosophers Because of this we are not able to choose or to rule out anything and we end up with suspension of judgement In the mode deriving from infinite regress we say that what is brought forward as a source of conviction for the matter proposed itself needs another such source which itself needs another and so ad infinitum so that we have no point from which to begin to establish anything and suspension of judgement follows In the mode deriving from relativity as we said above the existing object appears to be such and such relative to the subject judging and to the things observed together with it but we suspend judgement on what it is like in its nature We have the mode from hypothesis when the Dogmatists being thrown back ad infinitum begin from something which they do not establish but claim to assume simply and without proof in virtue of a concession The reciprocal mode occurs when what ought to be confirmatory of the object under investigation needs to be made convincing by the object under investigation then being unable to take either in order to establish the other we suspend judgement about both 14 With reference to these five tropes that the first and third are a short summary of the earlier Ten Modes of Aenesidemus 13 The three additional ones show a progress in the Pyrrhonist system building upon the objections derived from the fallibility of sense and opinion to more abstract and metaphysical grounds According to Victor Brochard the five tropes can be regarded as the most radical and most precise formulation of skepticism that has ever been given In a sense they are still irresistible today 15 Criteria of action edit Pyrrhonist decision making is made according to what the Pyrrhonists describe as the criteria of action holding to the appearances without beliefs in accord with the ordinary regimen of life based on the guidance of nature by which we are naturally capable of sensation and thought the compulsion of the passions by which hunger drives us to food and thirst makes us drink the handing down of customs and laws by which we accept that piety in the conduct of life is good and impiety bad instruction in techne 16 Skeptic sayings edit The Pyrrhonists devised several sayings Greek FWNWN to help practitioners bring their minds to suspend judgment 17 Among these are Not more nothing more a saying attributed to Democritus 18 Non assertion aphasia Perhaps it is possible maybe I withhold assent I determine nothing Montaigne created a variant of this as his own personal motto Que sais je what do I know Everything is indeterminate Everything is non apprehensible I do not apprehend To every argument an equal argument is opposedTexts editExcept for the works of Sextus Empiricus the texts of ancient Pyrrhonism have been lost There is a summary of the Pyrrhonian Discourses by Aenesidemus preserved by Photius and a brief summary of Pyrrho s teaching by Aristocles quoting Pyrrho s student Timon preserved by Eusebius The things themselves are equally indifferent and unstable and indeterminate and therefore neither our senses nor our opinions are either true or false For this reason then we must not trust them but be without opinions and without bias and without wavering saying of every single thing that it no more is than is not or both is and is not or neither is nor is not 19 Influence editIn Ancient Greek philosophy edit nbsp Skeptics in Raphael s School of Athens painting Pyrrho is 4 and Timon 5 Pyrrhonism is often contrasted with Academic skepticism a similar but distinct form of Hellenistic philosophical skepticism 9 20 21 While early Academic skepticism was influenced in part by Pyrrho 22 it grew more and more dogmatic until Aenesidemus broke with the Academics to revive Pyrrhonism in the first century BCE denouncing the Academy as Stoics fighting against Stoics 23 Some later Pyrrhonists such as Sextus Empiricus go so far as to claim that Pyrrhonists are the only real skeptics dividing all philosophy into the dogmatists the Academics and the skeptics 20 Dogmatists claim to have knowledge Academic skeptics claim that knowledge is impossible while Pyrrhonists assent to neither proposition suspending judgment on both 9 20 24 The second century Roman historian Aulus Gellius describes the distinction as the Academics apprehend in some sense the very fact that nothing can be apprehended and they determine in some sense that nothing can be determined whereas the Pyrrhonists assert that not even that seems to be true since nothing seems to be true 25 21 Sextus Empiricus also said that the Pyrrhonist school influenced and had substantial overlap with the Empiric school of medicine but that Pyrrhonism had more in common with the Methodic school in that it follow s the appearances and take s from these whatever seems expedient 26 Although Julian the Apostate 27 mentions that Pyrrhonism had died out at the time of his writings other writers mention the existence of later Pyrrhonists