fbpx
Wikipedia

Gödel's ontological proof

Gödel's ontological proof is a formal argument by the mathematician Kurt Gödel (1906–1978) for the existence of God. The argument is in a line of development that goes back to Anselm of Canterbury (1033–1109). St. Anselm's ontological argument, in its most succinct form, is as follows: "God, by definition, is that for which no greater can be conceived. God exists in the understanding. If God exists in the understanding, we could imagine Him to be greater by existing in reality. Therefore, God must exist." A more elaborate version was given by Gottfried Leibniz (1646–1716); this is the version that Gödel studied and attempted to clarify with his ontological argument.

Gödel left a fourteen-point outline of his philosophical beliefs in his papers.[1] Points relevant to the ontological proof include:

4. There are other worlds and rational beings of a different and higher kind.
5. The world in which we live is not the only one in which we shall live or have lived.
13. There is a scientific (exact) philosophy and theology, which deals with concepts of the highest abstractness; and this is also most highly fruitful for science.
14. Religions are, for the most part, bad—but religion is not.

History edit

The first version of the ontological proof in Gödel's papers is dated "around 1941". Gödel is not known to have told anyone about his work on the proof until 1970, when he thought he was dying. In February, he allowed Dana Scott to copy out a version of the proof, which circulated privately. In August 1970, Gödel told Oskar Morgenstern that he was "satisfied" with the proof, but Morgenstern recorded in his diary entry for 29 August 1970, that Gödel would not publish because he was afraid that others might think "that he actually believes in God, whereas he is only engaged in a logical investigation (that is, in showing that such a proof with classical assumptions (completeness, etc.) correspondingly axiomatized, is possible)."[2] Gödel died January 14, 1978. Another version, slightly different from Scott's, was found in his papers. It was finally published, together with Scott's version, in 1987.[3]

In letters to his mother, who was not a churchgoer and had raised Kurt and his brother as freethinkers,[4] Gödel argued at length for a belief in an afterlife.[5] He did the same in an interview with a skeptical Hao Wang, who said: "I expressed my doubts as G spoke [...] Gödel smiled as he replied to my questions, obviously aware that his answers were not convincing me."[6] Wang reports that Gödel's wife, Adele, two days after Gödel's death, told Wang that "Gödel, although he did not go to church, was religious and read the Bible in bed every Sunday morning."[7] In an unmailed answer to a questionnaire, Gödel described his religion as "baptized Lutheran (but not member of any religious congregation). My belief is theistic, not pantheistic, following Leibniz rather than Spinoza."[note 1]

Outline edit

The proof[8][10] uses modal logic, which distinguishes between necessary truths and contingent truths. In the most common semantics for modal logic, many "possible worlds" are considered. A truth is necessary if it is true in all possible worlds. By contrast, if a statement happens to be true in our world, but is false in another world, then it is a contingent truth. A statement that is true in some world (not necessarily our own) is called a possible truth.

Furthermore, the proof uses higher-order (modal) logic because the definition of God employs an explicit quantification over properties.[11]

First, Gödel axiomatizes the notion of a "positive property":[note 2] for each property φ, either φ or its negation ¬φ must be positive, but not both (axiom 2). If a positive property φ implies a property ψ in each possible world, then ψ is positive, too (axiom 1).[note 3] Gödel then argues that each positive property is "possibly exemplified", i.e. applies at least to some object in some world (theorem 1). Defining an object to be Godlike if it has all positive properties (definition 1),[note 4] and requiring that property to be positive itself (axiom 3),[note 5] Gödel shows that in some possible world a Godlike object exists (theorem 2), called "God" in the following.[note 6] Gödel proceeds to prove that a Godlike object exists in every possible world.

To this end, he defines essences: if x is an object in some world, then a property φ is said to be an essence of x if φ(x) is true in that world and if φ necessarily entails all other properties that x has in that world (definition 2). Requiring positive properties being positive in every possible world (axiom 4), Gödel can show that Godlikeness is an essence of a Godlike object (theorem 3). Now, x is said to exist necessarily if, for every essence φ of x, there is an element y with property φ in every possible world (definition 3). Axiom 5 requires necessary existence to be a positive property.

Hence, it must follow from Godlikeness. Moreover, Godlikeness is an essence of God, since it entails all positive properties, and any non-positive property is the negation of some positive property, so God cannot have any non-positive properties. Since necessary existence is also a positive property (axiom 5), it must be a property of every Godlike object, as every Godlike object has all the positive properties (definition 1). Since any Godlike object is necessarily existent, it follows that any Godlike object in one world is a Godlike object in all worlds, by the definition of necessary existence. Given the existence of a Godlike object in one world, proven above, we may conclude that there is a Godlike object in every possible world, as required (theorem 4). Besides axiom 1-5 and definition 1-3, a few other axioms from modal logic[clarification needed] were tacitly used in the proof.

From these hypotheses, it is also possible to prove that there is only one God in each world by Leibniz's law, the identity of indiscernibles: two or more objects are identical (the same) if they have all their properties in common, and so, there would only be one object in each world that possesses property G. Gödel did not attempt to do so however, as he purposely limited his proof to the issue of existence, rather than uniqueness.

Symbolic notation edit

 

Criticism edit

Most criticism of Gödel's proof is aimed at its axioms: as with any proof in any logical system, if the axioms the proof depends on are doubted, then the conclusions can be doubted. It is particularly applicable to Gödel's proof – because it rests on five axioms, some of which are considered questionable. A proof does not necessitate that the conclusion be correct, but rather that by accepting the axioms, the conclusion follows logically.

Many philosophers have called the axioms into question. The first layer of criticism is simply that there are no arguments presented that give reasons why the axioms are true. A second layer is that these particular axioms lead to unwelcome conclusions. This line of thought was argued by Jordan Howard Sobel,[12] showing that if the axioms are accepted, they lead to a "modal collapse" where every statement that is true is necessarily true, i.e. the sets of necessary, of contingent, and of possible truths all coincide (provided there are accessible worlds at all).[note 7] According to Robert Koons,[9]: 9  Sobel suggested in a 2005 conference paper[citation needed] that Gödel might have welcomed modal collapse.[13]

There are suggested amendments to the proof, presented by C. Anthony Anderson,[14] but argued to be refutable by Anderson and Michael Gettings.[15] Sobel's proof of modal collapse has been questioned by Koons,[9][note 8] but a counter-defence by Sobel has been given.[citation needed]

Gödel's proof has also been questioned by Graham Oppy,[16] asking whether many other almost-gods would also be "proven" through Gödel's axioms. This counter-argument has been questioned by Gettings,[17] who agrees that the axioms might be questioned, but disagrees that Oppy's particular counter-example can be shown from Gödel's axioms.

Religious scholar Fr. Robert J. Spitzer accepted Gödel's proof, calling it "an improvement over the Anselmian Ontological Argument (which does not work)."[18]

There are, however, many more criticisms, most of them focusing on the question of whether these axioms must be rejected to avoid odd conclusions. The broader criticism is that even if the axioms cannot be shown to be false, that does not mean that they are true. Hilbert's famous remark about interchangeability of the primitives' names applies to those in Gödel's ontological axioms ("positive", "god-like", "essence") as well as to those in Hilbert's geometry axioms ("point", "line", "plane"). According to André Fuhrmann (2005) it remains to show that the dazzling notion prescribed by traditions and often believed to be essentially mysterious satisfies Gödel's axioms. This is not a mathematical, but a theological task.[19]: 364–366  It is this task which decides which religion's god has been proven to exist.

Computationally verified versions edit

Christoph Benzmüller and Bruno Woltzenlogel-Paleo formalized Gödel's proof to a level that is suitable for automated theorem proving or at least computational verification via proof assistants.[20] The effort made headlines in German newspapers. According to the authors of this effort, they were inspired by Melvin Fitting's book.[21]

In 2014, they computationally verified Gödel's proof (in the above version).[22]: 97 [note 9] They also proved that this version's axioms are consistent,[note 10] but imply modal collapse,[note 11] thus confirming Sobel's 1987 argument. In the same paper, they suspected Gödel's original version of the axioms[note 12] to be inconsistent, as they failed to prove their consistency.[note 13]

In 2016, they gave an automated proof that the original version implies  , i.e., is inconsistent in every modal logic with a reflexive or symmetric accessibility relation.[24]: 940 lf  Moreover, they gave an argument that this version is inconsistent in every logic at all,[note 14] but failed to duplicate it by automated provers.[note 15] However, they were able to verify Melvin Fitting's reformulation of the argument and guarantee its consistency.[25]

In literature edit

A humorous variant of Gödel's ontological proof is mentioned in Quentin Canterel's novel The Jolly Coroner.[26][page needed] The proof is also mentioned in the TV series Hand of God.[specify]

Jeffrey Kegler's 2007 novel The God Proof depicts the (fictional) rediscovery of Gödel's lost notebook about the ontological proof.[27]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Gödel's answer to a special questionnaire sent him by the sociologist Burke Grandjean. This answer is quoted directly in Wang 1987, p. 18, and indirectly in Wang 1996, p. 112. It's also quoted directly in Dawson 1997, p. 6, who cites Wang 1987. The Grandjean questionnaire is perhaps the most extended autobiographical item in Gödel's papers. Gödel filled it out in pencil and wrote a cover letter, but he never returned it. "Theistic" is italicized in both Wang 1987 and Wang 1996. It is possible that this italicization is Wang's and not Gödel's. The quote follows Wang 1987, with two corrections taken from Wang 1996. Wang 1987 reads "Baptist Lutheran" where Wang 1996 has "baptized Lutheran". "Baptist Lutheran" makes no sense, especially in context, and was presumably a typo or mistranscription. Wang 1987 has "rel. cong.", which in Wang 1996 is expanded to "religious congregation".
  2. ^ It assumes that it is possible to single out positive properties from among all properties. Gödel comments that "Positive means positive in the moral aesthetic sense (independently of the accidental structure of the world)... It may also mean pure attribution as opposed to privation (or containing privation)." (Gödel 1995), see also manuscript in (Gawlick 2012).
  3. ^ As a profane example, if the property of being green is positive, that of not being red is, too (by axiom 1), hence that of being red is negative (by axiom 2). More generally, at most one color can be considered positive.
  4. ^ Continuing the color example, a godlike object must have the unique color that is considered positive, or no color at all; both alternatives may seem counter-intuitive.
  5. ^ If one considers the partial order   defined by   if  , then Axioms 1-3 can be summarized by saying that positive properties form an ultrafilter on this ordering. Definition 1 and Axiom 4 are needed to establish the Godlike property as principal element of the ultrafilter.
  6. ^ By removing all modal operators from axioms, definitions, proofs, and theorems, a modified version of theorem 2 is obtained saying "∃x G(x)", i.e. "There exists an object which has all positive, but no negative properties". Nothing more than axioms 1-3, definition 1, and theorems 1-2 needs to be considered for this result.
  7. ^ Formally,   for all p implies   for all p by indirect proof, and   holds for all p whenever there are accessible worlds.
  8. ^ Since Sobel's proof of modal collapse uses lambda abstraction, but Gödel's proof does not, Koons suggests to forbid this property-construction operation as the "most conservative" measure, before "rejecting or emending ... axioms (as Anderson does)".
  9. ^ Lines "T3" in Fig.2, and item 3 in section 4 ("Main findings"). Their theorem "T3" corresponds to "Th.4" shown above.
  10. ^ Line "CO" in Fig.2, and item 1 in section 4 (p. 97).
  11. ^ Line "MC" in Fig.2, and item 6 in section 4 (p. 97).
  12. ^ The version shown here is by Dana Scott.[23] It differs from Gödel's original by omitting the first conjunct,  , in Df.2.
  13. ^ Lines "CO'" in Fig.2, and item 5 in section 4 (p. 97).
  14. ^ Item 8 in section 4.1 "Informal argument" (p. 940).
  15. ^ See the detailed discussion in section 4 "Intuitive Inconsistency Argument" (p. 939–941).

References edit

  1. ^ In: Wang, Hao. A Logical Journey: From Gödel to Philosophy. A Bradford Book, 1997. Print. p.316.
  2. ^ Quoted in Gödel 1995, p. 388. The German original is quoted in Dawson 1997, p. 307. The nested parentheses are in Morgenstern's original diary entry, as quoted by Dawson.
  3. ^ The publication history of the proof in this paragraph is from Gödel 1995, p. 388
  4. ^ Dawson 1997, pp. 6.
  5. ^ Dawson 1997, pp. 210–212.
  6. ^ Wang 1996, p. 317. The ellipsis is Wikipedia's.
  7. ^ Wang 1996, p. 51.
  8. ^ Gödel's proof is reprinted on p.403-404,429-437 of: Kurt Gödel (Mar 1995). Solomon Feferman and John W. Dawson jr. and Warren Goldfarb and Charles Parsons and Robert M. Solovay (ed.). Unpublished Essays and Lectures (PDF). Collected Works. Vol. III (1st ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-507255-3.
  9. ^ a b c Robert C. Koons (Jul 2005). (PDF) (Unpublished Paper). University of Texas at Austin. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2020-08-02.
  10. ^ The presentation below follows that in Koons (2005),[9] p.3-7.
  11. ^ Fitting, 2002, p. 139
  12. ^ Jordan Howard Sobel (Nov 1987). "Gödel's ontological proof". In Judith Jarvis Thomson (ed.). On Being and Saying: Essays for Richard Cartwright. Cambridge/MA & London, England: MIT Press. pp. 241–261. ISBN 978-0262200639.
  13. ^ Kurt Gödel (Mar 1995). "Texts Relating to the Ontological Proof (App. B)". In Solomon Feferman; John W. Dawson jr.; Warren Goldfarb; Charles Parsons; Robert M. Solovay (eds.). Unpublished Essays and Lectures (PDF). Collected Works. Vol. III (1st ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 429–437. ISBN 0-19-507255-3. Here: p.435; probably, Sobel referred to Gödel's note 4.: "... If   is assumed [as following from the essence of  ], ... but that is the inferior way. Rather,   should follow first from the existence of God." The note might indicate that Gödel was aware of his axioms implying modal collapse.
  14. ^ Curtis Anthony Anderson (Jul 1990). "Some Emendations of Gödel's Ontological Proof" (PDF). Faith and Philosophy. 7 (3): 291–303. doi:10.5840/faithphil19907325. (PDF) from the original on 2015-06-04.
  15. ^ Curtis Anthony Anderson and Michael Gettings (Aug 1996). "Gödel's ontological proof revisited". In Petr Hájek (ed.). Proc. Gödel '96: Logical Foundations of Mathematics, Computer Science and Physics — Kurt Gödel's Legacy. Lecture Notes in Logic. Vol. 6. Springer. pp. 167–172.
  16. ^ Graham Oppy (Oct 1996). "Godelian ontological arguments". Analysis. 54 (4): 226–230. doi:10.1093/analys/56.4.226. — Longer version (2005)
  17. ^ Gettings Michael (1999). "Gödel's ontological argument: a reply to Oppy". Analysis. 59 (264): 309–313. doi:10.1111/1467-8284.00184 (inactive 31 January 2024).{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: DOI inactive as of January 2024 (link)
  18. ^ "Godel's Theorem and the Existence of God". Magis Center. 2017-04-26. Retrieved 2018-05-23.
  19. ^ André Fuhrmann (2005). "Existenz und Notwendigkeit — Kurt Gödels axiomatische Theologie" [Existence and Necessity — Kurt Gödel's Axiomatic Theology] (PDF). In W. Spohn (ed.). Logik in der Philosophie [Logic in Philosophy] (in German). Heidelberg: Synchron. pp. 349–374. (PDF) from the original on 2016-05-18.
  20. ^ "FormalTheology/GoedelGod". GitHub. 28 June 2021.
  21. ^ Knight, David (23 October 2013). "Scientists Use Computer to Mathematically Prove Gödel's God Theorem". Der Spiegel. