fbpx
Wikipedia

Categorical proposition

In logic, a categorical proposition, or categorical statement, is a proposition that asserts or denies that all or some of the members of one category (the subject term) are included in another (the predicate term).[1] The study of arguments using categorical statements (i.e., syllogisms) forms an important branch of deductive reasoning that began with the Ancient Greeks.

The Ancient Greeks such as Aristotle identified four primary distinct types of categorical proposition and gave them standard forms (now often called A, E, I, and O). If, abstractly, the subject category is named S and the predicate category is named P, the four standard forms are:

  • All S are P. (A form, )
  • No S are P. (E form, )
  • Some S are P. (I form, )
  • Some S are not P. (O form, )

Surprisingly, a large number of sentences may be translated into one of these canonical forms while retaining all or most of the original meaning of the sentence. Greek investigations resulted in the so-called square of opposition, which codifies the logical relations among the different forms; for example, that an A-statement is contradictory to an O-statement; that is to say, for example, if one believes "All apples are red fruits," one cannot simultaneously believe that "Some apples are not red fruits." Thus the relationships of the square of opposition may allow immediate inference, whereby the truth or falsity of one of the forms may follow directly from the truth or falsity of a statement in another form.

Modern understanding of categorical propositions (originating with the mid-19th century work of George Boole) requires one to consider if the subject category may be empty. If so, this is called the hypothetical viewpoint, in opposition to the existential viewpoint which requires the subject category to have at least one member. The existential viewpoint is a stronger stance than the hypothetical and, when it is appropriate to take, it allows one to deduce more results than otherwise could be made. The hypothetical viewpoint, being the weaker view, has the effect of removing some of the relations present in the traditional square of opposition.

Arguments consisting of three categorical propositions — two as premises and one as conclusion — are known as categorical syllogisms and were of paramount importance from the times of ancient Greek logicians through the Middle Ages. Although formal arguments using categorical syllogisms have largely given way to the increased expressive power of modern logic systems like the first-order predicate calculus, they still retain practical value in addition to their historic and pedagogical significance.

Translating statements into standard form

Sentences in natural language may be translated into standard forms. In each row of the following chart, S corresponds to the subject of the example sentence, and P corresponds to the predicate.

Name English Sentence Standard Form
A All cats have four legs. All S is P.
E No cats have eight legs. No S is P.
I Some cats are orange. Some S is P.
O Some cats are not black. Some S is not P.

Note that "All S is not P" (e.g., "All cats do not have eight legs") is not classified as an example of the standard forms. This is because the translation to natural language is ambiguous. In common speech, the sentence "All cats do not have eight legs" could be used informally to indicate either (1) "At least some, and perhaps all, cats do not have eight legs" or (2) "No cats have eight legs".

Properties of categorical propositions

Categorical propositions can be categorized into four types on the basis of their "quality" and "quantity", or their "distribution of terms". These four types have long been named A, E, I, and O. This is based on the Latin affirmo (I affirm), referring to the affirmative propositions A and I, and nego (I deny), referring to the negative propositions E and O.[2]

Quantity and quality

Quantity refers to the number of members of the subject class (A class is a collection or group of things designated by a term that is either subject or predicate in a categorical proposition.[3]) that are used in the proposition. If the proposition refers to all members of the subject class, it is universal. If the proposition does not employ all members of the subject class, it is particular. For instance, an I-proposition ("Some S is P") is particular since it only refers to some of the members of the subject class.

Quality It is described as whether the proposition affirms or denies the inclusion of a subject within the class of the predicate. The two possible qualities are called affirmative and negative.[4] For instance, an A-proposition ("All S is P") is affirmative since it states that the subject is contained within the predicate. On the other hand, an O-proposition ("Some S is not P") is negative since it excludes the subject from the predicate.

The Four Aristotelian Propositions
Name Statement Quantity Quality
A All S is P. universal affirmative
E No S is P. universal negative
I Some S is P. particular affirmative
O Some S is not P. particular negative

An important consideration is the definition of the word some. In logic, some refers to "one or more", which is consistent with "all". Therefore, the statement "Some S is P" does not guarantee that the statement "Some S is not P" is also true.

Distributivity

The two terms (subject and predicate) in a categorical proposition may each be classified as distributed or undistributed. If all members of the term's class are affected by the proposition, that class is distributed; otherwise it is undistributed. Every proposition therefore has one of four possible distribution of terms.