Pseudo Clement writing around the same time c 300 320 CE mentions Pyrrhonists in his Homilies 28 and Agathias even reports a Pyrrhonist named Uranius as late as the middle of the 6th century CE 29 Similarities between Pyrrhonism and Indian philosophy edit nbsp Nagarjuna a Madhyamaka Buddhist philosopher whose skeptical arguments are similar to those preserved in the work of Sextus Empiricus According to Diogenes Laertius Pyrrho was said to have traveled to India with Alexander the Great s army where Pyrrho was said to have studied with the magi and the gymnosophists 30 and where he may have been influenced by Buddhist teachings 31 most particularly the three marks of existence 32 Scholars who argue for such influence mention the fact that even the ancient author Diogenesis Laertius states as much when he wrote that Pyrrho foregathered with the Indian Gymnosophists and with the Magi This led him to adopt a most noble philosophy 31 According to Christopher I Beckwith s analysis of the Aristocles Passage adiaphora anatta astathmeta dukkha and anepikrita anicca are strikingly similar to the Buddhist three marks of existence 32 indicating that Pyrrho s teaching is based on Buddhism Beckwith contends that the 18 months Pyrrho spent in India were long enough to learn a foreign language and that the key innovative tenets of Pyrrho s skepticism were only found in Indian philosophy at the time and not in Greece 33 Other similarities between Pyrrhonism and Buddhism include a version of the tetralemma among the Pyrrhonist maxims and more significantly the idea of suspension of judgement and how that can lead to peace and liberation ataraxia in Pyrrhonism and nirvana in Buddhism 34 35 Furthermore Buddhist philosopher Jan Westerhoff says many of Nagarjuna s arguments concerning causation bear strong similarities to classical sceptical arguments as presented in the third book of Sextus Empiricus s Outlines of Pyrrhonism 36 and Thomas McEvilley suspects that Nagarjuna may have been influenced by Greek Pyrrhonist texts imported into India 37 McEvilley argues for mutual iteration in the Buddhist logico epistemological traditions between Pyrrhonism and Madhyamika An extraordinary similarity that has long been noticed between Pyrrhonism and Madhyamika is the formula known in connection with Buddhism as the fourfold negation Catuṣkoṭi and which in Pyrrhonic form might be called the fourfold indeterminacy 38 McEvilley also notes a correspondence between the Pyrrhonist and Madhyamaka views about truth comparing Sextus account 39 of two criteria regarding truth one which judges between reality and unreality and another which we use as a guide in everyday life By the first criteria nothing is either true or false but by the second information from the senses may be considered either true or false for practical purposes As Edward Conze 40 verification needed has noted this is similar to the Madhyamika Two Truths doctrine a distinction between Absolute truth paramarthasatya the knowledge of the real as it is without any distortion 41 and Truth so called saṃvṛti satya truth as conventionally believed in common parlance 41 42 nbsp Map of Alexander the Great s empire and the route he and Pyrrho took to India However other scholars such as Stephen Batchelor 43 and Charles Goodman 44 question Beckwith s conclusions about the degree of Buddhist influence on Pyrrho Conversely while critical of Beckwith s ideas Kuzminsky sees credibility in the hypothesis that Pyrrho was influenced by Buddhism even if it cannot be safely ascertained with our current information 31 While discussing Christopher Beckwith s claims in Greek Buddha Pyrrho s Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia Jerker Blomqvist states that On the other hand certain elements that are generally regarded as essential features of Buddhism are entirely absent from ancient Pyrrhonism scepticism The concepts of good and bad karma must have been an impossibility in the Pyrrhonist universe if things were ἀdiafora without a logical self identity and consequently could not be differentiated from each other by labels such as good and bad or just and unjust A doctrine of rebirth reminiscent of the Buddhist one though favored by Plato and Pythagoras was totally alien to the Pyrrhonists The ἀtara3ia undisturbedness that the Pyrrhonists promised their followers may have a superficial resemblance to the Buddhist nirvana but ἀtara3ia unlike nirvana did not involve a liberation from a cycle of reincarnation rather it was a mode of life in this world blessed with metriopa8eia moderation of feeling or moderate suffering not with the absence of any variety of pain Kuzminski whom Beckwith hails as a precursor of his had largely ignored the problem with this disparity between Buddhism and Pyrrhonism 45 Ajnana which upheld radical skepticism may have been a more powerful influence on Pyrrho than Buddhism The Buddhists referred to Ajnana s adherents as