fbpx
Wikipedia

Info-gap decision theory

Info-gap decision theory seeks to optimize robustness to failure under severe uncertainty,[1][2] in particular applying sensitivity analysis of the stability radius type[3] to perturbations in the value of a given estimate of the parameter of interest. It has some connections with Wald's maximin model; some authors distinguish them, others consider them instances of the same principle.

It has been developed by ,[4] and has found many applications and described as a theory for decision-making under "severe uncertainty". It has been criticized as unsuited for this purpose, and alternatives proposed, including such classical approaches as robust optimization.

Summary edit

Info-gap is a theory: it assists in decisions under uncertainty. It does this by using models, each built on the last. One begins with a model for the situation, where some parameter or parameters are unknown. Then takes an estimate for the parameter, and one analyzes how sensitive the outcomes under the model are to the error in this estimate.

Uncertainty model
Starting from the estimate, an uncertainty model measures how far away other values of the parameter are: as uncertainty increases, the set of values increase.
Robustness/opportuneness model
Given an uncertainty model, then for each decision, how uncertain can you be and be confident succeeding? (robustness) Also, given a windfall, how uncertain must you be for this result to be plausible? (opportuneness)
Decision-making model
One optimizes the robustness on the basis of the model. Given an outcome, which decision can stand the most uncertainty and give the outcome? Also, given a windfall, which decision requires the least uncertainty for the outcome?

Models edit

Info-gap theory models uncertainty as subsets   around a point estimate  : the estimate is accurate, and uncertainty increases, in general without bound. The uncertainty measures the "distance" between an estimate and a plausibility – providing an intermediate measure between a point (the point estimate) and all plausibilities, and giving a sensitivity measure: what is the margin of error?

Info-gap analysis gives answers to such questions as:

  • under what level of uncertainty can specific requirements be reliably assured (robustness), and
  • what level of uncertainty is necessary to achieve certain windfalls (opportuneness).

It can be used for satisficing, as an alternative to optimizing in the presence of uncertainty or bounded rationality; see robust optimization for an alternative approach.

Comparison with classical decision theory edit

In contrast to probabilistic decision theory, info-gap analysis does not use probability distributions: it measures the deviation of errors (differences between the parameter and the estimate), but not the probability of outcomes – in particular, the estimate   is in no sense more or less likely than other points, as info-gap does not use probability. Info-gap, by not using probability distributions, is robust in that it is not sensitive to assumptions on probabilities of outcomes. However, the model of uncertainty does include a notion of "closer" and "more distant" outcomes, and thus includes some assumptions, and is not as robust as simply considering all possible outcomes, as in minimax. Further, it considers a fixed universe   so it is not robust to unexpected (not modeled) events.

The connection to minimax analysis has occasioned some controversy: (Ben-Haim 1999, pp. 271–2) argues that info-gap's robustness analysis, while similar in some ways, is not minimax worst-case analysis, as it does not evaluate decisions over all possible outcomes, while (Sniedovich, 2007) argues that the robustness analysis can be seen as an example of maximin (not minimax). This is discussed in criticism, below, and elaborated in the classical decision theory perspective.

Basic example: budget edit

As a simple example, consider a worker. They expect to make $20 per week, while if they make under $15 they will be unable to work and will sleep in the street, otherwise they can afford a night's entertainment.

Using absolute error model:

where   one can say the robustness is $15, and opportuneness is $20: if they make $20, they will not sleep rough nor feast, and if they make within $20 of $200. But, if they erred by $20, they may sleep rough, while for more than $30, they may find themselves dining in opulence.

As stated, this example is only descriptive, and does not enable any decision making – in applications, one considers alternative decision rules, and often situations with more complex uncertainty.

The worker is thinking of moving elsewhere, where accommodation is cheaper. They will earn $26 per week, but hostels costs $20, while entertainment still costs $170. In that case the robustness will be $24, and the opportuneness will be $43. The second case has less robustness and less opportuneness.

But, measuring uncertainty by relative error,

robustness is 20% and opportuneness is 23%, while in the other robustness is 38% and opportuneness is 60%, so moving is less opportune.

Info-gap models edit

Info-gap can be applied to spaces of functions; in that case the uncertain parameter is a function   with estimate   and the nested subsets are sets of functions. One way to describe such a set of functions is by requiring values of u to be close to values of   for all x, using a family of info-gap models on the values.

For example, the above fraction error model for values becomes the fractional error model for functions by adding a parameter x to the definition:

 

More generally, if   is a family of info-gap models of values, then one obtains an info-gap model of functions in the same way:

 

Motivation edit

It is common to make decisions under uncertainty.[note 1] What can be done to make good (or at least the best possible) decisions under conditions of uncertainty? Info-gap robustness analysis evaluates each feasible decision by asking: how much deviation from an estimate of a parameter value, function, or set, is permitted and yet "guarantee" acceptable performance? In everyday terms, the "robustness" of a decision is set by the size of deviation from an estimate that still leads to performance within requirements when using that decision. It is sometimes difficult to judge how much robustness is needed or sufficient. However, according to info-gap theory, the ranking of feasible decisions in terms of their degree of robustness is independent of such judgments.

Info-gap theory also proposes an opportuneness function which evaluates the potential for windfall outcomes resulting from favorable uncertainty.

Example: resource allocation edit

Resource allocation edit

Suppose you are a project manager, supervising two teams: orange and white. Some revenue at the end of the year will be achieved. You have a limited timescale, and you aim to decide how to space these resources between the orange and white, so that the total revenues are large.

Introducing uncertainty edit

The actual revenue may be different. For uncertainty level we can define an envelope. Lower uncertainty would correspond to a smaller envelope.

These envelopes are called info-gap models of uncertainty, since they describe one's understanding of the uncertainty surrounding the revenue functions.

We can find a model for the total revenue. Figure 5 shows the info-gap model of the total revenue.

Robustness edit

High revenues would typically earn a project manager the senior management's respect, but if the total revenues are below a certain threshold, it will cost said project manager's job. We will define such a threshold as a critical revenue, since total revenues beneath the critical revenue will be considered as failure.

This is shown in Figure 6. If the uncertainty will increase, the envelope of uncertainty will become more inclusive, to include instances of the total revenue function that, for the specific allocation, yields a revenue smaller than the critical revenue.

The robustness measures the immunity of a decision to failure. A robust satisficer is a decision maker that prefers choices with higher robustness.

If, for some allocation  , the correlation between the critical revenue and the robustness is illustrated, the result is a graph somewhat similar to that in Figure 7. This graph, called robustness curve of allocation  , has two important features, that are common to (most) robustness curves:

  1. The curve is non-increasing. This captures the notion that when higher requirements (higher critical revenue) are in place, failure to meet the target is more likely (lower robustness). This is the tradeoff between quality and robustness.
  2. At the nominal revenue, that is, when the critical revenue equals the revenue under the nominal model (the estimate of the revenue functions), the robustness is zero. This is since a slight deviation from the estimate may decrease the total revenue.

The decision depends on the value of failure.

Opportuneness edit

As well as the threat of losing your job, the senior management offers you a carrot: if the revenues are higher than some revenue, you will be rewarded.

If the uncertainty will decrease, the envelope of uncertainty will become less inclusive, to exclude all instances of the total revenue function that, for the specific allocation, yields a revenue higher than the windfall revenue.

If, for some allocation  , we will illustrate the correlation between the windfall revenue and the robustness, we will have a graph somewhat similar to Figure 10. This graph, called opportuneness curve of allocation  , has two important features, that are common to (most) opportuneness curves:

  1. The curve is non-decreasing. This captures the notion that when we have higher requirements (higher windfall revenue), we are more immune to failure (higher opportuneness, which is less desirable). That is, we need a more substantial deviation from the estimate in order to achieve our ambitious goal. This is the tradeoff between quality and opportuneness.
  2. At the nominal revenue, that is, when the critical revenue equals the revenue under the nominal model (our estimate of the revenue functions), the opportuneness is zero. This is since no deviation from the estimate is needed in order to achieve the windfall revenue.

Treatment of severe uncertainty edit

Note that in addition to the results generated by the estimate, two "possible" true values of the revenue are also displayed at a distance from the estimate.

As indicated by the picture, since info-gap robustness model applies its Maximin analysis in an immediate neighborhood of the estimate, there is no assurance that the analysis is in fact conducted in the neighborhood of the true value of the revenue. In fact, under conditions of severe uncertainty this—methodologically speaking—is very unlikely.

This raises the question: how valid/useful/meaningful are the results? Aren't we sweeping the severity of the uncertainty under the carpet?

For example, suppose that a given allocation is found to be very fragile in the neighborhood of the estimate. Does this mean that this allocation is also fragile elsewhere in the region of uncertainty? Conversely, what guarantee is there that an allocation that is robust in the neighborhood of the estimate is also robust elsewhere in the region of uncertainty, indeed in the neighborhood of the true value of the revenue?

More fundamentally, given that the results generated by info-gap are based on a local revenue/allocation analysis in the neighborhood of an estimate that is likely to be substantially wrong, we have no other choice—methodologically speaking—but to assume that the results generated by this analysis are equally likely to be substantially wrong. In other words, in accordance with the universal Garbage In - Garbage Out Axiom, we have to assume that the quality of the results generated by info-gap's analysis is only as good as the quality of the estimate on which the results are based.

The picture speaks for itself.

What emerges then is that info-gap theory is yet to explain in what way, if any, it actually attempts to deal with the severity of the uncertainty under consideration. Subsequent sections of this article will address this severity issue and its methodological and practical implications.

A more detailed analysis of an illustrative numerical investment problem of this type can be found in Sniedovich (2007).

Uncertainty models edit

Info-gaps are quantified by info-gap models of uncertainty. An info-gap model is an unbounded family of nested sets. For example, a frequently encountered example is a family of nested ellipsoids all having the same shape. The structure of the sets in an info-gap model derives from the information about the uncertainty. In general terms, the structure of an info-gap model of uncertainty is chosen to define the smallest or strictest family of sets whose elements are consistent with the prior information. Since there is, usually, no known worst case, the family of sets may be unbounded.

A common example of an info-gap model is the fractional error model. The best estimate of an uncertain function   is  , but the fractional error of this estimate is unknown. The following unbounded family of nested sets of functions is a fractional-error info-gap model:

 

At any horizon of uncertainty  , the set   contains all functions   whose fractional deviation from   is no greater than  . However, the horizon of uncertainty is unknown, so the info-gap model is an unbounded family of sets, and there is no worst case or greatest deviation.

There are many other types of info-gap models of uncertainty. All info-gap models obey two basic axioms:

  • Nesting. The info-gap model   is nested if   implies that:
 
  • Contraction. The info-gap model   is a singleton set containing its center point:
 

The nesting axiom imposes the property of "clustering" which is characteristic of info-gap uncertainty. Furthermore, the nesting axiom implies that the uncertainty sets   become more inclusive as   grows, thus endowing   with its meaning as a horizon of uncertainty. The contraction axiom implies that, at horizon of uncertainty zero, the estimate   is correct.

Recall that the uncertain element   may be a parameter, vector, function or set. The info-gap model is then an unbounded family of nested sets of parameters, vectors, functions or sets.

Sublevel sets edit

For a fixed point estimate   an info-gap model is often equivalent to a function   defined as:

 

meaning "the uncertainty of a point u is the minimum uncertainty such that u is in the set with that uncertainty". In this case, the family of sets   can be recovered as the sublevel sets of  :

 

meaning: "the nested subset with horizon of uncertainty   consists of all points with uncertainty less than or equal to  ".

Conversely, given a function   satisfying the axiom   (equivalently,   if and only if  ), it defines an info-gap model via the sublevel sets.

For instance, if the region of uncertainty is a metric space, then the uncertainty function can simply be the distance,   so the nested subsets are simply

 

This always defines an info-gap model, as distances are always non-negative (axiom of non-negativity), and satisfies   (info-gap axiom of contraction) because the distance between two points is zero if and only if they are equal (the identity of indiscernibles); nesting follows by construction of sublevel set.

Not all info-gap models arise as sublevel sets: for instance, if   for all   but not for   (it has uncertainty "just more" than 1), then the minimum above is not defined; one can replace it by an infimum, but then the resulting sublevel sets will not agree with the infogap model:   but   The effect of this distinction is very minor, however, as it modifies sets by less than changing the horizon of uncertainty by any positive number   however small.

Robustness and opportuneness edit

Uncertainty may be either pernicious or propitious. That is, uncertain variations may be either adverse or favorable. Adversity entails the possibility of failure, while favorability is the opportunity for sweeping success. Info-gap decision theory is based on quantifying these two aspects of uncertainty, and choosing an action which addresses one or the other or both of them simultaneously. The pernicious and propitious aspects of uncertainty are quantified by two "immunity functions": the robustness function expresses the immunity to failure, while the opportuneness function expresses the immunity to windfall gain.

Robustness and opportuneness functions edit

The robustness function expresses the greatest level of uncertainty at which failure cannot occur; the opportuneness function is the least level of uncertainty which entails the possibility of sweeping success. The robustness and opportuneness functions address, respectively, the pernicious and propitious facets of uncertainty.

Let   be a decision vector of parameters such as design variables, time of initiation, model parameters or operational options. We can verbally express the robustness and opportuneness functions as the maximum or minimum of a set of values of the uncertainty parameter   of an info-gap model:

  (robustness) (1a)
  (opportuneness) (2a)

Formally,

  (robustness) (1b)
  (opportuneness) (2b)

We can "read" eq. (1) as follows. The robustness   of decision vector   is the greatest value of the horizon of uncertainty   for which specified minimal requirements are always satisfied.   expresses robustness — the degree of resistance to uncertainty and immunity against failure — so a large value of   is desirable. Robustness is defined as a worst-case scenario up to the horizon of uncertainty: how large can the horizon of uncertainty be and still, even in the worst case, achieve the critical level of outcome?