Each of the four canonical forms will be examined in turn regarding its distribution of terms. Although not developed here, Venn diagrams are sometimes helpful when trying to understand the distribution of terms for the four forms.

A form

An A-proposition distributes the subject to the predicate, but not the reverse. Consider the following categorical proposition: "All dogs are mammals". All dogs are indeed mammals, but it would be false to say all mammals are dogs. Since all dogs are included in the class of mammals, "dogs" is said to be distributed to "mammals". Since all mammals are not necessarily dogs, "mammals" is undistributed to "dogs".

E form

An E-proposition distributes bidirectionally between the subject and predicate. From the categorical proposition "No beetles are mammals", we can infer that no mammals are beetles. Since all beetles are defined not to be mammals, and all mammals are defined not to be beetles, both classes are distributed.

The empty set is a particular case of subject and predicate class distribution.

I form

Both terms in an I-proposition are undistributed. For example, "Some Americans are conservatives". Neither term can be entirely distributed to the other. From this proposition, it is not possible to say that all Americans are conservatives or that all conservatives are Americans. Note the ambiguity in the statement: It could either mean that "Some Americans (or other) are conservatives" (de dicto), or it could mean that "Some Americans (in particular, Albert and Bob) are conservatives" (de re).

O form

In an O-proposition, only the predicate is distributed. Consider the following: "Some politicians are not corrupt". Since not all politicians are defined by this rule, the subject is undistributed. The predicate, though, is distributed because all the members of "corrupt people" will not match the group of people defined as "some politicians". Since the rule applies to every member of the corrupt people group, namely, "All corrupt people are not some politicians", the predicate is distributed.

The distribution of the predicate in an O-proposition is often confusing due to its ambiguity. When a statement such as "Some politicians are not corrupt" is said to distribute the "corrupt people" group to "some politicians", the information seems of little value, since the group "some politicians" is not defined; This is the de dicto interpretation of the intensional statement ( ), or "Some politicians (or other) are not corrupt". But if, as an example, this group of "some politicians" were defined to contain a single person, Albert, the relationship becomes clearer; This is the de re interpretation of the intensional statement ( ), or "Some politicians (in particular) are not corrupt". The statement would then mean that, of every entry listed in the corrupt people group, not one of them will be Albert: "All corrupt people are not Albert". This is a definition that applies to every member of the "corrupt people" group, and is, therefore, distributed.

Summary

In short, for the subject to be distributed, the statement must be universal (e.g., "all", "no"). For the predicate to be distributed, the statement must be negative (e.g., "no", "not").[5]

Name Statement Distribution
Subject Predicate
A All S is P. distributed undistributed
E No S is P. distributed distributed
I Some S is P. undistributed undistributed
O Some S is not P. undistributed distributed

Criticism

Peter Geach and others have criticized the use of distribution to determine the validity of an argument.[6][7]

It has been suggested that statements of the form "Some A are not B" would be less problematic if stated as "Not every A is B,"[8] which is perhaps a closer translation to Aristotle's original form for this type of statement.[9]

Operations on categorical statements

There are several operations (e.g., conversion, obversion, and contraposition) that can be performed on a categorical statement to change it into another. The new statement may or may not be equivalent to the original. [In the following tables that illustrate such operations, at each row, boxes are green if statements in one green box are equivalent to statements in another green box, boxes are red if statements in one red box are inequivalent to statements in another red box. Statements in a yellow box means that these are implied or valid by the statement in the left-most box when the condition stated in the same yellow box is satisfied.]

Some operations require the notion of the class complement. This refers to every element under consideration which is not an element of the class. Class complements are very similar to set complements. The class complement of a set P will be called "non-P".

Conversion

The simplest operation is conversion where the subject and predicate terms are interchanged. Note that this is not same to the implicational converse in the modern logic where a material implication statement   is converted (conversion) to another material implication statement  . The both conversions are equivalent only for A type categorical statements.

Name Statement Converse / Obverted Converse Subaltern / Obverted Subaltern / Condition of Validity Converse per accidens / Obverted Converse per accidens / Condition of Validity
A All S is P. All P is S.
No P is non-S.
Some S is P.
Some S is not non-P.
(if S exists)
Some P is S.
Some P is not non-S.
(if S exists)
E No S is P. No P is S.
All P is non-S.
Some S is not P.
Some S is non-P.
(if S exists)
Some P is not S.
Some P is non-S.
(if P exists)
I Some S is P. Some P is S.
Some P is not non-S.
O Some S is not P. Some P is not S.
Some P is non-S.

From a statement in E or I form, it is valid to conclude its converse (as they are equivalent). This is not the case for the A and O forms.

Obversion

Obversion changes the quality (that is the affirmativity or negativity) of the statement and the predicate term.[10] For example, by obversion, a universal affirmative statement become a universal negative statement with the predicate term that is the class complement of the predicate term of the original universal affirmative statement. In the modern forms of the four categorical statements, the negation of the statement corresponding to a predicate term P,  , is interpreted as a predicate term 'non-P' in each categorical statement in obversion. The equality of   can be used to obvert affirmative categorical statements.

Name Statement Obverse (obverted)
A All S is P. No S is non-P.
E No S is P. All S is non-P.
I Some S is P. Some S is not non-P.
O Some S is not P. Some S is non-P.

Categorical statements are logically equivalent to their obverse. As such, a Venn diagram illustrating any one of the forms would be identical to the Venn diagram illustrating its obverse.

Contraposition

Contraposition is the process of simultaneous interchange and negation of the subject and predicate of a categorical statement. It is also equivalent to converting (applying conversion) the obvert (the outcome of obversion) of a categorical statement. Note that this contraposition in the traditional logic is not same to contraposition (also called transposition) in the modern logic stating that material implication statements   and   are logically equivalent. The both contrapositions are equivalent only for A type categorical statements.

Name Statement Contrapositive / Obverted Contrapositive Contrapositive per accidens / Obverted Contrapositive per accidens / Condition of Validity
A All S is P. All non-P is non-S.
No non-P is S.
Some non-P is non-S.
Some non-P is not S.
(if non-P exists)
E No S is P. No non-P is non-S.
All non-P is S.
Some non-P is not non-S.
Some non-P is S.
(if S exists)
I Some S is P. Some non-P is non-S.
Some non-P is not S.
O Some S is not P. Some non-P is not non-S.
Some non-P is S.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Churchill, Robert Paul (1990). Logic: An Introduction (2nd ed.). New York: St. Martin's Press. p. 143. ISBN 0-312-02353-7. OCLC 21216829. A categorical statement is an assertion or a denial that all or some members of the subject class are included in the predicate class.
  2. ^ Churchill, Robert Paul (1990). Logic: An Introduction (2nd ed.). New York: St. Martin's Press. p. 144. ISBN 0-312-02353-7. OCLC 21216829. During the Middle Ages, logicians gave the four categorical forms the special names of A, E, I, and O. These four letters came from the first two vowels in the Latin word 'affirmo' ('I affirm') and the vowels in the Latin 'nego' ('I deny').
  3. ^ "Dictionary". Philosophy Pages. 2021-08-25. from the original on 2001-02-09.
  4. ^ Copi, Irving M.; Cohen, Carl (2002). Introduction to Logic (11th ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice-Hall. p. 185. ISBN 0-13-033735-8. Every standard-form categorical proposition is said to have a quality, either affirmative or negative.
  5. ^ Damer 2008, p. 82.
  6. ^ Lagerlund, Henrik (January 21, 2010). "Medieval Theories of the Syllogism". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2010-12-10.
  7. ^ Murphree, Wallace A. (Summer 1994). "The Irrelevance of Distribution for the Syllogism". Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic. 35 (3): 433–449. doi:10.1305/ndjfl/1040511349.
  8. ^ Geach 1980, pp. 62–64.
  9. ^ Parsons, Terence (2006-10-01). "The Traditional Square of Opposition". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2010-12-10.
  10. ^ Hausman, Alan; Kahane, Howard; Tidman, Paul (2010). Logic and Philosophy: A Modern Introduction (11th ed.). Australia: Thomson Wadsworth/Cengage learning. p. 326. ISBN 9780495601586. Retrieved 26 February 2013. In the process of obversion, we change the quality of a proposition (from affirmative to negative or from negative to affirmative), and then replace its predicate with the negation or complement of the predicate.