Amaravikkhepikas or eel wrigglers due to their refusal to commit to a single doctrine 46 Scholars including Barua Jayatilleke and Flintoff contend that Pyrrho was influenced by or at the very least agreed with Indian skepticism rather than Buddhism or Jainism based on the fact that he valued ataraxia which can be translated as freedom from worry 47 48 49 Jayatilleke in particular contends that Pyrrho may have been influenced by the first three schools of Ajnana since they too valued freedom from worry 50 Modern edit nbsp Balance scales in equal balance are a modern symbol of Pyrrhonism The recovery and publication of the works of Sextus Empiricus particularly a widely influential translation by Henri Estienne published in 1562 51 ignited a revival of interest in Pyrrhonism 51 Philosophers of the time used his works to source their arguments on how to deal with the religious issues of their day Major philosophers such as Michel de Montaigne Marin Mersenne and Pierre Gassendi later drew on the model of Pyrrhonism outlined in Sextus Empiricus works for their own arguments This resurgence of Pyrrhonism has sometimes been called the beginning of modern philosophy 51 Montaigne adopted the image of a balance scale for his motto 52 which became a modern symbol of Pyrrhonism citation needed It has also been suggested that Pyrrhonism provided the skeptical underpinnings that Rene Descartes drew from in developing his influential method of Cartesian doubt and the associated turn of early modern philosophy towards epistemology 51 In the 18th century David Hume was also considerably influenced by Pyrrhonism using Pyrrhonism as a synonym for skepticism 53 better source needed nbsp Nietzsche was critical of Pyrrhonian ephectics Friedrich Nietzsche however criticized the ephetics of the Pyrrhonists as a flaw of early philosophers who he characterized as shy little blunderer s and milquetoast s with crooked legs prone to overindulging his doubting drive his negating drive his wait and see ephectic drive his analytical drive his exploring searching venturing drive his comparing balancing drive his will to neutrality and objectivity his will to every sine ira et studio have we already grasped that for the longest time they all went against the first demands of morality and conscience 54 Contemporary edit The term neo Pyrrhonism is used to refer to modern Pyrrhonists such as Benson Mates and Robert Fogelin 55 56 See also editAjnana Apophasis Apophatic theology Cognitive closure philosophy Cratylism De Docta Ignorantia Defeatism Quietism Buddhism and the Roman world Greco Buddhism Ancient Greece Ancient India relations E Prime Nassim Nicholas Taleb Trivialism The Hedgehog and the Fox List of unsolved problems in philosophyNotes edit a b c d Long A A 12 September 1996 Hellenistic Philosophy Stoics Epicureans Sceptics Bloomsbury Academic pp 75 76 ISBN 978 0 7156 1238 5 Retrieved 15 January 2023 Popkin Richard Henry 2003 The history of scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle Popkin Richard Henry 1923 Rev and expanded ed Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 0198026714 OCLC 65192690 Thorsrud Harald 2009 Ancient scepticism Stocksfield U K Acumen pp 120 121 ISBN 978 1 84465 409 3 OCLC 715184861 Pyrrhonism in whatever form it might have taken after Timon s death in 230 BCE was utterly neglected until Aenesidemus brought it back to public attention Stephane Marchand Sextus Empiricus Style Of Writing in New Essays on Ancient Pyrrhonism p 113 Warren James 2002 Epicurus and Democritean ethics An archaeology of ataraxia Cambridge University Press p I ISBN 0521813697 Pulleyn William 1830 The Etymological Compendium Or Portfolio of Origins and Inventions T Tegg pp 353 Bett Richard Arnot Home 28 January 2010 The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism Cambridge University Press p 212 Bett Richard Arnot Home 28 January 2010 The Cambridge Companion to Ancient Scepticism Cambridge University Press p 213 a b c d Klein Peter 2015 Skepticism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Archived from the original on 25 July 2018 Retrieved 19 March 2021 McInerny Ralph 1969 A History of Western Philosophy Volume 2 Aeterna Press pp Chp III Skeptics and the New Academy A Pyrrho of Elis section para 3 4 nbsp One or more of the preceding sentences incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Chisholm Hugh ed 1911 Aenesidemus Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 1 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 257 258 Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism Trans R G Bury Harvard University Press Cambridge Massachusetts 1933 pp 25 27 a b Diogenes Laertius ix Sextus Empiricus Pyrrhōneioi hypotypōseis i from Annas J Outlines of Scepticism Cambridge University Press 2000 Brochard V The Greek Skeptics Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book I Chapter 11 Section 23 Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book I Chapter 18 Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book II Chapter 30 Eusebius Praeparatio Evangelica Book XIV Tertullian Project Retrieved 27 January 2023 a b c Sextus Empiricus 1990 Outlines of pyrrhonism Robert Gregg Bury Buffalo N Y Prometheus Books ISBN 0 87975 597 0 OCLC 23367477 a b Thorsrud Harald 2009 Ancient scepticism Stocksfield U K Acumen ISBN 978 1 84465 409 3 OCLC 715184861 Thorsrud Harald 2009 Ancient scepticism Stocksfield U K Acumen p 45 ISBN 978 1 84465 409 3 OCLC 715184861 Thorsrud Harald 2009 Ancient scepticism Stocksfield U K Acumen pp 102 103 ISBN 978 1 84465 409 3 OCLC 715184861 Aenesidemus criticized his fellow Academics for being dogmatic Aenesidemus committed his scepticism to writing probably some time in the early to mid first century BCE leading Aenesidemus to dismiss them as Stoics fighting against Stoics Popkin Richard 1995 The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy Robert Audi Cambridge p 741 ISBN 0 521 40224 7 OCLC 32272442 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link Gellius Aulus 2008 Noctes Atticae Josef Feix 3 Dr ed Paderborn Schoningh ISBN 978 3 14 010714 3 OCLC 635311697 Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism I 237 trans Etheridge Scepticism Man and God Wesleyan University Press 1964 p 98 Epistles lxxxix 301C Pseudo Clement Homilies 13 7 Agathias II 29 32 cited in Jonathan Barnes Mantissa 2015 p 652 Diogenes Laertius Lives of Eminent Philosophers Book IX Chapter 11 PYRRHO c 360 270 b c www perseus tufts edu a b c Kuzminski Adrian 2021 Pyrrhonian Buddhism A Philosophical Reconstruction Routledge ISBN 9781000350074 a b Beckwith Christopher I 2015 Greek Buddha Pyrrho s Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia PDF Princeton University Press p 28 ISBN 9781400866328 Beckwith Christopher I 2015 Greek Buddha Pyrrho s Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia Princeton University Press p 221 ISBN 9781400866328 Sextus Empricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism Book 1 Section 19 Hanner Oren Buddhism and Scepticism Historical Philosophical and Comparative Perspectives pp 126 129 ISBN 978 3 89733 518 9 Jan Westerhoff Nagarjuna s Madhyamaka A Philosophical Introduction ISBN 0195384962 2009 p93 Thomas McEvilley The Shape of Ancient Thought 2002 pp499 505 McEvilley Thomas 2002 The Shape of Ancient Thought Allworth Communications ISBN 1 58115 203 5 p 495 Sextus Empiricus Outlines of Pyrrhonism II 14 18 Anthologia Palatina Palatine Anthology VII 29 35 and elsewhere Conze 1959 pp 140 141 a b Conze 1959 p 244 McEvilley Thomas 2002 The Shape of Ancient Thought Allworth Communications ISBN 1 58115 203 5 p 474 Stephen Batchelor Greek Buddha Pyrrho s encounter with early Buddhism in central Asia Contemporary Buddhism 2016 pp 195 215 Charles Goodman Neither Scythian nor Greek A Response to Beckwith s Greek Buddha and Kuzminski s Early Buddhism Reconsidered Philosophy East and West University of Hawai i Press Volume 68 Number 3 July 2018 pp 984 1006 says Unknown Greek Buddha Pyrrho s Encounter with Early Buddhism in Central Asia Bryn Mawr Classical Review Jayatilleke K N Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge George Allen amp Unwin Ltd London p 122 Barua 1921 p 299 Jayatilleke 1963 pp 129 130 Flintoff 1980 Jayatilleke 1963 pp 130 a b c d Popkin Richard Henry 2003 The History of Scepticism from Savonarola to Bayle Revised ed Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 9780198026716 OCLC 65192690 Sarah Bakewell How to Live Or A Life of Montaigne in One Question and Twenty Attempts at an Answer 2011 p 127 ISBN 1590514831 Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion page 7 section 23 Friedrich Nietzsche Maudemarie Clark Alan J Swensen 1998 On the Genealogy of Morality Hackett Publishing p 79 Michael Williams Fogelin s Neo Pyrrhonism International Journal of Philosophical Studies Volume 7 Issue 2 1999 p141 Smith Plinio Junqueira Bueno Otavio 7 May 2016 Zalta Edward N ed Skepticism in Latin America Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University via Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy References editBarua Benimadhab 1921 A History of Pre Buddhistic Indian Philosophy 1st ed London University of Calcutta p 468 Flintoff Everard 1980 Pyrrho and India Phronesis 25 1 Brill 88 108 doi 10 1163 156852880X00052 JSTOR 4182084 Jayatilleke K N 1963 Early Buddhist Theory of Knowledge PDF 1st ed London George Allen amp Unwin Ltd p 524 Archived from the original PDF on 11 September 2015 Thorsrud Harold Ancient Greek Skepticism Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Vogt Katja Ancient Skepticism In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy External links edit nbsp Wikimedia Commons has media related to Pyrrhonism Pyrrhonian Skepticism at PhilPapers Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Pyrrhonism amp oldid 1209169528, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.