fbpx
Wikipedia

Join and meet

In mathematics, specifically order theory, the join of a subset of a partially ordered set is the supremum (least upper bound) of denoted and similarly, the meet of is the infimum (greatest lower bound), denoted In general, the join and meet of a subset of a partially ordered set need not exist. Join and meet are dual to one another with respect to order inversion.

This Hasse diagram depicts a partially ordered set with four elements: a, b, the maximal element a b equal to the join of a and b, and the minimal element a b equal to the meet of a and b. The join/meet of a maximal/minimal element and another element is the maximal/minimal element and conversely the meet/join of a maximal/minimal element with another element is the other element. Thus every pair in this poset has both a meet and a join and the poset can be classified as a lattice.

A partially ordered set in which all pairs have a join is a join-semilattice. Dually, a partially ordered set in which all pairs have a meet is a meet-semilattice. A partially ordered set that is both a join-semilattice and a meet-semilattice is a lattice. A lattice in which every subset, not just every pair, possesses a meet and a join is a complete lattice. It is also possible to define a partial lattice, in which not all pairs have a meet or join but the operations (when defined) satisfy certain axioms.[1]

The join/meet of a subset of a totally ordered set is simply the maximal/minimal element of that subset, if such an element exists.

If a subset of a partially ordered set is also an (upward) directed set, then its join (if it exists) is called a directed join or directed supremum. Dually, if is a downward directed set, then its meet (if it exists) is a directed meet or directed infimum.

Definitions

Partial order approach

Let   be a set with a partial order   and let   An element   of   is called the meet (or greatest lower bound or infimum) of   and is denoted by   if the following two conditions are satisfied:

  1.   (that is,   is a lower bound of  ).
  2. For any   if   then   (that is,   is greater than or equal to any other lower bound of  ).

The meet need not exist, either since the pair has no lower bound at all, or since none of the lower bounds is greater than all the others. However, if there is a meet of   then it is unique, since if both   are greatest lower bounds of   then   and thus  [2] If not all pairs of elements from   have a meet, then the meet can still be seen as a partial binary operation on  [1]

If the meet does exist then it is denoted   If all pairs of elements from   have a meet, then the meet is a binary operation on   and it is easy to see that this operation fulfills the following three conditions: For any elements  

  1.   (commutativity),
  2.   (associativity), and
  3.   (idempotency).

Joins are defined dually with the join of   if it exists, denoted by   An element   of   is the join (or least upper bound or supremum) of   in   if the following two conditions are satisfied:

  1.   (that is,   is an upper bound of  ).
  2. For any   if   then   (that is,   is less than or equal to any other upper bound of  ).

Universal algebra approach

By definition, a binary operation   on a set   is a meet if it satisfies the three conditions a, b, and c. The pair   is then a meet-semilattice. Moreover, we then may define a binary relation   on A, by stating that   if and only if   In fact, this relation is a partial order on   Indeed, for any elements  

  •   since   by c;
  • if   then   by a; and
  • if   then   since then   by b.

Both meets and joins equally satisfy this definition: a couple of associated meet and join operations yield partial orders which are the reverse of each other. When choosing one of these orders as the main ones, one also fixes which operation is considered a meet (the one giving the same order) and which is considered a join (the other one).

Equivalence of approaches

If   is a partially ordered set, such that each pair of elements in   has a meet, then indeed   if and only if   since in the latter case indeed   is a lower bound of   and since   is the greatest lower bound if and only if it is a lower bound. Thus, the partial order defined by the meet in the universal algebra approach coincides with the original partial order.

Conversely, if   is a meet-semilattice, and the partial order   is defined as in the universal algebra approach, and   for some elements   then   is the greatest lower bound of   with respect to   since

 
and therefore   Similarly,   and if   is another lower bound of   then   whence
 
Thus, there is a meet defined by the partial order defined by the original meet, and the two meets coincide.

In other words, the two approaches yield essentially equivalent concepts, a set equipped with both a binary relation and a binary operation, such that each one of these structures determines the other, and fulfill the conditions for partial orders or meets, respectively.

Meets of general subsets

If   is a meet-semilattice, then the meet may be extended to a well-defined meet of any non-empty finite set, by the technique described in iterated binary operations. Alternatively, if the meet defines or is defined by a partial order, some subsets of   indeed have infima with respect to this, and it is reasonable to consider such an infimum as the meet of the subset. For non-empty finite subsets, the two approaches yield the same result, and so either may be taken as a definition of meet. In the case where each subset of   has a meet, in fact   is a complete lattice; for details, see completeness (order theory).

Examples

If some power set   is partially ordered in the usual way (by  ) then joins are unions and meets are intersections; in symbols,   (where the similarity of these symbols may be used as a mnemonic for remembering that   denotes the join/supremum and   denotes the meet/infimum[note 1]).

More generally, suppose that   is a family of subsets of some set   that is partially ordered by   If   is closed under arbitrary unions and arbitrary intersections and if   belong to   then

 
But if   is not closed under unions then   exists in   if and only if there exists a unique  -smallest   such that   For example, if   then   whereas if   then   does not exist because the sets   are the only upper bounds of   in   that could possibly be the least upper bound   but   and   If   then   does not exist because there is no upper bound of   in  

See also

Notes

  1. ^ a b Grätzer 1996, p. 52.
  2. ^ Hachtel, Gary D.; Somenzi, Fabio (1996). Logic synthesis and verification algorithms. Kluwer Academic Publishers. p. 88. ISBN 0792397460.
  1. ^ It can be immediately determined that supremums and infimums in this canonical, simple example   are   respectively. The similarity of the symbol   to   and of   to   may thus be used as a mnemonic for remembering that in the most general setting,   denotes the supremum (because a supremum is a bound from above, just like   is "above"   and  ) while   denotes the infimum (because an infimum is a bound from below, just like   is "below"   and  ). This can also be used to remember whether meets/joins are denoted by   or by   Intuition suggests that "join"ing two sets together should produce their union   which looks similar to   so "join" must be denoted by   Similarly, two sets should "meet" at their intersection   which looks similar to   so "meet" must be denoted by  

References

join, meet, transitive, binary, relations, vtesymmetricantisymmetricconnectedwell, foundedhas, joinshas, meetsreflexiveirreflexiveasymmetrictotal, semiconnexanti, reflexiveequivalence, relationy, preorder, quasiorder, partial, order, total, preorder, total, or. Transitive binary relations vteSymmetricAntisymmetricConnectedWell foundedHas joinsHas meetsReflexiveIrreflexiveAsymmetricTotal SemiconnexAnti reflexiveEquivalence relationY Y Preorder Quasiorder Y Partial order Y Y Total preorder Y Y Total order YY Y Prewellordering YY Y Well quasi ordering Y Y Well ordering YYY Y Lattice Y YYY Join semilattice Y Y Y Meet semilattice Y YY Strict partial order Y YYStrict weak order Y YYStrict total order YY YYSymmetricAntisymmetricConnectedWell foundedHas joinsHas meetsReflexiveIrreflexiveAsymmetricDefinitions for all a b displaystyle a b and S displaystyle S neq varnothing a R b b R a displaystyle begin aligned amp aRb Rightarrow amp bRa end aligned a R b and b R a a b displaystyle begin aligned aRb text and amp bRa Rightarrow a amp b end aligned a b a R b or b R a displaystyle begin aligned a neq amp b Rightarrow aRb text or amp bRa end aligned min S exists displaystyle begin aligned min S text exists end aligned a b exists displaystyle begin aligned a vee b text exists end aligned a b exists displaystyle begin aligned a wedge b text exists end aligned a R a displaystyle aRa not a R a displaystyle text not aRa a R b not b R a displaystyle begin aligned aRb Rightarrow text not bRa end aligned Y indicates that the column s property is always true the row s term at the very left while indicates that the property is not guaranteed in general it might or might not hold For example that every equivalence relation is symmetric but not necessarily antisymmetric is indicated by Y in the Symmetric column and in the Antisymmetric column respectively All definitions tacitly require the homogeneous relation R displaystyle R be transitive for all a b c displaystyle a b c if a R b displaystyle aRb and b R c displaystyle bRc then a R c displaystyle aRc A term s definition may require additional properties that are not listed in this table In mathematics specifically order theory the join of a subset S displaystyle S of a partially ordered set P displaystyle P is the supremum least upper bound of S displaystyle S denoted S textstyle bigvee S and similarly the meet of S displaystyle S is the infimum greatest lower bound denoted S textstyle bigwedge S In general the join and meet of a subset of a partially ordered set need not exist Join and meet are dual to one another with respect to order inversion This Hasse diagram depicts a partially ordered set with four elements a b the maximal element a displaystyle vee b equal to the join of a and b and the minimal element a displaystyle wedge b equal to the meet of a and b The join meet of a maximal minimal element and another element is the maximal minimal element and conversely the meet join of a maximal minimal element with another element is the other element Thus every pair in this poset has both a meet and a join and the poset can be classified as a lattice A partially ordered set in which all pairs have a join is a join semilattice Dually a partially ordered set in which all pairs have a meet is a meet semilattice A partially ordered set that is both a join semilattice and a meet semilattice is a lattice A lattice in which every subset not just every pair possesses a meet and a join is a complete lattice It is also possible to define a partial lattice in which not all pairs have a meet or join but the operations when defined satisfy certain axioms 1 The join meet of a subset of a totally ordered set is simply the maximal minimal element of that subset if such an element exists If a subset S displaystyle S of a partially ordered set P displaystyle P is also an upward directed set then its join if it exists is called a directed join or directed supremum Dually if S displaystyle S is a downward directed set then its meet if it exists is a directed meet or directed infimum Contents 1 Definitions 1 1 Partial order approach 1 2 Universal algebra approach 1 3 Equivalence of approaches 2 Meets of general subsets 3 Examples 4 See also 5 Notes 6 ReferencesDefinitions EditPartial order approach Edit Let A displaystyle A be a set with a partial order displaystyle leq and let x y A displaystyle x y in A An element m displaystyle m of A displaystyle A is called the meet or greatest lower bound or infimum of x and y displaystyle x text and y and is denoted by x y displaystyle x wedge y if the following two conditions are satisfied m x and m y displaystyle m leq x text and m leq y that is m displaystyle m is a lower bound of x and y displaystyle x text and y For any w A displaystyle w in A if w x and w y displaystyle w leq x text and w leq y then w m displaystyle w leq m that is m displaystyle m is greater than or equal to any other lower bound of x and y displaystyle x text and y The meet need not exist either since the pair has no lower bound at all or since none of the lower bounds is greater than all the others However if there is a meet of x and y displaystyle x text and y then it is unique since if both m and m displaystyle m text and m prime are greatest lower bounds of x and y displaystyle x text and y then m m and m m displaystyle m leq m prime text and m prime leq m and thus m m displaystyle m m prime 2 If not all pairs of elements from A displaystyle A have a meet then the meet can still be seen as a partial binary operation on A displaystyle A 1 If the meet does exist then it is denoted x y displaystyle x wedge y If all pairs of elements from A displaystyle A have a meet then the meet is a binary operation on A displaystyle A and it is easy to see that this operation fulfills the following three conditions For any elements x y z A displaystyle x y z in A x y y x displaystyle x wedge y y wedge x commutativity x y z x y z displaystyle x wedge y wedge z x wedge y wedge z associativity and x x x displaystyle x wedge x x idempotency Joins are defined dually with the join of x and y displaystyle x text and y if it exists denoted by x y displaystyle x vee y An element j displaystyle j of A displaystyle A is the join or least upper bound or supremum of x and y displaystyle x text and y in A displaystyle A if the following two conditions are satisfied x j and y j displaystyle x leq j text and y leq j that is j displaystyle j is an upper bound of x and y displaystyle x text and y For any w A displaystyle w in A if x w and y w displaystyle x leq w text and y leq w then j w displaystyle j leq w that is j displaystyle j is less than or equal to any other upper bound of x and y displaystyle x text and y Universal algebra approach Edit By definition a binary operation displaystyle wedge on a set A displaystyle A is a meet if it satisfies the three conditions a b and c The pair A displaystyle A wedge is then a meet semilattice Moreover we then may define a binary relation displaystyle leq on A by stating that x y displaystyle x leq y if and only if x y x displaystyle x wedge y x In fact this relation is a partial order on A displaystyle A Indeed for any elements x y z A displaystyle x y z in A x x displaystyle x leq x since x x x displaystyle x wedge x x by c if x y and y x displaystyle x leq y text and y leq x then x x y y x y displaystyle x x wedge y y wedge x y by a and if x y and y z displaystyle x leq y text and y leq z then x z displaystyle x leq z since then x z x y z x y z x y x displaystyle x wedge z x wedge y wedge z x wedge y wedge z x wedge y x by b Both meets and joins equally satisfy this definition a couple of associated meet and join operations yield partial orders which are the reverse of each other When choosing one of these orders as the main ones one also fixes which operation is considered a meet the one giving the same order and which is considered a join the other one Equivalence of approaches Edit If A displaystyle A leq is a partially ordered set such that each pair of elements in A displaystyle A has a meet then indeed x y x displaystyle x wedge y x if and only if x y displaystyle x leq y since in the latter case indeed x displaystyle x is a lower bound of x and y displaystyle x text and y and since x displaystyle x is the greatest lower bound if and only if it is a lower bound Thus the partial order defined by the meet in the universal algebra approach coincides with the original partial order Conversely if A displaystyle A wedge is a meet semilattice and the partial order displaystyle leq is defined as in the universal algebra approach and z x y displaystyle z x wedge y for some elements x y A displaystyle x y in A then z displaystyle z is the greatest lower bound of x and y displaystyle x text and y with respect to displaystyle leq sincez x x z x x y x x y x y z displaystyle z wedge x x wedge z x wedge x wedge y x wedge x wedge y x wedge y z and therefore z x displaystyle z leq x Similarly z y displaystyle z leq y and if w displaystyle w is another lower bound of x and y displaystyle x text and y then w x w y w displaystyle w wedge x w wedge y w whence w z w x y w x y w y w displaystyle w wedge z w wedge x wedge y w wedge x wedge y w wedge y w Thus there is a meet defined by the partial order defined by the original meet and the two meets coincide In other words the two approaches yield essentially equivalent concepts a set equipped with both a binary relation and a binary operation such that each one of these structures determines the other and fulfill the conditions for partial orders or meets respectively Meets of general subsets EditIf A displaystyle A wedge is a meet semilattice then the meet may be extended to a well defined meet of any non empty finite set by the technique described in iterated binary operations Alternatively if the meet defines or is defined by a partial order some subsets of A displaystyle A indeed have infima with respect to this and it is reasonable to consider such an infimum as the meet of the subset For non empty finite subsets the two approaches yield the same result and so either may be taken as a definition of meet In the case where each subset of A displaystyle A has a meet in fact A displaystyle A leq is a complete lattice for details see completeness order theory Examples EditIf some power set X displaystyle wp X is partially ordered in the usual way by displaystyle subseteq then joins are unions and meets are intersections in symbols and displaystyle vee cup text and wedge cap where the similarity of these symbols may be used as a mnemonic for remembering that displaystyle vee denotes the join supremum and displaystyle wedge denotes the meet infimum note 1 More generally suppose that F displaystyle mathcal F neq varnothing is a family of subsets of some set X displaystyle X that is partially ordered by displaystyle subseteq If F displaystyle mathcal F is closed under arbitrary unions and arbitrary intersections and if A B F i i I displaystyle A B left F i right i in I belong to F displaystyle mathcal F thenA B A B A B A B i I F i i I F i and i I F i i I F i displaystyle A vee B A cup B quad A wedge B A cap B quad bigvee i in I F i bigcup i in I F i quad text and quad bigwedge i in I F i bigcap i in I F i But if F displaystyle mathcal F is not closed under unions then A B displaystyle A vee B exists in F displaystyle mathcal F subseteq if and only if there exists a unique displaystyle subseteq smallest J F displaystyle J in mathcal F such that A B J displaystyle A cup B subseteq J For example if F 1 2 1 2 3 R displaystyle mathcal F 1 2 1 2 3 mathbb R then 1 2 1 2 3 displaystyle 1 vee 2 1 2 3 whereas if F 1 2 1 2 3 0 1 2 R displaystyle mathcal F 1 2 1 2 3 0 1 2 mathbb R then 1 2 displaystyle 1 vee 2 does not exist because the sets 0 1 2 and 1 2 3 displaystyle 0 1 2 text and 1 2 3 are the only upper bounds of 1 and 2 displaystyle 1 text and 2 in F displaystyle mathcal F subseteq that could possibly be the least upper bound 1 2 displaystyle 1 vee 2 but 0 1 2 1 2 3 displaystyle 0 1 2 not subseteq 1 2 3 and 1 2 3 0 1 2 displaystyle 1 2 3 not subseteq 0 1 2 If F 1 2 0 2 3 0 1 3 displaystyle mathcal F 1 2 0 2 3 0 1 3 then 1 2 displaystyle 1 vee 2 does not exist because there is no upper bound of 1 and 2 displaystyle 1 text and 2 in F displaystyle mathcal F subseteq See also EditLocally convex vector latticeNotes Edit a b Gratzer 1996 p 52 sfn error no target CITEREFGratzer1996 help Hachtel Gary D Somenzi Fabio 1996 Logic synthesis and verification algorithms Kluwer Academic Publishers p 88 ISBN 0792397460 It can be immediately determined that supremums and infimums in this canonical simple example X displaystyle wp X subseteq are and displaystyle cup text and cap respectively The similarity of the symbol displaystyle vee to displaystyle cup and of displaystyle wedge to displaystyle cap may thus be used as a mnemonic for remembering that in the most general setting displaystyle vee denotes the supremum because a supremum is a bound from above just like A B displaystyle A cup B is above A displaystyle A and B displaystyle B while displaystyle wedge denotes the infimum because an infimum is a bound from below just like A B displaystyle A cap B is below A displaystyle A and B displaystyle B This can also be used to remember whether meets joins are denoted by displaystyle vee or by displaystyle wedge Intuition suggests that join ing two sets together should produce their union A B displaystyle A cup B which looks similar to A B displaystyle A vee B so join must be denoted by displaystyle vee Similarly two sets should meet at their intersection A B displaystyle A cap B which looks similar to A B displaystyle A wedge B so meet must be denoted by displaystyle wedge References EditDavey B A Priestley H A 2002 Introduction to Lattices and Order 2nd ed Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 78451 4 Zbl 1002 06001 Vickers Steven 1989 Topology via Logic Cambridge Tracts in Theoretic Computer Science Vol 5 ISBN 0 521 36062 5 Zbl 0668 54001 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Join and meet amp oldid 1127634788, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.