References

External links

  • ChangingMinds.org: Categorical propositions
  • Catlogic: An open source computer script written in Ruby to construct, investigate, and compute categorical propositions and syllogisms

categorical, proposition, this, article, needs, additional, citations, verification, please, help, improve, this, article, adding, citations, reliable, sources, unsourced, material, challenged, removed, find, sources, news, newspapers, books, scholar, jstor, f. This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Categorical proposition news newspapers books scholar JSTOR February 2013 Learn how and when to remove this template message In logic a categorical proposition or categorical statement is a proposition that asserts or denies that all or some of the members of one category the subject term are included in another the predicate term 1 The study of arguments using categorical statements i e syllogisms forms an important branch of deductive reasoning that began with the Ancient Greeks The Ancient Greeks such as Aristotle identified four primary distinct types of categorical proposition and gave them standard forms now often called A E I and O If abstractly the subject category is named S and the predicate category is named P the four standard forms are All S are P A form x S x P x x S x P x displaystyle forall x S x rightarrow P x equiv forall x neg S x lor P x No S are P E form x S x P x x S x P x displaystyle forall x S x rightarrow neg P x equiv forall x neg S x lor neg P x Some S are P I form x S x P x displaystyle exists x S x land P x Some S are not P O form x S x P x displaystyle exists x S x land neg P x Surprisingly a large number of sentences may be translated into one of these canonical forms while retaining all or most of the original meaning of the sentence Greek investigations resulted in the so called square of opposition which codifies the logical relations among the different forms for example that an A statement is contradictory to an O statement that is to say for example if one believes All apples are red fruits one cannot simultaneously believe that Some apples are not red fruits Thus the relationships of the square of opposition may allow immediate inference whereby the truth or falsity of one of the forms may follow directly from the truth or falsity of a statement in another form Modern understanding of categorical propositions originating with the mid 19th century work of George Boole requires one to consider if the subject category may be empty If so this is called the hypothetical viewpoint in opposition to the existential viewpoint which requires the subject category to have at least one member The existential viewpoint is a stronger stance than the hypothetical and when it is appropriate to take it allows one to deduce more results than otherwise could be made The hypothetical viewpoint being the weaker view has the effect of removing some of the relations present in the traditional square of opposition Arguments consisting of three categorical propositions two as premises and one as conclusion are known as categorical syllogisms and were of paramount importance from the times of ancient Greek logicians through the Middle Ages Although formal arguments using categorical syllogisms have largely given way to the increased expressive power of modern logic systems like the first order predicate calculus they still retain practical value in addition to their historic and pedagogical significance Contents 1 Translating statements into standard form 2 Properties of categorical propositions 2 1 Quantity and quality 2 2 Distributivity 2 2 1 A form 2 2 2 E form 2 2 3 I form 2 2 4 O form 2 2 5 Summary 2 2 6 Criticism 3 Operations on categorical statements 3 1 Conversion 3 2 Obversion 3 3 Contraposition 4 See also 5 Notes 6 References 7 External linksTranslating statements into standard form EditSentences in natural language may be translated into standard forms In each row of the following chart S corresponds to the subject of the example sentence and P corresponds to the predicate Name English Sentence Standard FormA All cats have four legs All S is P E No cats have eight legs No S is P I Some cats are orange Some S is P O Some cats are not black Some S is not P Note that All S is not P e g All cats do not have eight legs is not classified as an example of the standard forms This is because the translation to natural language is ambiguous In common speech the sentence All cats do not have eight legs could be used informally to indicate either 1 At least some and perhaps all cats do not have eight legs or 2 No cats have eight legs Properties of categorical propositions EditCategorical propositions can be categorized into four types on the basis of their quality and quantity or their distribution of terms These four types have long been named A E I and O This is based on the Latin affirmo I affirm referring to the affirmative propositions A and I and nego I deny referring to the negative propositions E and O 2 Quantity and quality Edit Quantity refers to the number of members of the subject class A class is a collection or group of things designated by a term that is either subject or predicate in a categorical proposition 3 that are used in the proposition If the proposition refers to all members of the subject class it is universal If the proposition does not employ all members of the subject class it is particular For instance an I proposition Some S is P is particular since it only refers to some of the members of the subject class Quality It is described as whether the proposition affirms or denies the inclusion of a subject within the class of the predicate The two possible qualities are called affirmative and negative 4 For instance an A proposition All S is P is affirmative since it states that the subject is contained within the predicate On the other hand an O proposition Some S is not P is negative since it excludes the subject from the predicate The Four Aristotelian Propositions Name Statement Quantity QualityA All S is P universal affirmativeE No S is P universal negativeI Some S is P particular affirmativeO Some S is not P particular negativeAn important consideration is the definition of the word some In logic some refers to one or more which is consistent with all Therefore the statement Some S is P does not guarantee that the statement Some S is not P is also true Distributivity Edit The two terms subject and predicate in a categorical proposition may each be classified as distributed or undistributed If all members of the term s class are affected by the proposition that class is distributed otherwise it is undistributed Every proposition therefore has one of four possible distribution of terms Each of the four canonical forms will be examined in turn regarding its distribution of terms Although not developed here Venn diagrams are sometimes helpful when trying to understand the distribution of terms for the four forms A form Edit An A proposition distributes the subject to the predicate but not the reverse Consider the following categorical proposition All dogs are mammals All dogs are indeed mammals but it would be false to say all mammals are dogs Since all dogs are included in the class of mammals dogs is said to be distributed to mammals Since all mammals are not necessarily dogs mammals is undistributed to dogs E form Edit An E proposition distributes bidirectionally between the subject and predicate From the categorical proposition No beetles are mammals we can infer that no mammals are beetles Since all beetles are defined not to be mammals and all mammals are defined not to be beetles both classes are distributed The empty set is a particular case of subject and predicate class distribution I form Edit Both terms in an I proposition are undistributed For example Some Americans are conservatives Neither term can be entirely distributed to the other From this proposition it is not possible to say that all Americans are conservatives or that all conservatives are Americans Note the ambiguity in the statement It could either mean that Some Americans or other are conservatives de dicto or it could mean that Some Americans in particular Albert and Bob are conservatives de re O form Edit In an O proposition only the predicate is distributed Consider the following Some politicians are not corrupt Since not all politicians are defined by this rule the subject is undistributed The predicate though is distributed because all the members of corrupt people will not match the group of people defined as some politicians Since the rule applies to every member of the corrupt people group namely All corrupt people are not some politicians the predicate is distributed The distribution of the predicate in an O proposition is often confusing due to its ambiguity When a statement such as Some politicians are not corrupt is said to distribute the corrupt people group to some politicians the information seems of little value since the group some politicians is not defined This is the de dicto interpretation of the intensional statement x P l x C x displaystyle Box exists x Pl x land neg C x or Some politicians or other are not corrupt But if as an example this group of some politicians were defined to contain a single person Albert the relationship becomes clearer This is the de re interpretation of the intensional statement x P l x C x displaystyle exists x Box Pl x land neg C x or Some politicians in particular are not corrupt The statement would then mean that of every entry listed in the corrupt people group not one of them will be Albert All corrupt people are not Albert This is a definition that applies to every member of the corrupt people group and is therefore distributed Summary Edit In short for the subject to be distributed the statement must be universal e g all no For the predicate to be distributed the statement must be negative e g no not 5 Name Statement DistributionSubject PredicateA All S is P distributed undistributedE No S is P distributed distributedI Some S is P undistributed undistributedO Some S is not P undistributed distributedCriticism Edit Peter Geach and others have criticized the use of distribution to determine the validity of an argument 6 7 It has been suggested that statements of the form Some A are not B would be less problematic if stated as Not every A is B 8 which is perhaps a closer translation to Aristotle s original form for this type of statement 9 Operations on categorical statements EditThere are several operations e g conversion obversion and contraposition that can be performed on a categorical statement to change it into another The new statement may or may not be equivalent to the original In the following tables that illustrate such operations at each row boxes are green if statements in one green box are equivalent to statements in another green box boxes are red if statements in one red box are inequivalent to statements in another red box Statements in a yellow box means that these are implied or valid by the statement in the left most box when the condition stated in the same yellow box is satisfied Some operations require the notion of the class complement This refers to every element under consideration which is not an element of the class Class complements are very similar to set complements The class complement of a set P will be called non P Conversion Edit Main article Logical conversion The simplest operation is conversion where the subject and predicate terms are interchanged Note that this is not same to the implicational converse in the modern logic where a material implication statement P Q displaystyle P rightarrow Q is converted conversion to another material implication statement Q P displaystyle Q rightarrow P The both conversions are equivalent only for A type categorical statements Name Statement Converse Obverted Converse Subaltern Obverted Subaltern Condition of Validity Converse per accidens Obverted Converse per accidens Condition of ValidityA All S is P All P is S No P is non S Some S is P Some S is not non P if S exists Some P is S Some P is not non S if S exists E No S is P No P is S All P is non S Some S is not P Some S is non P if S exists Some P is not S Some P is non S if P exists I Some S is P Some P is S Some P is not non S O Some S is not P Some P is not S Some P is non S From a statement in E or I form it is valid to conclude its converse as they are equivalent This is not the case for the A and O forms Obversion Edit Main article Obversion Obversion changes the quality that is the affirmativity or negativity of the statement and the predicate term 10 For example by obversion a universal affirmative statement become a universal negative statement with the predicate term that is the class complement of the predicate term of the original universal affirmative statement In the modern forms of the four categorical statements the negation of the statement corresponding to a predicate term P P x displaystyle neg Px is interpreted as a predicate term non P in each categorical statement in obversion The equality of P x P x displaystyle Px neg neg Px can be used to obvert affirmative categorical statements Name Statement Obverse obverted A All S is P No S is non P E No S is P All S is non P I Some S is P Some S is not non P O Some S is not P Some S is non P Categorical statements are logically equivalent to their obverse As such a Venn diagram illustrating any one of the forms would be identical to the Venn diagram illustrating its obverse Contraposition Edit Main article Contraposition traditional logic Contraposition is the process of simultaneous interchange and negation of the subject and predicate of a categorical statement It is also equivalent to converting applying conversion the obvert the outcome of obversion of a categorical statement Note that this contraposition in the traditional logic is not same to contraposition also called transposition in the modern logic stating that material implication statements P Q displaystyle P rightarrow Q and Q P displaystyle neg Q rightarrow neg P are logically equivalent The both contrapositions are equivalent only for A type categorical statements Name Statement Contrapositive Obverted Contrapositive Contrapositive per accidens Obverted Contrapositive per accidens Condition of ValidityA All S is P All non P is non S No non P is S Some non P is non S Some non P is not S if non P exists E No S is P No non P is non S All non P is S Some non P is not non S Some non P is S if S exists I Some S is P Some non P is non S Some non P is not S O Some S is not P Some non P is not non S Some non P is S See also EditSquare of opposition Term logicNotes Edit Churchill Robert Paul 1990 Logic An Introduction 2nd ed New York St Martin s Press p 143 ISBN 0 312 02353 7 OCLC 21216829 A categorical statement is an assertion or a denial that all or some members of the subject class are included in the predicate class Churchill Robert Paul 1990 Logic An Introduction 2nd ed New York St Martin s Press p 144 ISBN 0 312 02353 7 OCLC 21216829 During the Middle Ages logicians gave the four categorical forms the special names of A E I and O These four letters came from the first two vowels in the Latin word affirmo I affirm and the vowels in the Latin nego I deny Dictionary Philosophy Pages 2021 08 25 Archived from the original on 2001 02 09 Copi Irving M Cohen Carl 2002 Introduction to Logic 11th ed Upper Saddle River NJ Prentice Hall p 185 ISBN 0 13 033735 8 Every standard form categorical proposition is said to have a quality either affirmative or negative Damer 2008 p 82 Lagerlund Henrik January 21 2010 Medieval Theories of the Syllogism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2010 12 10 Murphree Wallace A Summer 1994 The Irrelevance of Distribution for the Syllogism Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic 35 3 433 449 doi 10 1305 ndjfl 1040511349 Geach 1980 pp 62 64 Parsons Terence 2006 10 01 The Traditional Square of Opposition Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2010 12 10 Hausman Alan Kahane Howard Tidman Paul 2010 Logic and Philosophy A Modern Introduction 11th ed Australia Thomson Wadsworth Cengage learning p 326 ISBN 9780495601586 Retrieved 26 February 2013 In the process of obversion we change the quality of a proposition from affirmative to negative or from negative to affirmative and then replace its predicate with the negation or complement of the predicate References EditCopi Irving M Cohen Carl 2009 Introduction to Logic Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0 13 136419 6 Damer T Edward 2008 Attacking Faulty Reasoning Cengage Learning ISBN 978 0 495 09506 4 Geach Peter 1980 Logic Matters University of California Press ISBN 978 0 520 03847 9 Baum Robert 1989 Logic Holt Rinehart and Winston Inc ISBN 0 03 014078 1 External links EditChangingMinds org Categorical propositions Catlogic An open source computer script written in Ruby to construct investigate and compute categorical propositions and syllogisms Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Categorical proposition amp oldid 1112687652, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.