Eq. (2) states that the opportuneness   is the least level of uncertainty   which must be tolerated in order to enable the possibility of sweeping success as a result of decisions  .   is the immunity against windfall reward, so a small value of   is desirable. A small value of   reflects the opportune situation that great reward is possible even in the presence of little ambient uncertainty. Opportuneness is defined as a best-case scenario up to the horizon of uncertainty: how small can the horizon of uncertainty be and still, in the best case, achieve the windfall reward?

The immunity functions   and   are complementary and are defined in an anti-symmetric sense. Thus "bigger is better" for   while "big is bad" for  . The immunity functions — robustness and opportuneness — are the basic decision functions in info-gap decision theory.

Optimization edit

The robustness function involves a maximization, but not of the performance or outcome of the decision: in general the outcome could be arbitrarily bad. Rather, it maximizes the level of uncertainty that would be required for the outcome to fail.

The greatest tolerable uncertainty is found at which decision   satisfices the performance at a critical survival-level. One may establish one's preferences among the available actions   according to their robustnesses  , whereby larger robustness engenders higher preference. In this way the robustness function underlies a satisficing decision algorithm which maximizes the immunity to pernicious uncertainty.

The opportuneness function in eq. (2) involves a minimization, however not, as might be expected, of the damage which can accrue from unknown adverse events. The least horizon of uncertainty is sought at which decision   enables (but does not necessarily guarantee) large windfall gain. Unlike the robustness function, the opportuneness function does not satisfice, it "windfalls". Windfalling preferences are those which prefer actions for which the opportuneness function takes a small value. When   is used to choose an action  , one is "windfalling" by optimizing the opportuneness from propitious uncertainty in an attempt to enable highly ambitious goals or rewards.

Given a scalar reward function  , depending on the decision vector   and the info-gap-uncertain function  , the minimal requirement in eq. (1) is that the reward   be no less than a critical value  . Likewise, the sweeping success in eq. (2) is attainment of a "wildest dream" level of reward   which is much greater than  . Usually neither of these threshold values,   and  , is chosen irrevocably before performing the decision analysis. Rather, these parameters enable the decision maker to explore a range of options. In any case the windfall reward   is greater, usually much greater, than the critical reward  :

 

The robustness and opportuneness functions of eqs. (1) and (2) can now be expressed more explicitly:

  (3)
  (4)

  is the greatest level of uncertainty consistent with guaranteed reward no less than the critical reward  , while   is the least level of uncertainty which must be accepted in order to facilitate (but not guarantee) windfall as great as  . The complementary or anti-symmetric structure of the immunity functions is evident from eqs. (3) and (4).

These definitions can be modified to handle multi-criterion reward functions. Likewise, analogous definitions apply when   is a loss rather than a reward.

Decision rules edit

Based on these function, one can then decided on a course of action by optimizing for uncertainty: choose the decision which is most robust (can withstand the greatest uncertainty; "satisficing"), or choose the decision which requires the least uncertainty to achieve a windfall.

Formally, optimizing for robustness or optimizing for opportuneness yields a preference relation on the set of decisions, and the decision rule is the "optimize with respect to this preference".

In the below, let   be the set of all available or feasible decision vectors  .

Robust-satisficing edit

The robustness function generates robust-satisficing preferences on the options: decisions are ranked in increasing order of robustness, for a given critical reward, i.e., by   value, meaning   if  

A robust-satisficing decision is one which maximizes the robustness and satisfices the performance at the critical level  .

Denote the maximum robustness by   (formally   for the maximum robustness for a given critical reward), and the corresponding decision (or decisions) by   (formally,   the critical optimizing action for a given level of critical reward):

 

Usually, though not invariably, the robust-satisficing action   depends on the critical reward  .

Opportune-windfalling edit

Conversely, one may optimize opportuneness: the opportuneness function generates opportune-windfalling preferences on the options: decisions are ranked in decreasing order of opportuneness, for a given windfall reward, i.e., by   value, meaning   if  

The opportune-windfalling decision,  , minimizes the opportuneness function on the set of available decisions.

Denote the minimum opportuneness by   (formally   for the minimum opportuneness for a given windfall reward), and the corresponding decision (or decisions) by   (formally,   the windfall optimizing action for a given level of windfall reward):

 

The two preference rankings, as well as the corresponding the optimal decisions   and  , may be different, and may vary depending on the values of   and  

Applications edit

Info-gap theory has generated a lot of literature. Info-gap theory has been studied or applied in a range of applications including engineering,[5] [6] [7] [8] [9] [10] [11] [12] [13] [14] [15] [16][17][18] biological conservation,[19] [20] [21] [22] [23] [24] [25] [26] [27] [28][29][30] theoretical biology,[31] homeland security,[32] economics,[33][34][35] project management[36] [37] [38] and statistics.[39] Foundational issues related to info-gap theory have also been studied.[40] [41] [42] [43] [44] [45]

The remainder of this section describes in a little more detail the kind of uncertainties addressed by info-gap theory. Although many published works are mentioned below, no attempt is made here to present insights from these papers. The emphasis is not upon elucidation of the concepts of info-gap theory, but upon the context where it is used and the goals.

Engineering edit

A typical engineering application is the vibration analysis of a cracked beam, where the location, size, shape and orientation of the crack is unknown and greatly influence the vibration dynamics.[9] Very little is usually known about these spatial and geometrical uncertainties. The info-gap analysis allows one to model these uncertainties, and to determine the degree of robustness - to these uncertainties - of properties such as vibration amplitude, natural frequencies, and natural modes of vibration. Another example is the structural design of a building subject to uncertain loads such as from wind or earthquakes.[8][10] The response of the structure depends strongly on the spatial and temporal distribution of the loads. However, storms and earthquakes are highly idiosyncratic events, and the interaction between the event and the structure involves very site-specific mechanical properties which are rarely known. The info-gap analysis enables the design of the structure to enhance structural immunity against uncertain deviations from design-base or estimated worst-case loads.[citation needed] Another engineering application involves the design of a neural net for detecting faults in a mechanical system, based on real-time measurements. A major difficulty is that faults are highly idiosyncratic, so that training data for the neural net will tend to differ substantially from data obtained from real-time faults after the net has been trained. The info-gap robustness strategy enables one to design the neural net to be robust to the disparity between training data and future real events.[11][13]

Biology edit

The conservation biologist faces info-gaps in using biological models. They use info-gap robustness curves to select among management options for spruce-budworm populations in Eastern Canada. Burgman [46] uses the fact that the robustness curves of different alternatives can intersect.

Project management edit

Project management is another area where info-gap uncertainty is common. The project manager often has very limited information about the duration and cost of some of the tasks in the project, and info-gap robustness can assist in project planning and integration.[37] Financial economics is another area where the future is fraught with surprises, which may be either pernicious or propitious. Info-gap robustness and opportuneness analyses can assist in portfolio design, credit rationing, and other applications.[33]

Limitations edit

In applying info-gap theory, one must remain aware of certain limitations.

Firstly, info-gap makes assumptions, namely on universe in question, and the degree of uncertainty – the info-gap model is a model of degrees of uncertainty or similarity of various assumptions, within a given universe. Info-gap does not make probability assumptions within this universe – it is non-probabilistic – but does quantify a notion of "distance from the estimate". In brief, info-gap makes fewer assumptions than a probabilistic method, but does make some assumptions.

For instance, a simple model of daily stock market returns – which by definition fall in the range   – may include extreme moves such as Black Monday (1987) but might not model the market breakdowns following the September 11 attacks: it considers the "known unknowns", not the "unknown unknowns". This is a general criticism of much decision theory, and is by no means specific to info-gap, but info-gap is not immune to it.

Secondly, there is no natural scale: is uncertainty of   small or large? Different models of uncertainty give different scales, and require judgment and understanding of the domain and the model of uncertainty. Similarly, measuring differences between outcomes requires judgment and understanding of the domain.

Thirdly, if the universe under consideration is larger than a significant horizon of uncertainty, and outcomes for these distant points are significantly different from points near the estimate, then conclusions of robustness or opportuneness analyses will generally be: "one must be very confident of one's assumptions, else outcomes may be expected to vary significantly from projections" – a cautionary conclusion.

Disclaimer and summary edit

The robustness and opportuneness functions can inform decision. For example, a change in decision increasing robustness may increase or decrease opportuneness. From a subjective stance, robustness and opportuneness both trade-off against aspiration for outcome: robustness and opportuneness deteriorate as the decision maker's aspirations increase. Robustness is zero for model-best anticipated outcomes. Robustness curves for alternative decisions may cross as a function of aspiration, implying reversal of preference.

Various theorems identify conditions where larger info-gap robustness implies larger probability of success, regardless of the underlying probability distribution. However, these conditions are technical, and do not translate into any common-sense, verbal recommendations, limiting such applications of info-gap theory by non-experts.

Criticism edit

A general criticism of non-probabilistic decision rules, discussed in detail at decision theory: alternatives to probability theory, is that optimal decision rules (formally, admissible decision rules) can always be derived by probabilistic methods, with a suitable utility function and prior distribution (this is the statement of the complete class theorems), and thus that non-probabilistic methods such as info-gap are unnecessary and do not yield new or better decision rules.

A more general criticism of decision making under uncertainty is the impact of outsized, unexpected events, ones that are not captured by the model. This is discussed particularly in black swan theory, and info-gap, used in isolation, is vulnerable to this, as are a fortiori all decision theories that use a fixed universe of possibilities, notably probabilistic ones.

Sniedovich[47] raises two points to info-gap decision theory, one substantive, one scholarly:

1. the info-gap uncertainty model is flawed and oversold
One should consider the range of possibilities, not its subsets. Sniedovich argues that info-gap decision theory is therefore a "voodoo decision theory."
2. info-gap is maximin
Ben-Haim states (Ben-Haim 1999, pp. 271–2) that "robust reliability is emphatically not a [min-max] worst-case analysis". Note that Ben-Haim compares info-gap to minimax, while Sniedovich considers it a case of maximin.

Sniedovich has challenged the validity of info-gap theory for making decisions under severe uncertainty. Sniedovich notes that the info-gap robustness function is "local" to the region around  , where   is likely to be substantially in error.

Maximin edit

Symbolically, max   assuming min (worst-case) outcome, or maximin.

In other words, while it is not a maximin analysis of outcome over the universe of uncertainty, it is a maximin analysis over a properly construed decision space.

Ben-Haim argues that info-gap's robustness model is not min-max/maximin analysis because it is not worst-case analysis of outcomes; it is a satisficing model, not an optimization model – a (straightforward) maximin analysis would consider worst-case outcomes over the entire space which, since uncertainty is often potentially unbounded, would yield an unbounded bad worst case.

Stability radius edit

Sniedovich[3] has shown that info-gap's robustness model is a simple stability radius model, namely a local stability model of the generic form

 

where   denotes a ball of radius   centered at   and   denotes the set of values of   that satisfy pre-determined stability conditions.

In other words, info-gap's robustness model is a stability radius model characterized by a stability requirement of the form  . Since stability radius models are designed for the analysis of small perturbations in a given nominal value of a parameter, Sniedovich[3] argues that info-gap's robustness model is unsuitable for the treatment of severe uncertainty characterized by a poor estimate and a vast uncertainty space.

Discussion edit

Satisficing and bounded rationality edit

It is correct that the info-gap robustness function is local, and has restricted quantitative value in some cases. However, a major purpose of decision analysis is to provide focus for subjective judgments. That is, regardless of the formal analysis, a framework for discussion is provided. Without entering into any particular framework, or characteristics of frameworks in general, discussion follows about proposals for such frameworks.

Simon [48] introduced the idea of bounded rationality. Limitations on knowledge, understanding, and computational capability constrain the ability of decision makers to identify optimal choices. Simon advocated satisficing rather than optimizing: seeking adequate (rather than optimal) outcomes given available resources. Schwartz,[49] Conlisk [50] and others discuss extensive evidence for the phenomenon of bounded rationality among human decision makers, as well as for the advantages of satisficing when knowledge and understanding are deficient. The info-gap robustness function provides a means of implementing a satisficing strategy under bounded rationality. For instance, in discussing bounded rationality and satisficing in conservation and environmental management, Burgman notes that "Info-gap theory ... can function sensibly when there are 'severe' knowledge gaps." The info-gap robustness and opportuneness functions provide "a formal framework to explore the kinds of speculations that occur intuitively when examining decision options." [51] Burgman then proceeds to develop an info-gap robust-satisficing strategy for protecting the endangered orange-bellied parrot. Similarly, Vinot, Cogan and Cipolla [52] discuss engineering design and note that "the downside of a model-based analysis lies in the knowledge that the model behavior is only an approximation to the real system behavior. Hence the question of the honest designer: how sensitive is my measure of design success to uncertainties in my system representation? ... It is evident that if model-based analysis is to be used with any level of confidence then ... [one must] attempt to satisfy an acceptable sub-optimal level of performance while remaining maximally robust to the system uncertainties."[52] They proceed to develop an info-gap robust-satisficing design procedure for an aerospace application.

Alternatives edit

Of course, decision in the face of uncertainty is nothing new, and attempts to deal with it have a long history. A number of authors have noted and discussed similarities and differences between info-gap robustness and minimax or worst-case methods [7][16][35][37] [53] .[54] Sniedovich [47] has demonstrated formally that the info-gap robustness function can be represented as a maximin optimization, and is thus related to Wald's minimax theory. Sniedovich [47] has claimed that info-gap's robustness analysis is conducted in the neighborhood of an estimate that is likely to be substantially wrong, concluding that the resulting robustness function is equally likely to be substantially wrong.

On the other hand, the estimate is the best one has, so it is useful to know if it can err greatly and still yield an acceptable outcome. This critical question clearly raises the issue of whether robustness (as defined by info-gap theory) is qualified to judge whether confidence is warranted,[5][55] [56] and how it compares to methods used to inform decisions under uncertainty using considerations not limited to the neighborhood of a bad initial guess. Answers to these questions vary with the particular problem at hand. Some general comments follow.

Sensitivity analysis edit

Sensitivity analysis – how sensitive conclusions are to input assumptions – can be performed independently of a model of uncertainty: most simply, one may take two different assumed values for an input and compares the conclusions. From this perspective, info-gap can be seen as a technique of sensitivity analysis, though by no means the only.

Robust optimization edit

The robust optimization literature [57][58][59][60][61][62] provides methods and techniques that take a global approach to robustness analysis. These methods directly address decision under severe uncertainty, and have been used for this purpose for more than thirty years now. Wald's Maximin model is the main instrument used by these methods.

The principal difference between the Maximin model employed by info-gap and the various Maximin models employed by robust optimization methods is in the manner in which the total region of uncertainty is incorporated in the robustness model. Info-gap takes a local approach that concentrates on the immediate neighborhood of the estimate. In sharp contrast, robust optimization methods set out to incorporate in the analysis the entire region of uncertainty, or at least an adequate representation thereof. In fact, some of these methods do not even use an estimate.

Comparative analysis edit

Classical decision theory,[63][64] offers two approaches to decision-making under severe uncertainty, namely maximin and Laplaces' principle of insufficient reason (assume all outcomes equally likely); these may be considered alternative solutions to the problem info-gap addresses.

Further, as discussed at decision theory: alternatives to probability theory, probabilists, particularly Bayesians probabilists, argue that optimal decision rules (formally, admissible decision rules) can always be derived by probabilistic methods (this is the statement of the complete class theorems), and thus that non-probabilistic methods such as info-gap are unnecessary and do not yield new or better decision rules.

Maximin edit

As attested by the rich literature on robust optimization, maximin provides a wide range of methods for decision making in the face of severe uncertainty.

Indeed, as discussed in criticism of info-gap decision theory, info-gap's robustness model can be interpreted as an instance of the general maximin model.

Bayesian analysis edit

As for Laplaces' principle of insufficient reason, in this context it is convenient to view it as an instance of Bayesian analysis.

The essence of the Bayesian analysis is applying probabilities for different possible realizations of the uncertain parameters. In the case of Knightian (non-probabilistic) uncertainty, these probabilities represent the decision maker's "degree of belief" in a specific realization.

In our example, suppose there are only five possible realizations of the uncertain revenue to allocation function. The decision maker believes that the estimated function is the most likely, and that the likelihood decreases as the difference from the estimate increases. Figure 11 exemplifies such a probability distribution.

 
Figure 11 – Probability distribution of the revenue function realizations

Now, for any allocation, one can construct a probability distribution of the revenue, based on his prior beliefs. The decision maker can then choose the allocation with the highest expected revenue, with the lowest probability for an unacceptable revenue, etc.

The most problematic step of this analysis is the choice of the realizations probabilities. When there is an extensive and relevant past experience, an expert may use this experience to construct a probability distribution. But even with extensive past experience, when some parameters change, the expert may only be able to estimate that   is more likely than  , but will not be able to reliably quantify this difference. Furthermore, when conditions change drastically, or when there is no past experience at all, it may prove to be difficult even estimating whether   is more likely than  .

Nevertheless, methodologically speaking, this difficulty is not as problematic as basing the analysis of a problem subject to severe uncertainty on a single point estimate and its immediate neighborhood, as done by info-gap. And what is more, contrary to info-gap, this approach is global, rather than local.

Still, it must be stressed that Bayesian analysis does not expressly concern itself with the question of robustness.

Bayesian analysis raises the issue of learning from experience and adjusting probabilities accordingly. In other words, decision is not a one-stop process, but profits from a sequence of decisions and observations.

Classical decision theory perspective edit

Sniedovich[47] raises two points to info-gap, from the point of view of classical decision theory, one substantive, one scholarly:

the info-gap uncertainty model is flawed and oversold
Under severe uncertainty, one should use global decision theory , not local decision theory.
info-gap is maximin
Ben-Haim (2006, p.xii) claims that info-gap is "radically different from all current theories of decision under uncertainty,". Ben-Haim states (Ben-Haim 1999, pp. 271–2) that "robust reliability is emphatically not a [min-max] worst-case analysis".

Sniedovich has challenged the validity of info-gap theory for making decisions under severe uncertainty.

In the framework of classical decision theory, info-gap's robustness model can be construed as an instance of Wald's Maximin model and its opportuneness model is an instance of the classical Minimin model. Both operate in the neighborhood of an estimate of the parameter of interest whose true value is subject to severe uncertainty and therefore is likely to be substantially wrong. Moreover, the considerations brought to bear upon the decision process itself also originate in the locality of this unreliable estimate, and so may or may not be reflective of the entire range of decisions and uncertainties.

Background, working assumptions, and a look ahead edit

Now, as portrayed in the info-gap literature, Info-Gap was designed expressly as a methodology for solving decision problems that are subject to severe uncertainty. And what is more, its aim is to seek solutions that are robust.

Thus, to have a clear picture of info-gap's modus operandi and its role and place in decision theory and robust optimization, it is imperative to examine it within this context. In other words, it is necessary to establish info-gap's relation to classical decision theory and robust optimization. To this end, the following questions must be addressed:

  • What are the characteristics of decision problems that are subject to severe uncertainty?
  • What difficulties arise in the modelling and solution of such problems?
  • What type of robustness is sought?
  • How does info-gap theory address these issues?
  • In what way is info-gap decision theory similar to and/or different from other theories for decision under uncertainty?

Two important points need to be elucidated in this regard at the outset:

  • Considering the severity of the uncertainty that info-gap was designed to tackle, it is essential to clarify the difficulties posed by severe uncertainty.
  • Since info-gap is a non-probabilistic method that seeks to maximize robustness to uncertainty, it is imperative to compare it to the single most important "non-probabilistic" model in classical decision theory, namely Wald's Maximin paradigm (Wald 1945, 1950). After all, this paradigm has dominated the scene in classical decision theory for well over sixty years now.

So, first let us clarify the assumptions that are implied by severe uncertainty.

Working assumptions edit

Info-gap decision theory employs three simple constructs to capture the uncertainty associated with decision problems:

  1. A parameter   whose true value is subject to severe uncertainty.
  2. A region of uncertainty   where the true value of   lies.
  3. An estimate   of the true value of  .

It should be pointed out, though, that as such these constructs are generic, meaning that they can be employed to model situations where the uncertainty is not severe but mild, indeed very mild. So it is vital to be clear that to give apt expression to the severity of the uncertainty, in the Info-Gap framework these three constructs are given specific meaning.

 
Working Assumptions
  1. The region of uncertainty   is relatively large.
    In fact, Ben-Haim (2006, p. 210) indicates that in the context of info-gap decision theory most of the commonly encountered regions of uncertainty are unbounded.
  2. The estimate   is a poor approximation of the true value of  .
    That is, the estimate is a poor indication of the true value of   (Ben-Haim, 2006, p. 280) and is likely to be substantially wrong (Ben-Haim, 2006, p. 281).

In the picture   represents the true (unknown) value of  .

The point to note here is that conditions of severe uncertainty entail that the estimate   can—relatively speaking—be very distant from the true value  . This is particularly pertinent for methodologies, like info-gap, that seek robustness to uncertainty. Indeed, assuming otherwise would—methodologically speaking—be tantamount to engaging in wishful thinking.

Wald's Maximin paradigm edit

The basic idea behind this famous paradigm can be expressed in plain language as follows:

Maximin Rule

We are to adopt the alternative the worst outcome of which is superior to the worst outcome of the others.

Rawls[65](1971, p. 152)

Thus, according to this paradigm, in the framework of decision-making under severe uncertainty, the robustness of an alternative is a measure of how well this alternative can cope with the worst uncertain outcome that it can generate. Needless to say, this attitude towards severe uncertainty often leads to the selection of highly conservative alternatives. This is precisely the reason that this paradigm is not always a satisfactory methodology for decision-making under severe uncertainty (Tintner 1952).

As indicated in the overview, info-gap's robustness model is a Maximin model in disguise. More specifically, it is a simple instance of Wald's Maximin model where:

  1. The region of uncertainty associated with an alternative decision is an immediate neighborhood of the estimate  .
  2. The uncertain outcomes of an alternative are determined by a characteristic function of the performance requirement under consideration.

Thus, aside from the conservatism issue, a far more serious issue must be addressed. This is the validity issue arising from the local nature of info-gap's robustness analysis.

Local vs global robustness edit

 

The validity of the results generated by info-gap's robustness analysis are contingent on the quality of the estimate  . According to info-gap's own working assumptions, this estimate is poor and likely to be substantially wrong (Ben-Haim, 2006, p. 280-281).

The trouble with this feature of info-gap's robustness model is brought out more forcefully by the picture. The white circle represents the immediate neighborhood of the estimate   on which the Maximin analysis is conducted. Since the region of uncertainty is large and the quality of the estimate is poor, it is very likely that the true value of   is distant from the point at which the Maximin analysis is conducted.

So given the severity of the uncertainty under consideration, how valid/useful can this type of Maximin analysis really be?

What extent a local robustness analysis a la Maximin in the immediate neighborhood of a poor estimate can aptly represent a large region of uncertainty.

Robust optimization methods invariably take a far more global view of robustness. So much so that scenario planning and scenario generation are central issues in this area. This reflects a strong commitment to an adequate representation of the entire region of uncertainty in the definition of robustness and in the robustness analysis itself.

This has to do with the portrayal of info-gap's contribution to the state of the art in decision theory, and its role and place vis-a-vis other methodologies.

Role and place in decision theory edit

Info-gap is emphatic about its advancement of the state of the art in decision theory (color is used here for emphasis):

Info-gap decision theory is radically different from all current theories of decision under uncertainty. The difference originates in the modelling of uncertainty as an information gap rather than as a probability.

Ben-Haim (2006, p.xii)

In this book we concentrate on the fairly new concept of information-gap uncertainty, whose differences from more classical approaches to uncertainty are real and deep. Despite the power of classical decision theories, in many areas such as engineering, economics, management, medicine and public policy, a need has arisen for a different format for decisions based on severely uncertain evidence.

Ben-Haim (2006, p. 11)

These strong claims must be substantiated. In particular, a clear-cut, unequivocal answer must be given to the following question: in what way is info-gap's generic robustness model different, indeed radically different, from worst-case analysis a la Maximin?

Subsequent sections of this article describe various aspects of info-gap decision theory and its applications, how it proposes to cope with the working assumptions outlined above, the local nature of info-gap's robustness analysis and its intimate relationship with Wald's classical Maximin paradigm and worst-case analysis.

Invariance property edit

The main point to keep in mind here is that info-gap's raison d'être is to provide a methodology for decision under severe uncertainty. This means that its primary test would be in the efficacy of its handling of and coping with severe uncertainty. To this end it must be established first how Info-Gap's robustness/opportuneness models behave/fare, as the severity of the uncertainty is increased/decreased.

Second, it must be established whether info-gap's robustness/opportuneness models give adequate expression to the potential variability of the performance function over the entire region of uncertainty. This is particularly important because Info—Gap is usually concerned with relatively large, indeed unbounded, regions of uncertainty.

So, let   denote the total region of uncertainty and consider these key questions:

  • How does the robustness/opportuneness analysis respond to an increase/decrease in the size of  ?
  • How does an increase/decrease in the size of   affect the robustness or opportuneness of a decision?
  • How representative are the results generated by info-gap's robustness/opportuneness analysis of what occurs in the relatively large total region of uncertainty  ?
 

Suppose then that the robustness   has been computed for a decision   and it is observed that   where    for some  .

The question is then: how would the robustness of  , namely  , be affected if the region of uncertainty would be say, twice as large as  , or perhaps even 10 times as large as  ?

Consider then the following result which is a direct consequence of the local nature of info-gap's robustness/opportuneness analysis and the nesting property of info-gaps' regions of uncertainty (Sniedovich 2007):

Invariance theorem edit

The robustness of decision   is invariant with the size of the total region of uncertainty   for all   such that

(7)    for some                 

In other words, for any given decision, info-gap's analysis yields the same results for all total regions of uncertainty that contain  . This applies to both the robustness and opportuneness models.

This is illustrated in the picture: the robustness of a given decision does not change notwithstanding an increase in the region of uncertainty from   to  .

In short, by dint of focusing exclusively on the immediate neighborhood of the estimate   info-gap's robustness/opportuneness models are inherently local. For this reason they are -- in principle -- incapable of incorporating in the analysis of   and   regions of uncertainty that lie outside the neighborhoods   and   of the estimate  , respectively.

To illustrate, consider a simple numerical example where the total region of uncertainty is   the estimate is   and for some decision   we obtain  . The picture is this:

 

where the term "No man's land"   refers to the part of the total region of uncertainty that is outside the region  .

Note that in this case the robustness of decision   is based on its (worst-case) performance over no more than a minuscule part of the total region of uncertainty that is an immediate neighborhood of the estimate  . Since usually info-gap's total region of uncertainty is unbounded, this illustration represents a usual   case rather than an exception.

Info-gap's robustness/opportuneness are by definition local properties. As such they cannot assess the performance of decisions over the total region of uncertainty. For this reason it is not clear how Info-Gap's Robustness/Opportuneness models can provide a meaningful/sound/useful basis for decision under severe uncertainty where the estimate is poor and is likely to be substantially wrong.

This crucial issue is addressed in subsequent sections of this article.

Maximin/Minimin: playing robustness/opportuneness games with Nature edit

For well over sixty years now Wald's Maximin model has figured in classical decision theory and related areas – such as robust optimization - as the foremost non-probabilistic paradigm for modeling and treatment of severe uncertainty.

Info-gap is propounded (e.g. Ben-Haim 2001, 2006) as a new non-probabilistic theory that is radically different from all current decision theories for decision under uncertainty. So, it is imperative to examine in this discussion in what way, if any, is info-gap's robustness model radically different from Maximin. For one thing, there is a well-established assessment of the utility of Maximin. For example, Berger (Chapter 5)[66] suggests that even in situations where no prior information is available (a best case for Maximin), Maximin can lead to bad decision rules and be hard to implement. He recommends Bayesian methodology. And as indicated above,

It should also be remarked that the minimax principle even if it is applicable leads to an extremely conservative policy.

Tintner (1952, p. 25)[67]

However, quite apart from the ramifications that establishing this point might have for the utility of info-gaps' robustness model, the reason that it behooves us to clarify the relationship between info-gap and Maximin is the centrality of the latter in decision theory. After all, this is a major classical decision methodology. So, any theory claiming to furnish a new non-probabilistic methodology for decision under severe uncertainty would be expected to be compared to this stalwart of decision theory. And yet, not only is a comparison of info-gap's robustness model to Maximin absent from the three books expounding info-gap (Ben-Haim 1996, 2001, 2006), Maximin is not even mentioned in them as the major decision theoretic methodology for severe uncertainty that it is.

Elsewhere in the info-gap literature, one can find discussions dealing with similarities and differences between these two paradigms, as well as discussions on the relationship between info-gap and worst-case analysis,[7][16][35][37][53][68] However, the general impression is that the intimate connection between these two paradigms has not been identified. Indeed, the opposite is argued. For instance, Ben-Haim (2005[35]) argues that info-gap's robustness model is similar to Maximin but, is not a Maximin model.

The following quote eloquently expresses Ben-Haim's assessment of info-gap's relationship to Maximin and it provides ample motivation for the analysis that follows.

We note that robust reliability is emphatically not a worst-case analysis. In classical worst-case min-max analysis the designer minimizes the impact of the maximally damaging case. But an info-gap model of uncertainty is an unbounded family of nested sets:  , for all  . Consequently, there is no worst case: any adverse occurrence is less damaging than some other more extreme event occurring at a larger value of  . What Eq. (1) expresses is the greatest level of uncertainty consistent with no-failure. When the designer chooses q to maximize   he is maximizing his immunity to an unbounded ambient uncertainty. The closest this comes to "min-maxing" is that the design is chosen so that "bad" events (causing reward   less than  ) occur as "far away" as possible (beyond a maximized value of  ).

Ben-Haim, 1999, pp. 271–2[69]

The point to note here is that this statement misses the fact that the horizon of uncertainty   is bounded above (implicitly) by the performance requirement

 

and that info-gap conducts its worst-case analysis—one analysis at a time for a given    -- within each of the regions of uncertainty   .

In short, given the discussions in the info-gap literature on this issue, it is obvious that the kinship between info-gap's robustness model and Wald's Maximin model, as well as info-gap's kinship with other models of classical decision theory must be brought to light. So, the objective in this section is to place info-gap's robustness and opportuneness models in their proper context, namely within the wider frameworks of classical decision theory and robust optimization.

The discussion is based on the classical decision theoretic perspective outlined by Sniedovich (2007[70]) and on standard texts in this area (e.g. Resnik 1987,[63] French 1988[64]).

Certain parts of the exposition that follows have a mathematical slant.
This is unavoidable because info-gap's models are mathematical.

Generic models edit

The basic conceptual framework that classical decision theory provides for dealing with uncertainty is that of a two-player game. The two players are the decision maker (DM) and Nature, where Nature represents uncertainty. More specifically, Nature represents the DM's attitude towards uncertainty and risk.

Note that a clear distinction is made in this regard between a pessimistic decision maker and an optimistic decision maker, namely between a worst-case attitude and a best-case attitude. A pessimistic decision maker assumes that Nature plays against him whereas an optimistic decision maker assumes that Nature plays with him.

To express these intuitive notions mathematically, classical decision theory uses a simple model consisting of the following three constructs:

  • A set   representing the decision space available to the DM.
  • A set of sets   representing state spaces associated with the decisions in  .
  • A function   stipulating the outcomes generated by the decision-state pairs  .

The function   is called objective function, payoff function, return function, cost function etc.

The decision-making process (game) defined by these objects consists of three steps:

  • Step 1: The DM selects a decision  .
  • Step 2: In response, given  , Nature selects a state  .
  • Step 3: The outcome   is allotted to DM.

Note that in contrast to games considered in classical game theory, here the first player (DM) moves first so that the second player (Nature) knows what decision was selected by the first player prior to selecting her decision. Thus, the conceptual and technical complications regarding the existence of Nash equilibrium point are not pertinent here. Nature is not an independent player, it is a conceptual device describing the DM's attitude towards uncertainty and risk.

At first sight, the simplicity of this framework may strike one as naive. Yet, as attested by the variety of specific instances that it encompasses it is rich in possibilities, flexible, and versatile. For the purposes of this discussion it suffices to consider the following classical generic setup:

 

where   and   represent the DM's and Nature's optimality criteria, respectively, that is, each is equal to either   or  .

If   then the game is cooperative, and if   then the game is non-cooperative. Thus, this format represents four cases: two non-cooperative games (Maximin and Minimax) and two cooperative games (Minimin, and Maximax). The respective formulations are as follows:

 

Each case is specified by a pair of optimality criteria employed by DM and Nature. For example, Maximin depicts a situation where DM strives to maximize the outcome and Nature strives to minimize it. Similarly, the Minimin paradigm represents situations where both DM and Nature are striving to in minimize the outcome.

Of particular interest to this discussion are the Maximin and Minimin paradigms because they subsume info-gap's robustness and opportuneness models, respectively. So, here they are:

      Maximin Game:         
  • Step 1: The DM selects a decision   with a view to maximize the outcome  .
  • Step 2: In response, given  , Nature selects a state in   that minimizes   over  .
  • Step 3: The outcome   is allotted to DM.
      Minimin Game:         
  • Step 1: The DM selects a decision   with a view to minimizes the outcome  .
  • Step 2: In response, given  , Nature selects a state in   that minimizes   over  .
  • Step 3: The outcome   is allotted to DM.

With this in mind, consider now info-gap's robustness and opportuneness models.

Info-gap's robustness model edit

From a classical decision theoretic point of view info-gap's robustness model is a game between the DM and Nature, where the DM selects the value of   (aiming for the largest possible) whereas Nature selects the worst value of   in  . In this context the worst value of   pertaining to a given   pair is a   that violates the performance requirement  . This is achieved by minimizing   over  .

There are various ways to incorporate the DM's objective and Nature's antagonistic response in a single outcome. For instance, one can use the following characteristic function for this purpose:

 

Note that, as desired, for any triplet   of interest we have

 

hence from the DM's point of view satisficing the performance constraint is equivalent to maximizing    .

In short,

      Info-gap's Maximin Robustness Game for decision  :         
  • Step 1: The DM selects a horizon of uncertainty   with a view to maximize the outcome  .
  • Step 2: In response, given  , Nature selects a   that minimizes   over  .
  • Step 3: The outcome   is allotted to DM.

Clearly, the DM's optimal alternative is to select the largest value of   such that the worst   satisfies the performance requirement.

Maximin Theorem edit

As shown in Sniedovich (2007),[47] Info-gap's robustness model is a simple instance of Wald's maximin model. Specifically,

info, decision, theory, this, article, multiple, issues, please, help, improve, discuss, these, issues, talk, page, learn, when, remove, these, template, messages, this, article, need, reorganization, comply, with, wikipedia, layout, guidelines, please, help, . This article has multiple issues Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page Learn how and when to remove these template messages This article may be in need of reorganization to comply with Wikipedia s layout guidelines Please help by editing the article to make improvements to the overall structure April 2012 Learn how and when to remove this message This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Info gap decision theory news newspapers books scholar JSTOR April 2012 Learn how and when to remove this message An editor has expressed concern that this article may have a number of irrelevant and questionable citations Please help improve this article by verifying these references and challenge or remove any that are not reliable or do not support the article April 2012 Learn how and when to remove this message This article may contain an excessive amount of intricate detail that may interest only a particular audience Please help by spinning off or relocating any relevant information and removing excessive detail that may be against Wikipedia s inclusion policy June 2014 Learn how and when to remove this message This article is written like a personal reflection personal essay or argumentative essay that states a Wikipedia editor s personal feelings or presents an original argument about a topic Please help improve it by rewriting it in an encyclopedic style October 2019 Learn how and when to remove this message Learn how and when to remove this message Info gap decision theory seeks to optimize robustness to failure under severe uncertainty 1 2 in particular applying sensitivity analysis of the stability radius type 3 to perturbations in the value of a given estimate of the parameter of interest It has some connections with Wald s maximin model some authors distinguish them others consider them instances of the same principle It has been developed by Yakov Ben Haim 4 and has found many applications and described as a theory for decision making under severe uncertainty It has been criticized as unsuited for this purpose and alternatives proposed including such classical approaches as robust optimization Contents 1 Summary 1 1 Models 1 2 Comparison with classical decision theory 2 Basic example budget 2 1 Info gap models 3 Motivation 4 Example resource allocation 4 1 Resource allocation 4 2 Introducing uncertainty 4 3 Robustness 4 4 Opportuneness 4 5 Treatment of severe uncertainty 5 Uncertainty models 5 1 Sublevel sets 6 Robustness and opportuneness 6 1 Robustness and opportuneness functions 6 2 Optimization 7 Decision rules 7 1 Robust satisficing 7 2 Opportune windfalling 8 Applications 8 1 Engineering 8 2 Biology 8 3 Project management 9 Limitations 9 1 Disclaimer and summary 10 Criticism 10 1 Maximin 10 2 Stability radius 11 Discussion 11 1 Satisficing and bounded rationality 12 Alternatives 12 1 Sensitivity analysis 12 2 Robust optimization 12 3 Comparative analysis 12 3 1 Maximin 12 3 2 Bayesian analysis 13 Classical decision theory perspective 13 1 Background working assumptions and a look ahead 13 1 1 Working assumptions 13 1 2 Wald s Maximin paradigm 13 1 3 Local vs global robustness 13 1 4 Role and place in decision theory 13 2 Invariance property 13 2 1 Invariance theorem 13 3 Maximin Minimin playing robustness opportuneness games with Nature 13 3 1 Generic models 13 3 2 Info gap s robustness model 13 3 3 Maximin Theorem 13 3 4 Info gap s opportuneness model 13 3 5 Mathematical programming formulations 13 3 6 Summary 13 4 Treasure hunt 13 5 Notes on the art of math modeling 13 5 1 Constraint satisficing vs payoff optimization 13 5 2 The role of min and max 13 5 3 The nature of the info gap maximin minimin connection 13 5 4 Other formulations 13 5 5 Simplifications 13 5 6 Summary 14 See also 15 Notes 16 References 17 External linksSummary editInfo gap is a theory it assists in decisions under uncertainty It does this by using models each built on the last One begins with a model for the situation where some parameter or parameters are unknown Then takes an estimate for the parameter and one analyzes how sensitive the outcomes under the model are to the error in this estimate Uncertainty model Starting from the estimate an uncertainty model measures how far away other values of the parameter are as uncertainty increases the set of values increase Robustness opportuneness model Given an uncertainty model then for each decision how uncertain can you be and be confident succeeding robustness Also given a windfall how uncertain must you be for this result to be plausible opportuneness Decision making model One optimizes the robustness on the basis of the model Given an outcome which decision can stand the most uncertainty and give the outcome Also given a windfall which decision requires the least uncertainty for the outcome Models edit Info gap theory models uncertainty as subsets U a u displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp around a point estimate u displaystyle tilde u nbsp the estimate is accurate and uncertainty increases in general without bound The uncertainty measures the distance between an estimate and a plausibility providing an intermediate measure between a point the point estimate and all plausibilities and giving a sensitivity measure what is the margin of error Info gap analysis gives answers to such questions as under what level of uncertainty can specific requirements be reliably assured robustness and what level of uncertainty is necessary to achieve certain windfalls opportuneness It can be used for satisficing as an alternative to optimizing in the presence of uncertainty or bounded rationality see robust optimization for an alternative approach Comparison with classical decision theory edit Further information on Alternatives Alternatives In contrast to probabilistic decision theory info gap analysis does not use probability distributions it measures the deviation of errors differences between the parameter and the estimate but not the probability of outcomes in particular the estimate u displaystyle tilde u nbsp is in no sense more or less likely than other points as info gap does not use probability Info gap by not using probability distributions is robust in that it is not sensitive to assumptions on probabilities of outcomes However the model of uncertainty does include a notion of closer and more distant outcomes and thus includes some assumptions and is not as robust as simply considering all possible outcomes as in minimax Further it considers a fixed universe U displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp so it is not robust to unexpected not modeled events The connection to minimax analysis has occasioned some controversy Ben Haim 1999 pp 271 2 argues that info gap s robustness analysis while similar in some ways is not minimax worst case analysis as it does not evaluate decisions over all possible outcomes while Sniedovich 2007 argues that the robustness analysis can be seen as an example of maximin not minimax This is discussed in criticism below and elaborated in the classical decision theory perspective Basic example budget editAs a simple example consider a worker They expect to make 20 per week while if they make under 15 they will be unable to work and will sleep in the street otherwise they can afford a night s entertainment Using absolute error model where u 20 displaystyle tilde u 20 nbsp one can say the robustness is 15 and opportuneness is 20 if they make 20 they will not sleep rough nor feast and if they make within 20 of 200 But if they erred by 20 they may sleep rough while for more than 30 they may find themselves dining in opulence As stated this example is only descriptive and does not enable any decision making in applications one considers alternative decision rules and often situations with more complex uncertainty The worker is thinking of moving elsewhere where accommodation is cheaper They will earn 26 per week but hostels costs 20 while entertainment still costs 170 In that case the robustness will be 24 and the opportuneness will be 43 The second case has less robustness and less opportuneness But measuring uncertainty by relative error robustness is 20 and opportuneness is 23 while in the other robustness is 38 and opportuneness is 60 so moving is less opportune Info gap models edit Info gap can be applied to spaces of functions in that case the uncertain parameter is a function u x displaystyle u x nbsp with estimate u x displaystyle tilde u x nbsp and the nested subsets are sets of functions One way to describe such a set of functions is by requiring values of u to be close to values of u displaystyle tilde u nbsp for all x using a family of info gap models on the values For example the above fraction error model for values becomes the fractional error model for functions by adding a parameter x to the definition U a u u x u x u x a u x for all x X a 0 displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u left u x u x tilde u x leq alpha tilde u x mbox for all x in X right alpha geq 0 nbsp More generally if U a y displaystyle U alpha y nbsp is a family of info gap models of values then one obtains an info gap model of functions in the same way U a u u x u x U a u x for all x X a 0 displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u left u x u x in U alpha tilde u x mbox for all x in X right alpha geq 0 nbsp Motivation editIt is common to make decisions under uncertainty note 1 What can be done to make good or at least the best possible decisions under conditions of uncertainty Info gap robustness analysis evaluates each feasible decision by asking how much deviation from an estimate of a parameter value function or set is permitted and yet guarantee acceptable performance In everyday terms the robustness of a decision is set by the size of deviation from an estimate that still leads to performance within requirements when using that decision It is sometimes difficult to judge how much robustness is needed or sufficient However according to info gap theory the ranking of feasible decisions in terms of their degree of robustness is independent of such judgments Info gap theory also proposes an opportuneness function which evaluates the potential for windfall outcomes resulting from favorable uncertainty Example resource allocation editResource allocation edit Suppose you are a project manager supervising two teams orange and white Some revenue at the end of the year will be achieved You have a limited timescale and you aim to decide how to space these resources between the orange and white so that the total revenues are large Introducing uncertainty edit The actual revenue may be different For uncertainty level we can define an envelope Lower uncertainty would correspond to a smaller envelope These envelopes are called info gap models of uncertainty since they describe one s understanding of the uncertainty surrounding the revenue functions We can find a model for the total revenue Figure 5 shows the info gap model of the total revenue Robustness edit High revenues would typically earn a project manager the senior management s respect but if the total revenues are below a certain threshold it will cost said project manager s job We will define such a threshold as a critical revenue since total revenues beneath the critical revenue will be considered as failure This is shown in Figure 6 If the uncertainty will increase the envelope of uncertainty will become more inclusive to include instances of the total revenue function that for the specific allocation yields a revenue smaller than the critical revenue The robustness measures the immunity of a decision to failure A robust satisficer is a decision maker that prefers choices with higher robustness If for some allocation q displaystyle q nbsp the correlation between the critical revenue and the robustness is illustrated the result is a graph somewhat similar to that in Figure 7 This graph called robustness curve of allocation q displaystyle q nbsp has two important features that are common to most robustness curves The curve is non increasing This captures the notion that when higher requirements higher critical revenue are in place failure to meet the target is more likely lower robustness This is the tradeoff between quality and robustness At the nominal revenue that is when the critical revenue equals the revenue under the nominal model the estimate of the revenue functions the robustness is zero This is since a slight deviation from the estimate may decrease the total revenue The decision depends on the value of failure Opportuneness edit As well as the threat of losing your job the senior management offers you a carrot if the revenues are higher than some revenue you will be rewarded If the uncertainty will decrease the envelope of uncertainty will become less inclusive to exclude all instances of the total revenue function that for the specific allocation yields a revenue higher than the windfall revenue If for some allocation q displaystyle q nbsp we will illustrate the correlation between the windfall revenue and the robustness we will have a graph somewhat similar to Figure 10 This graph called opportuneness curve of allocation q displaystyle q nbsp has two important features that are common to most opportuneness curves The curve is non decreasing This captures the notion that when we have higher requirements higher windfall revenue we are more immune to failure higher opportuneness which is less desirable That is we need a more substantial deviation from the estimate in order to achieve our ambitious goal This is the tradeoff between quality and opportuneness At the nominal revenue that is when the critical revenue equals the revenue under the nominal model our estimate of the revenue functions the opportuneness is zero This is since no deviation from the estimate is needed in order to achieve the windfall revenue Treatment of severe uncertainty edit Note that in addition to the results generated by the estimate two possible true values of the revenue are also displayed at a distance from the estimate As indicated by the picture since info gap robustness model applies its Maximin analysis in an immediate neighborhood of the estimate there is no assurance that the analysis is in fact conducted in the neighborhood of the true value of the revenue In fact under conditions of severe uncertainty this methodologically speaking is very unlikely This raises the question how valid useful meaningful are the results Aren t we sweeping the severity of the uncertainty under the carpet For example suppose that a given allocation is found to be very fragile in the neighborhood of the estimate Does this mean that this allocation is also fragile elsewhere in the region of uncertainty Conversely what guarantee is there that an allocation that is robust in the neighborhood of the estimate is also robust elsewhere in the region of uncertainty indeed in the neighborhood of the true value of the revenue More fundamentally given that the results generated by info gap are based on a local revenue allocation analysis in the neighborhood of an estimate that is likely to be substantially wrong we have no other choice methodologically speaking but to assume that the results generated by this analysis are equally likely to be substantially wrong In other words in accordance with the universal Garbage In Garbage Out Axiom we have to assume that the quality of the results generated by info gap s analysis is only as good as the quality of the estimate on which the results are based The picture speaks for itself What emerges then is that info gap theory is yet to explain in what way if any it actually attempts to deal with the severity of the uncertainty under consideration Subsequent sections of this article will address this severity issue and its methodological and practical implications A more detailed analysis of an illustrative numerical investment problem of this type can be found in Sniedovich 2007 Uncertainty models editInfo gaps are quantified by info gap models of uncertainty An info gap model is an unbounded family of nested sets For example a frequently encountered example is a family of nested ellipsoids all having the same shape The structure of the sets in an info gap model derives from the information about the uncertainty In general terms the structure of an info gap model of uncertainty is chosen to define the smallest or strictest family of sets whose elements are consistent with the prior information Since there is usually no known worst case the family of sets may be unbounded A common example of an info gap model is the fractional error model The best estimate of an uncertain function u x displaystyle u x nbsp is u x displaystyle tilde u x nbsp but the fractional error of this estimate is unknown The following unbounded family of nested sets of functions is a fractional error info gap model U a u u x u x u x a u x for all x a 0 displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u left u x u x tilde u x leq alpha tilde u x mbox for all x right alpha geq 0 nbsp At any horizon of uncertainty a displaystyle alpha nbsp the set U a u displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp contains all functions u x displaystyle u x nbsp whose fractional deviation from u x displaystyle tilde u x nbsp is no greater than a displaystyle alpha nbsp However the horizon of uncertainty is unknown so the info gap model is an unbounded family of sets and there is no worst case or greatest deviation There are many other types of info gap models of uncertainty All info gap models obey two basic axioms Nesting The info gap model U a u displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp is nested if a lt a displaystyle alpha lt alpha prime nbsp implies that U a u U a u displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u subseteq mathcal U alpha prime tilde u nbsp dd Contraction The info gap model U 0 u displaystyle mathcal U 0 tilde u nbsp is a singleton set containing its center point U 0 u u displaystyle mathcal U 0 tilde u tilde u nbsp dd The nesting axiom imposes the property of clustering which is characteristic of info gap uncertainty Furthermore the nesting axiom implies that the uncertainty sets U a u displaystyle mathcal U alpha u nbsp become more inclusive as a displaystyle alpha nbsp grows thus endowing a displaystyle alpha nbsp with its meaning as a horizon of uncertainty The contraction axiom implies that at horizon of uncertainty zero the estimate u displaystyle tilde u nbsp is correct Recall that the uncertain element u displaystyle u nbsp may be a parameter vector function or set The info gap model is then an unbounded family of nested sets of parameters vectors functions or sets Sublevel sets edit For a fixed point estimate u displaystyle tilde u nbsp an info gap model is often equivalent to a function ϕ U 0 displaystyle phi colon mathfrak U to 0 infty nbsp defined as ϕ u min a u U a u displaystyle phi u min alpha mid u in mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp meaning the uncertainty of a point u is the minimum uncertainty such that u is in the set with that uncertainty In this case the family of sets U a u displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp can be recovered as the sublevel sets of ϕ displaystyle phi nbsp U a u ϕ 1 0 a displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u phi 1 0 alpha nbsp meaning the nested subset with horizon of uncertainty a displaystyle alpha nbsp consists of all points with uncertainty less than or equal to a displaystyle alpha nbsp Conversely given a function ϕ U 0 displaystyle phi colon mathfrak U to 0 infty nbsp satisfying the axiom ϕ 1 0 u displaystyle phi 1 0 tilde u nbsp equivalently ϕ u 0 displaystyle phi u 0 nbsp if and only if u u displaystyle u tilde u nbsp it defines an info gap model via the sublevel sets For instance if the region of uncertainty is a metric space then the uncertainty function can simply be the distance ϕ u d u u displaystyle phi u d tilde u u nbsp so the nested subsets are simply U a u u d u u a displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u u mid d tilde u u leq alpha nbsp This always defines an info gap model as distances are always non negative axiom of non negativity and satisfies ϕ 1 0 u displaystyle phi 1 0 tilde u nbsp info gap axiom of contraction because the distance between two points is zero if and only if they are equal the identity of indiscernibles nesting follows by construction of sublevel set Not all info gap models arise as sublevel sets for instance if u 1 U a u displaystyle u 1 in mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp for all a gt 1 displaystyle alpha gt 1 nbsp but not for a 1 displaystyle alpha 1 nbsp it has uncertainty just more than 1 then the minimum above is not defined one can replace it by an infimum but then the resulting sublevel sets will not agree with the infogap model u 1 ϕ 1 0 1 displaystyle u 1 in phi 1 0 1 nbsp but u 1 U 1 u displaystyle u 1 not in mathcal U 1 tilde u nbsp The effect of this distinction is very minor however as it modifies sets by less than changing the horizon of uncertainty by any positive number ϵ displaystyle epsilon nbsp however small Robustness and opportuneness editUncertainty may be either pernicious or propitious That is uncertain variations may be either adverse or favorable Adversity entails the possibility of failure while favorability is the opportunity for sweeping success Info gap decision theory is based on quantifying these two aspects of uncertainty and choosing an action which addresses one or the other or both of them simultaneously The pernicious and propitious aspects of uncertainty are quantified by two immunity functions the robustness function expresses the immunity to failure while the opportuneness function expresses the immunity to windfall gain Robustness and opportuneness functions edit The robustness function expresses the greatest level of uncertainty at which failure cannot occur the opportuneness function is the least level of uncertainty which entails the possibility of sweeping success The robustness and opportuneness functions address respectively the pernicious and propitious facets of uncertainty Let q displaystyle q nbsp be a decision vector of parameters such as design variables time of initiation model parameters or operational options We can verbally express the robustness and opportuneness functions as the maximum or minimum of a set of values of the uncertainty parameter a displaystyle alpha nbsp of an info gap model a q max a minimal requirements are always satisfied displaystyle hat alpha q max alpha mbox minimal requirements are always satisfied nbsp robustness 1a b q min a sweeping success is possible displaystyle hat beta q min alpha mbox sweeping success is possible nbsp opportuneness 2a Formally a q max a minimal requirements are satisfied for all u U a u displaystyle hat alpha q max alpha mbox minimal requirements are satisfied for all u in mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp robustness 1b b q min a windfall is achieved for at least one u U a u displaystyle hat beta q min alpha mbox windfall is achieved for at least one u in mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp opportuneness 2b We can read eq 1 as follows The robustness a q displaystyle hat alpha q nbsp of decision vector q displaystyle q nbsp is the greatest value of the horizon of uncertainty a displaystyle alpha nbsp for which specified minimal requirements are always satisfied a q displaystyle hat alpha q nbsp expresses robustness the degree of resistance to uncertainty and immunity against failure so a large value of a q displaystyle hat alpha q nbsp is desirable Robustness is defined as a worst case scenario up to the horizon of uncertainty how large can the horizon of uncertainty be and still even in the worst case achieve the critical level of outcome Eq 2 states that the opportuneness b q displaystyle hat beta q nbsp is the least level of uncertainty a displaystyle alpha nbsp which must be tolerated in order to enable the possibility of sweeping success as a result of decisions q displaystyle q nbsp b q displaystyle hat beta q nbsp is the immunity against windfall reward so a small value of b q displaystyle hat beta q nbsp is desirable A small value of b q displaystyle hat beta q nbsp reflects the opportune situation that great reward is possible even in the presence of little ambient uncertainty Opportuneness is defined as a best case scenario up to the horizon of uncertainty how small can the horizon of uncertainty be and still in the best case achieve the windfall reward The immunity functions a q displaystyle hat alpha q nbsp and b q displaystyle hat beta q nbsp are complementary and are defined in an anti symmetric sense Thus bigger is better for a q displaystyle hat alpha q nbsp while big is bad for b q displaystyle hat beta q nbsp The immunity functions robustness and opportuneness are the basic decision functions in info gap decision theory Optimization edit The robustness function involves a maximization but not of the performance or outcome of the decision in general the outcome could be arbitrarily bad Rather it maximizes the level of uncertainty that would be required for the outcome to fail The greatest tolerable uncertainty is found at which decision q displaystyle q nbsp satisfices the performance at a critical survival level One may establish one s preferences among the available actions q q displaystyle q q prime ldots nbsp according to their robustnesses a q a q displaystyle hat alpha q hat alpha q prime ldots nbsp whereby larger robustness engenders higher preference In this way the robustness function underlies a satisficing decision algorithm which maximizes the immunity to pernicious uncertainty The opportuneness function in eq 2 involves a minimization however not as might be expected of the damage which can accrue from unknown adverse events The least horizon of uncertainty is sought at which decision q displaystyle q nbsp enables but does not necessarily guarantee large windfall gain Unlike the robustness function the opportuneness function does not satisfice it windfalls Windfalling preferences are those which prefer actions for which the opportuneness function takes a small value When b q displaystyle hat beta q nbsp is used to choose an action q displaystyle q nbsp one is windfalling by optimizing the opportuneness from propitious uncertainty in an attempt to enable highly ambitious goals or rewards Given a scalar reward function R q u displaystyle R q u nbsp depending on the decision vector q displaystyle q nbsp and the info gap uncertain function u displaystyle u nbsp the minimal requirement in eq 1 is that the reward R q u displaystyle R q u nbsp be no less than a critical value r c displaystyle r rm c nbsp Likewise the sweeping success in eq 2 is attainment of a wildest dream level of reward r w displaystyle r rm w nbsp which is much greater than r c displaystyle r rm c nbsp Usually neither of these threshold values r c displaystyle r rm c nbsp and r w displaystyle r rm w nbsp is chosen irrevocably before performing the decision analysis Rather these parameters enable the decision maker to explore a range of options In any case the windfall reward r w displaystyle r rm w nbsp is greater usually much greater than the critical reward r c displaystyle r rm c nbsp r w gt r c displaystyle r rm w gt r rm c nbsp The robustness and opportuneness functions of eqs 1 and 2 can now be expressed more explicitly a q r c max a r c min u U a u R q u displaystyle hat alpha q r rm c max left alpha r rm c leq min u in mathcal U alpha tilde u R q u right nbsp 3 b q r w min a r w max u U a u R q u displaystyle hat beta q r rm w min left alpha r rm w leq max u in mathcal U alpha tilde u R q u right nbsp 4 a q r c displaystyle hat alpha q r rm c nbsp is the greatest level of uncertainty consistent with guaranteed reward no less than the critical reward r c displaystyle r rm c nbsp while b q r w displaystyle hat beta q r rm w nbsp is the least level of uncertainty which must be accepted in order to facilitate but not guarantee windfall as great as r w displaystyle r rm w nbsp The complementary or anti symmetric structure of the immunity functions is evident from eqs 3 and 4 These definitions can be modified to handle multi criterion reward functions Likewise analogous definitions apply when R q u displaystyle R q u nbsp is a loss rather than a reward Decision rules editBased on these function one can then decided on a course of action by optimizing for uncertainty choose the decision which is most robust can withstand the greatest uncertainty satisficing or choose the decision which requires the least uncertainty to achieve a windfall Formally optimizing for robustness or optimizing for opportuneness yields a preference relation on the set of decisions and the decision rule is the optimize with respect to this preference In the below let Q displaystyle mathcal Q nbsp be the set of all available or feasible decision vectors q displaystyle q nbsp Robust satisficing edit The robustness function generates robust satisficing preferences on the options decisions are ranked in increasing order of robustness for a given critical reward i e by a q r c displaystyle hat alpha q r rm c nbsp value meaning q r q displaystyle q succ rm r q prime nbsp if a q r c gt a q r c displaystyle hat alpha q r rm c gt hat alpha q prime r rm c nbsp A robust satisficing decision is one which maximizes the robustness and satisfices the performance at the critical level r c displaystyle r rm c nbsp Denote the maximum robustness by a displaystyle hat alpha nbsp formally a r c displaystyle hat alpha r rm c nbsp for the maximum robustness for a given critical reward and the corresponding decision or decisions by q c displaystyle hat q rm c nbsp formally q c r c displaystyle hat q rm c r rm c nbsp the critical optimizing action for a given level of critical reward a r c max q Q a q r c q c r c arg max q Q a q r c displaystyle begin aligned hat alpha r rm c amp max q in mathcal Q hat alpha q r rm c hat q rm c r rm c amp arg max q in mathcal Q hat alpha q r rm c end aligned nbsp Usually though not invariably the robust satisficing action q c r c displaystyle hat q rm c r rm c nbsp depends on the critical reward r c displaystyle r rm c nbsp Opportune windfalling edit Conversely one may optimize opportuneness the opportuneness function generates opportune windfalling preferences on the options decisions are ranked in decreasing order of opportuneness for a given windfall reward i e by b q r c displaystyle hat beta q r rm c nbsp value meaning q w q displaystyle q succ rm w q prime nbsp if b q r w lt b q r w displaystyle hat beta q r rm w lt hat beta q prime r rm w nbsp The opportune windfalling decision q w r w displaystyle hat q rm w r rm w nbsp minimizes the opportuneness function on the set of available decisions Denote the minimum opportuneness by b displaystyle hat beta nbsp formally b r w displaystyle hat beta r rm w nbsp for the minimum opportuneness for a given windfall reward and the corresponding decision or decisions by q w displaystyle hat q rm w nbsp formally q w r w displaystyle hat q rm w r rm w nbsp the windfall optimizing action for a given level of windfall reward b r w min q Q b q r w q w r w arg min q Q b q r w displaystyle begin aligned hat beta r rm w amp min q in mathcal Q hat beta q r rm w hat q rm w r rm w amp arg min q in mathcal Q hat beta q r rm w end aligned nbsp The two preference rankings as well as the corresponding the optimal decisions q c r c displaystyle hat q rm c r rm c nbsp and q w r w displaystyle hat q rm w r rm w nbsp may be different and may vary depending on the values of r c displaystyle r rm c nbsp and r w displaystyle r rm w nbsp Applications editInfo gap theory has generated a lot of literature Info gap theory has been studied or applied in a range of applications including engineering 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 12 13 14 15 16 17 18 biological conservation 19 20 21 22 23 24 25 26 27 28 29 30 theoretical biology 31 homeland security 32 economics 33 34 35 project management 36 37 38 and statistics 39 Foundational issues related to info gap theory have also been studied 40 41 42 43 44 45 The remainder of this section describes in a little more detail the kind of uncertainties addressed by info gap theory Although many published works are mentioned below no attempt is made here to present insights from these papers The emphasis is not upon elucidation of the concepts of info gap theory but upon the context where it is used and the goals Engineering edit A typical engineering application is the vibration analysis of a cracked beam where the location size shape and orientation of the crack is unknown and greatly influence the vibration dynamics 9 Very little is usually known about these spatial and geometrical uncertainties The info gap analysis allows one to model these uncertainties and to determine the degree of robustness to these uncertainties of properties such as vibration amplitude natural frequencies and natural modes of vibration Another example is the structural design of a building subject to uncertain loads such as from wind or earthquakes 8 10 The response of the structure depends strongly on the spatial and temporal distribution of the loads However storms and earthquakes are highly idiosyncratic events and the interaction between the event and the structure involves very site specific mechanical properties which are rarely known The info gap analysis enables the design of the structure to enhance structural immunity against uncertain deviations from design base or estimated worst case loads citation needed Another engineering application involves the design of a neural net for detecting faults in a mechanical system based on real time measurements A major difficulty is that faults are highly idiosyncratic so that training data for the neural net will tend to differ substantially from data obtained from real time faults after the net has been trained The info gap robustness strategy enables one to design the neural net to be robust to the disparity between training data and future real events 11 13 Biology edit The conservation biologist faces info gaps in using biological models They use info gap robustness curves to select among management options for spruce budworm populations in Eastern Canada Burgman 46 uses the fact that the robustness curves of different alternatives can intersect Project management edit Project management is another area where info gap uncertainty is common The project manager often has very limited information about the duration and cost of some of the tasks in the project and info gap robustness can assist in project planning and integration 37 Financial economics is another area where the future is fraught with surprises which may be either pernicious or propitious Info gap robustness and opportuneness analyses can assist in portfolio design credit rationing and other applications 33 Limitations editIn applying info gap theory one must remain aware of certain limitations Firstly info gap makes assumptions namely on universe in question and the degree of uncertainty the info gap model is a model of degrees of uncertainty or similarity of various assumptions within a given universe Info gap does not make probability assumptions within this universe it is non probabilistic but does quantify a notion of distance from the estimate In brief info gap makes fewer assumptions than a probabilistic method but does make some assumptions For instance a simple model of daily stock market returns which by definition fall in the range 100 displaystyle 100 infty nbsp may include extreme moves such as Black Monday 1987 but might not model the market breakdowns following the September 11 attacks it considers the known unknowns not the unknown unknowns This is a general criticism of much decision theory and is by no means specific to info gap but info gap is not immune to it Secondly there is no natural scale is uncertainty of a 1 displaystyle alpha 1 nbsp small or large Different models of uncertainty give different scales and require judgment and understanding of the domain and the model of uncertainty Similarly measuring differences between outcomes requires judgment and understanding of the domain Thirdly if the universe under consideration is larger than a significant horizon of uncertainty and outcomes for these distant points are significantly different from points near the estimate then conclusions of robustness or opportuneness analyses will generally be one must be very confident of one s assumptions else outcomes may be expected to vary significantly from projections a cautionary conclusion Disclaimer and summary edit The robustness and opportuneness functions can inform decision For example a change in decision increasing robustness may increase or decrease opportuneness From a subjective stance robustness and opportuneness both trade off against aspiration for outcome robustness and opportuneness deteriorate as the decision maker s aspirations increase Robustness is zero for model best anticipated outcomes Robustness curves for alternative decisions may cross as a function of aspiration implying reversal of preference Various theorems identify conditions where larger info gap robustness implies larger probability of success regardless of the underlying probability distribution However these conditions are technical and do not translate into any common sense verbal recommendations limiting such applications of info gap theory by non experts Criticism editA general criticism of non probabilistic decision rules discussed in detail at decision theory alternatives to probability theory is that optimal decision rules formally admissible decision rules can always be derived by probabilistic methods with a suitable utility function and prior distribution this is the statement of the complete class theorems and thus that non probabilistic methods such as info gap are unnecessary and do not yield new or better decision rules A more general criticism of decision making under uncertainty is the impact of outsized unexpected events ones that are not captured by the model This is discussed particularly in black swan theory and info gap used in isolation is vulnerable to this as are a fortiori all decision theories that use a fixed universe of possibilities notably probabilistic ones Sniedovich 47 raises two points to info gap decision theory one substantive one scholarly 1 the info gap uncertainty model is flawed and oversold One should consider the range of possibilities not its subsets Sniedovich argues that info gap decision theory is therefore a voodoo decision theory 2 info gap is maximin Ben Haim states Ben Haim 1999 pp 271 2 that robust reliability is emphatically not a min max worst case analysis Note that Ben Haim compares info gap to minimax while Sniedovich considers it a case of maximin Sniedovich has challenged the validity of info gap theory for making decisions under severe uncertainty Sniedovich notes that the info gap robustness function is local to the region around u displaystyle displaystyle tilde u nbsp where u displaystyle displaystyle tilde u nbsp is likely to be substantially in error Maximin edit Symbolically max a displaystyle alpha nbsp assuming min worst case outcome or maximin In other words while it is not a maximin analysis of outcome over the universe of uncertainty it is a maximin analysis over a properly construed decision space Ben Haim argues that info gap s robustness model is not min max maximin analysis because it is not worst case analysis of outcomes it is a satisficing model not an optimization model a straightforward maximin analysis would consider worst case outcomes over the entire space which since uncertainty is often potentially unbounded would yield an unbounded bad worst case Stability radius edit Sniedovich 3 has shown that info gap s robustness model is a simple stability radius model namely a local stability model of the generic form r p max r 0 p P s p B r p displaystyle hat rho tilde p max rho geq 0 p in P s forall p in B rho tilde p nbsp where B r p displaystyle B rho tilde p nbsp denotes a ball of radius r displaystyle rho nbsp centered at p displaystyle tilde p nbsp and P s displaystyle P s nbsp denotes the set of values of p displaystyle p nbsp that satisfy pre determined stability conditions In other words info gap s robustness model is a stability radius model characterized by a stability requirement of the form r c R q p displaystyle r c leq R q p nbsp Since stability radius models are designed for the analysis of small perturbations in a given nominal value of a parameter Sniedovich 3 argues that info gap s robustness model is unsuitable for the treatment of severe uncertainty characterized by a poor estimate and a vast uncertainty space Discussion editSatisficing and bounded rationality edit It is correct that the info gap robustness function is local and has restricted quantitative value in some cases However a major purpose of decision analysis is to provide focus for subjective judgments That is regardless of the formal analysis a framework for discussion is provided Without entering into any particular framework or characteristics of frameworks in general discussion follows about proposals for such frameworks Simon 48 introduced the idea of bounded rationality Limitations on knowledge understanding and computational capability constrain the ability of decision makers to identify optimal choices Simon advocated satisficing rather than optimizing seeking adequate rather than optimal outcomes given available resources Schwartz 49 Conlisk 50 and others discuss extensive evidence for the phenomenon of bounded rationality among human decision makers as well as for the advantages of satisficing when knowledge and understanding are deficient The info gap robustness function provides a means of implementing a satisficing strategy under bounded rationality For instance in discussing bounded rationality and satisficing in conservation and environmental management Burgman notes that Info gap theory can function sensibly when there are severe knowledge gaps The info gap robustness and opportuneness functions provide a formal framework to explore the kinds of speculations that occur intuitively when examining decision options 51 Burgman then proceeds to develop an info gap robust satisficing strategy for protecting the endangered orange bellied parrot Similarly Vinot Cogan and Cipolla 52 discuss engineering design and note that the downside of a model based analysis lies in the knowledge that the model behavior is only an approximation to the real system behavior Hence the question of the honest designer how sensitive is my measure of design success to uncertainties in my system representation It is evident that if model based analysis is to be used with any level of confidence then one must attempt to satisfy an acceptable sub optimal level of performance while remaining maximally robust to the system uncertainties 52 They proceed to develop an info gap robust satisficing design procedure for an aerospace application Alternatives editOf course decision in the face of uncertainty is nothing new and attempts to deal with it have a long history A number of authors have noted and discussed similarities and differences between info gap robustness and minimax or worst case methods 7 16 35 37 53 54 Sniedovich 47 has demonstrated formally that the info gap robustness function can be represented as a maximin optimization and is thus related to Wald s minimax theory Sniedovich 47 has claimed that info gap s robustness analysis is conducted in the neighborhood of an estimate that is likely to be substantially wrong concluding that the resulting robustness function is equally likely to be substantially wrong On the other hand the estimate is the best one has so it is useful to know if it can err greatly and still yield an acceptable outcome This critical question clearly raises the issue of whether robustness as defined by info gap theory is qualified to judge whether confidence is warranted 5 55 56 and how it compares to methods used to inform decisions under uncertainty using considerations not limited to the neighborhood of a bad initial guess Answers to these questions vary with the particular problem at hand Some general comments follow Sensitivity analysis edit Main article Sensitivity analysis Sensitivity analysis how sensitive conclusions are to input assumptions can be performed independently of a model of uncertainty most simply one may take two different assumed values for an input and compares the conclusions From this perspective info gap can be seen as a technique of sensitivity analysis though by no means the only Robust optimization edit Main article Robust optimization The robust optimization literature 57 58 59 60 61 62 provides methods and techniques that take a global approach to robustness analysis These methods directly address decision under severe uncertainty and have been used for this purpose for more than thirty years now Wald s Maximin model is the main instrument used by these methods The principal difference between the Maximin model employed by info gap and the various Maximin models employed by robust optimization methods is in the manner in which the total region of uncertainty is incorporated in the robustness model Info gap takes a local approach that concentrates on the immediate neighborhood of the estimate In sharp contrast robust optimization methods set out to incorporate in the analysis the entire region of uncertainty or at least an adequate representation thereof In fact some of these methods do not even use an estimate Comparative analysis edit Classical decision theory 63 64 offers two approaches to decision making under severe uncertainty namely maximin and Laplaces principle of insufficient reason assume all outcomes equally likely these may be considered alternative solutions to the problem info gap addresses Further as discussed at decision theory alternatives to probability theory probabilists particularly Bayesians probabilists argue that optimal decision rules formally admissible decision rules can always be derived by probabilistic methods this is the statement of the complete class theorems and thus that non probabilistic methods such as info gap are unnecessary and do not yield new or better decision rules Maximin edit As attested by the rich literature on robust optimization maximin provides a wide range of methods for decision making in the face of severe uncertainty Indeed as discussed in criticism of info gap decision theory info gap s robustness model can be interpreted as an instance of the general maximin model Bayesian analysis edit As for Laplaces principle of insufficient reason in this context it is convenient to view it as an instance of Bayesian analysis The essence of the Bayesian analysis is applying probabilities for different possible realizations of the uncertain parameters In the case of Knightian non probabilistic uncertainty these probabilities represent the decision maker s degree of belief in a specific realization In our example suppose there are only five possible realizations of the uncertain revenue to allocation function The decision maker believes that the estimated function is the most likely and that the likelihood decreases as the difference from the estimate increases Figure 11 exemplifies such a probability distribution nbsp Figure 11 Probability distribution of the revenue function realizations Now for any allocation one can construct a probability distribution of the revenue based on his prior beliefs The decision maker can then choose the allocation with the highest expected revenue with the lowest probability for an unacceptable revenue etc The most problematic step of this analysis is the choice of the realizations probabilities When there is an extensive and relevant past experience an expert may use this experience to construct a probability distribution But even with extensive past experience when some parameters change the expert may only be able to estimate that A displaystyle A nbsp is more likely than B displaystyle B nbsp but will not be able to reliably quantify this difference Furthermore when conditions change drastically or when there is no past experience at all it may prove to be difficult even estimating whether A displaystyle A nbsp is more likely than B displaystyle B nbsp Nevertheless methodologically speaking this difficulty is not as problematic as basing the analysis of a problem subject to severe uncertainty on a single point estimate and its immediate neighborhood as done by info gap And what is more contrary to info gap this approach is global rather than local Still it must be stressed that Bayesian analysis does not expressly concern itself with the question of robustness Bayesian analysis raises the issue of learning from experience and adjusting probabilities accordingly In other words decision is not a one stop process but profits from a sequence of decisions and observations Classical decision theory perspective editSniedovich 47 raises two points to info gap from the point of view of classical decision theory one substantive one scholarly the info gap uncertainty model is flawed and oversold Under severe uncertainty one should use global decision theory not local decision theory info gap is maximin Ben Haim 2006 p xii claims that info gap is radically different from all current theories of decision under uncertainty Ben Haim states Ben Haim 1999 pp 271 2 that robust reliability is emphatically not a min max worst case analysis Sniedovich has challenged the validity of info gap theory for making decisions under severe uncertainty In the framework of classical decision theory info gap s robustness model can be construed as an instance of Wald s Maximin model and its opportuneness model is an instance of the classical Minimin model Both operate in the neighborhood of an estimate of the parameter of interest whose true value is subject to severe uncertainty and therefore is likely to be substantially wrong Moreover the considerations brought to bear upon the decision process itself also originate in the locality of this unreliable estimate and so may or may not be reflective of the entire range of decisions and uncertainties Background working assumptions and a look ahead edit Now as portrayed in the info gap literature Info Gap was designed expressly as a methodology for solving decision problems that are subject to severe uncertainty And what is more its aim is to seek solutions that are robust Thus to have a clear picture of info gap s modus operandi and its role and place in decision theory and robust optimization it is imperative to examine it within this context In other words it is necessary to establish info gap s relation to classical decision theory and robust optimization To this end the following questions must be addressed What are the characteristics of decision problems that are subject to severe uncertainty What difficulties arise in the modelling and solution of such problems What type of robustness is sought How does info gap theory address these issues In what way is info gap decision theory similar to and or different from other theories for decision under uncertainty Two important points need to be elucidated in this regard at the outset Considering the severity of the uncertainty that info gap was designed to tackle it is essential to clarify the difficulties posed by severe uncertainty Since info gap is a non probabilistic method that seeks to maximize robustness to uncertainty it is imperative to compare it to the single most important non probabilistic model in classical decision theory namely Wald s Maximin paradigm Wald 1945 1950 After all this paradigm has dominated the scene in classical decision theory for well over sixty years now So first let us clarify the assumptions that are implied by severe uncertainty Working assumptions edit Info gap decision theory employs three simple constructs to capture the uncertainty associated with decision problems A parameter u displaystyle displaystyle u nbsp whose true value is subject to severe uncertainty A region of uncertainty U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp where the true value of u displaystyle displaystyle u nbsp lies An estimate u displaystyle displaystyle tilde u nbsp of the true value of u displaystyle displaystyle u nbsp It should be pointed out though that as such these constructs are generic meaning that they can be employed to model situations where the uncertainty is not severe but mild indeed very mild So it is vital to be clear that to give apt expression to the severity of the uncertainty in the Info Gap framework these three constructs are given specific meaning nbsp Working Assumptions The region of uncertainty U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp is relatively large In fact Ben Haim 2006 p 210 indicates that in the context of info gap decision theory most of the commonly encountered regions of uncertainty are unbounded The estimate u displaystyle displaystyle tilde u nbsp is a poor approximation of the true value of u displaystyle displaystyle u nbsp That is the estimate is a poor indication of the true value of u displaystyle displaystyle u nbsp Ben Haim 2006 p 280 and is likely to be substantially wrong Ben Haim 2006 p 281 In the picture u displaystyle displaystyle u circ nbsp represents the true unknown value of u displaystyle displaystyle u nbsp The point to note here is that conditions of severe uncertainty entail that the estimate u displaystyle displaystyle tilde u nbsp can relatively speaking be very distant from the true value u displaystyle displaystyle u circ nbsp This is particularly pertinent for methodologies like info gap that seek robustness to uncertainty Indeed assuming otherwise would methodologically speaking be tantamount to engaging in wishful thinking Wald s Maximin paradigm edit The basic idea behind this famous paradigm can be expressed in plain language as follows Maximin RuleWe are to adopt the alternative the worst outcome of which is superior to the worst outcome of the others Rawls 65 1971 p 152 Thus according to this paradigm in the framework of decision making under severe uncertainty the robustness of an alternative is a measure of how well this alternative can cope with the worst uncertain outcome that it can generate Needless to say this attitude towards severe uncertainty often leads to the selection of highly conservative alternatives This is precisely the reason that this paradigm is not always a satisfactory methodology for decision making under severe uncertainty Tintner 1952 As indicated in the overview info gap s robustness model is a Maximin model in disguise More specifically it is a simple instance of Wald s Maximin model where The region of uncertainty associated with an alternative decision is an immediate neighborhood of the estimate u displaystyle displaystyle tilde u nbsp The uncertain outcomes of an alternative are determined by a characteristic function of the performance requirement under consideration Thus aside from the conservatism issue a far more serious issue must be addressed This is the validity issue arising from the local nature of info gap s robustness analysis Local vs global robustness edit nbsp The validity of the results generated by info gap s robustness analysis are contingent on the quality of the estimate u displaystyle displaystyle tilde u nbsp According to info gap s own working assumptions this estimate is poor and likely to be substantially wrong Ben Haim 2006 p 280 281 The trouble with this feature of info gap s robustness model is brought out more forcefully by the picture The white circle represents the immediate neighborhood of the estimate u displaystyle displaystyle tilde u nbsp on which the Maximin analysis is conducted Since the region of uncertainty is large and the quality of the estimate is poor it is very likely that the true value of u displaystyle displaystyle u nbsp is distant from the point at which the Maximin analysis is conducted So given the severity of the uncertainty under consideration how valid useful can this type of Maximin analysis really be What extent a local robustness analysis a la Maximin in the immediate neighborhood of a poor estimate can aptly represent a large region of uncertainty Robust optimization methods invariably take a far more global view of robustness So much so that scenario planning and scenario generation are central issues in this area This reflects a strong commitment to an adequate representation of the entire region of uncertainty in the definition of robustness and in the robustness analysis itself This has to do with the portrayal of info gap s contribution to the state of the art in decision theory and its role and place vis a vis other methodologies Role and place in decision theory edit Info gap is emphatic about its advancement of the state of the art in decision theory color is used here for emphasis Info gap decision theory is radically different from all current theories of decision under uncertainty The difference originates in the modelling of uncertainty as an information gap rather than as a probability Ben Haim 2006 p xii In this book we concentrate on the fairly new concept of information gap uncertainty whose differences from more classical approaches to uncertainty are real and deep Despite the power of classical decision theories in many areas such as engineering economics management medicine and public policy a need has arisen for a different format for decisions based on severely uncertain evidence Ben Haim 2006 p 11 These strong claims must be substantiated In particular a clear cut unequivocal answer must be given to the following question in what way is info gap s generic robustness model different indeed radically different from worst case analysis a la Maximin Subsequent sections of this article describe various aspects of info gap decision theory and its applications how it proposes to cope with the working assumptions outlined above the local nature of info gap s robustness analysis and its intimate relationship with Wald s classical Maximin paradigm and worst case analysis Invariance property edit The main point to keep in mind here is that info gap s raison d etre is to provide a methodology for decision under severe uncertainty This means that its primary test would be in the efficacy of its handling of and coping with severe uncertainty To this end it must be established first how Info Gap s robustness opportuneness models behave fare as the severity of the uncertainty is increased decreased Second it must be established whether info gap s robustness opportuneness models give adequate expression to the potential variability of the performance function over the entire region of uncertainty This is particularly important because Info Gap is usually concerned with relatively large indeed unbounded regions of uncertainty So let U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp denote the total region of uncertainty and consider these key questions How does the robustness opportuneness analysis respond to an increase decrease in the size of U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp How does an increase decrease in the size of U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp affect the robustness or opportuneness of a decision How representative are the results generated by info gap s robustness opportuneness analysis of what occurs in the relatively large total region of uncertainty U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp nbsp Suppose then that the robustness a q r c displaystyle displaystyle hat alpha q r c nbsp has been computed for a decision q Q displaystyle displaystyle q in mathcal Q nbsp and it is observed that U a u U displaystyle displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u subseteq mathfrak U nbsp where a a q r c e displaystyle displaystyle alpha hat alpha q r c varepsilon nbsp for some e gt 0 displaystyle displaystyle varepsilon gt 0 nbsp The question is then how would the robustness of q displaystyle displaystyle q nbsp namely a q r c displaystyle displaystyle hat alpha q r c nbsp be affected if the region of uncertainty would be say twice as large as U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp or perhaps even 10 times as large as U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp Consider then the following result which is a direct consequence of the local nature of info gap s robustness opportuneness analysis and the nesting property of info gaps regions of uncertainty Sniedovich 2007 Invariance theorem edit The robustness of decision q displaystyle displaystyle q nbsp is invariant with the size of the total region of uncertainty U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp for all U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp such that 7 U a q r c e u U displaystyle mathcal U hat alpha q r c varepsilon tilde u subseteq mathfrak U nbsp for some e gt 0 displaystyle displaystyle varepsilon gt 0 nbsp displaystyle Box nbsp In other words for any given decision info gap s analysis yields the same results for all total regions of uncertainty that contain U a u displaystyle displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp This applies to both the robustness and opportuneness models This is illustrated in the picture the robustness of a given decision does not change notwithstanding an increase in the region of uncertainty from U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp to U displaystyle displaystyle mathfrak U nbsp In short by dint of focusing exclusively on the immediate neighborhood of the estimate u displaystyle displaystyle tilde u nbsp info gap s robustness opportuneness models are inherently local For this reason they are in principle incapable of incorporating in the analysis of a q r c displaystyle displaystyle hat alpha q r c nbsp and b q r c displaystyle displaystyle hat beta q r c nbsp regions of uncertainty that lie outside the neighborhoods U a q r c u displaystyle mathcal U hat alpha q r c tilde u nbsp and U b q r c u displaystyle mathcal U hat beta q r c tilde u nbsp of the estimate u displaystyle displaystyle tilde u nbsp respectively To illustrate consider a simple numerical example where the total region of uncertainty is U displaystyle mathfrak U infty infty nbsp the estimate is u 0 displaystyle displaystyle tilde u 0 nbsp and for some decision q displaystyle displaystyle hat q nbsp we obtain U a q r c u 2 2 displaystyle mathcal U hat alpha hat q r c tilde u 2 2 nbsp The picture is this nbsp where the term No man s land refers to the part of the total region of uncertainty that is outside the region U a q r c e u displaystyle displaystyle mathcal U hat alpha q r c varepsilon tilde u nbsp Note that in this case the robustness of decision q displaystyle displaystyle hat q nbsp is based on its worst case performance over no more than a minuscule part of the total region of uncertainty that is an immediate neighborhood of the estimate u displaystyle displaystyle tilde u nbsp Since usually info gap s total region of uncertainty is unbounded this illustration represents a usual case rather than an exception Info gap s robustness opportuneness are by definition local properties As such they cannot assess the performance of decisions over the total region of uncertainty For this reason it is not clear how Info Gap s Robustness Opportuneness models can provide a meaningful sound useful basis for decision under severe uncertainty where the estimate is poor and is likely to be substantially wrong This crucial issue is addressed in subsequent sections of this article Maximin Minimin playing robustness opportuneness games with Nature edit For well over sixty years now Wald s Maximin model has figured in classical decision theory and related areas such as robust optimization as the foremost non probabilistic paradigm for modeling and treatment of severe uncertainty Info gap is propounded e g Ben Haim 2001 2006 as a new non probabilistic theory that is radically different from all current decision theories for decision under uncertainty So it is imperative to examine in this discussion in what way if any is info gap s robustness model radically different from Maximin For one thing there is a well established assessment of the utility of Maximin For example Berger Chapter 5 66 suggests that even in situations where no prior information is available a best case for Maximin Maximin can lead to bad decision rules and be hard to implement He recommends Bayesian methodology And as indicated above It should also be remarked that the minimax principle even if it is applicable leads to an extremely conservative policy Tintner 1952 p 25 67 However quite apart from the ramifications that establishing this point might have for the utility of info gaps robustness model the reason that it behooves us to clarify the relationship between info gap and Maximin is the centrality of the latter in decision theory After all this is a major classical decision methodology So any theory claiming to furnish a new non probabilistic methodology for decision under severe uncertainty would be expected to be compared to this stalwart of decision theory And yet not only is a comparison of info gap s robustness model to Maximin absent from the three books expounding info gap Ben Haim 1996 2001 2006 Maximin is not even mentioned in them as the major decision theoretic methodology for severe uncertainty that it is Elsewhere in the info gap literature one can find discussions dealing with similarities and differences between these two paradigms as well as discussions on the relationship between info gap and worst case analysis 7 16 35 37 53 68 However the general impression is that the intimate connection between these two paradigms has not been identified Indeed the opposite is argued For instance Ben Haim 2005 35 argues that info gap s robustness model is similar to Maximin but is not a Maximin model The following quote eloquently expresses Ben Haim s assessment of info gap s relationship to Maximin and it provides ample motivation for the analysis that follows We note that robust reliability is emphatically not a worst case analysis In classical worst case min max analysis the designer minimizes the impact of the maximally damaging case But an info gap model of uncertainty is an unbounded family of nested sets U a u displaystyle displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp for all a 0 displaystyle displaystyle alpha geq 0 nbsp Consequently there is no worst case any adverse occurrence is less damaging than some other more extreme event occurring at a larger value of a displaystyle displaystyle alpha nbsp What Eq 1 expresses is the greatest level of uncertainty consistent with no failure When the designer chooses q to maximize a q r c displaystyle displaystyle hat alpha q r c nbsp he is maximizing his immunity to an unbounded ambient uncertainty The closest this comes to min maxing is that the design is chosen so that bad events causing reward R displaystyle displaystyle R nbsp less than r c displaystyle displaystyle r c nbsp occur as far away as possible beyond a maximized value of a displaystyle displaystyle hat alpha nbsp Ben Haim 1999 pp 271 2 69 The point to note here is that this statement misses the fact that the horizon of uncertainty a displaystyle displaystyle alpha nbsp is bounded above implicitly by the performance requirement r c R q u u U a u displaystyle r c leq R q u forall u in mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp and that info gap conducts its worst case analysis one analysis at a time for a given a 0 displaystyle displaystyle alpha geq 0 nbsp within each of the regions of uncertainty U a u a 0 displaystyle displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u alpha geq 0 nbsp In short given the discussions in the info gap literature on this issue it is obvious that the kinship between info gap s robustness model and Wald s Maximin model as well as info gap s kinship with other models of classical decision theory must be brought to light So the objective in this section is to place info gap s robustness and opportuneness models in their proper context namely within the wider frameworks of classical decision theory and robust optimization The discussion is based on the classical decision theoretic perspective outlined by Sniedovich 2007 70 and on standard texts in this area e g Resnik 1987 63 French 1988 64 Certain parts of the exposition that follows have a mathematical slant This is unavoidable because info gap s models are mathematical Generic models edit The basic conceptual framework that classical decision theory provides for dealing with uncertainty is that of a two player game The two players are the decision maker DM and Nature where Nature represents uncertainty More specifically Nature represents the DM s attitude towards uncertainty and risk Note that a clear distinction is made in this regard between a pessimistic decision maker and an optimistic decision maker namely between a worst case attitude and a best case attitude A pessimistic decision maker assumes that Nature plays against him whereas an optimistic decision maker assumes that Nature plays with him To express these intuitive notions mathematically classical decision theory uses a simple model consisting of the following three constructs A set D displaystyle displaystyle D nbsp representing the decision space available to the DM A set of sets S d d D displaystyle displaystyle S d d in D nbsp representing state spaces associated with the decisions in D displaystyle displaystyle D nbsp A function g g d s displaystyle displaystyle g g d s nbsp stipulating the outcomes generated by the decision state pairs d s displaystyle displaystyle d s nbsp The function g displaystyle displaystyle g nbsp is called objective function payoff function return function cost function etc The decision making process game defined by these objects consists of three steps Step 1 The DM selects a decision d D displaystyle d in D nbsp Step 2 In response given d displaystyle d nbsp Nature selects a state s S d displaystyle displaystyle s in S d nbsp Step 3 The outcome g d s displaystyle g d s nbsp is allotted to DM Note that in contrast to games considered in classical game theory here the first player DM moves first so that the second player Nature knows what decision was selected by the first player prior to selecting her decision Thus the conceptual and technical complications regarding the existence of Nash equilibrium point are not pertinent here Nature is not an independent player it is a conceptual device describing the DM s attitude towards uncertainty and risk At first sight the simplicity of this framework may strike one as naive Yet as attested by the variety of specific instances that it encompasses it is rich in possibilities flexible and versatile For the purposes of this discussion it suffices to consider the following classical generic setup z Opt DM d D opt Nature s S d g d s displaystyle z underset d in D overset text DM operatorname Opt underset s in S d overset text Nature operatorname opt g d s nbsp where O p t displaystyle displaystyle mathop Opt nbsp and o p t displaystyle displaystyle mathop opt nbsp represent the DM s and Nature s optimality criteria respectively that is each is equal to either max displaystyle displaystyle max nbsp or min displaystyle displaystyle min nbsp If O p t o p t displaystyle displaystyle mathop Opt mathop opt nbsp then the game is cooperative and if O p t o p t displaystyle displaystyle mathop Opt neq mathop opt nbsp then the game is non cooperative Thus this format represents four cases two non cooperative games Maximin and Minimax and two cooperative games Minimin and Maximax The respective formulations are as follows Worst case pessimism Best case optimism Maximin Minimax Minimin Maximax max d D min s S d g d s min d D max s S d g d s min d D min s S d g d s max d D max s S d g d s displaystyle begin array cc cc text Worst case pessimism amp amp text Best case optimism hline text Maximin amp text Minimax amp text Minimin amp text Maximax displaystyle max d in D min s in S d g d s amp displaystyle min d in D max s in S d g d s amp displaystyle min d in D min s in S d g d s amp displaystyle max d in D max s in S d g d s end array nbsp Each case is specified by a pair of optimality criteria employed by DM and Nature For example Maximin depicts a situation where DM strives to maximize the outcome and Nature strives to minimize it Similarly the Minimin paradigm represents situations where both DM and Nature are striving to in minimize the outcome Of particular interest to this discussion are the Maximin and Minimin paradigms because they subsume info gap s robustness and opportuneness models respectively So here they are Maximin Game max d D min s S d g d s displaystyle displaystyle max d in D min s in S d g d s nbsp Step 1 The DM selects a decision d D displaystyle displaystyle d in D nbsp with a view to maximize the outcome g d s displaystyle displaystyle g d s nbsp Step 2 In response given d displaystyle displaystyle d nbsp Nature selects a state in S d displaystyle displaystyle S d nbsp that minimizes g d s displaystyle displaystyle g d s nbsp over S d displaystyle displaystyle S d nbsp Step 3 The outcome g d s displaystyle displaystyle g d s nbsp is allotted to DM Minimin Game min d D min s S d g d s displaystyle displaystyle min d in D min s in S d g d s nbsp Step 1 The DM selects a decision d D displaystyle displaystyle d in D nbsp with a view to minimizes the outcome g d s displaystyle displaystyle g d s nbsp Step 2 In response given d displaystyle displaystyle d nbsp Nature selects a state in S d displaystyle displaystyle S d nbsp that minimizes g d s displaystyle displaystyle g d s nbsp over S d displaystyle displaystyle S d nbsp Step 3 The outcome g d s displaystyle displaystyle g d s nbsp is allotted to DM With this in mind consider now info gap s robustness and opportuneness models Info gap s robustness model edit From a classical decision theoretic point of view info gap s robustness model is a game between the DM and Nature where the DM selects the value of a displaystyle displaystyle alpha nbsp aiming for the largest possible whereas Nature selects the worst value of u displaystyle displaystyle u nbsp in U a u displaystyle displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp In this context the worst value of u displaystyle displaystyle u nbsp pertaining to a given q a displaystyle displaystyle q alpha nbsp pair is a u U a u displaystyle displaystyle u in mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp that violates the performance requirement r c R q u displaystyle displaystyle r c leq R q u nbsp This is achieved by minimizing R q u displaystyle displaystyle R q u nbsp over U a u displaystyle displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp There are various ways to incorporate the DM s objective and Nature s antagonistic response in a single outcome For instance one can use the following characteristic function for this purpose f q a u a r c R q u r c gt R q u q Q a 0 u U a u displaystyle varphi q alpha u begin cases quad alpha amp r c leq R q u infty amp r c gt R q u end cases q in mathcal Q alpha geq 0 u in mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp Note that as desired for any triplet q a u displaystyle q alpha u nbsp of interest we have r c R q u a f q a u displaystyle r c leq R q u longleftrightarrow alpha leq varphi q alpha u nbsp hence from the DM s point of view satisficing the performance constraint is equivalent to maximizing f q a u displaystyle displaystyle varphi q alpha u nbsp In short Info gap s Maximin Robustness Game for decision q displaystyle displaystyle q nbsp a q r c max a 0 min u U a u f q a u displaystyle displaystyle hat alpha q r c max alpha geq 0 min u in mathcal U alpha tilde u varphi q alpha u nbsp Step 1 The DM selects a horizon of uncertainty a 0 displaystyle displaystyle alpha geq 0 nbsp with a view to maximize the outcome f q a u displaystyle displaystyle varphi q alpha u nbsp Step 2 In response given a displaystyle displaystyle alpha nbsp Nature selects a u U a u displaystyle displaystyle u in mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp that minimizes f q a u displaystyle displaystyle varphi q alpha u nbsp over U a u displaystyle displaystyle mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp Step 3 The outcome f q a u displaystyle displaystyle varphi q alpha u nbsp is allotted to DM Clearly the DM s optimal alternative is to select the largest value of a displaystyle displaystyle alpha nbsp such that the worst u U a u displaystyle displaystyle u in mathcal U alpha tilde u nbsp satisfies the performance requirement Maximin Theorem edit As shown in Sniedovich 2007 47 Info gap s robustness model is a simple instance of Wald s maximin model Specifically math, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.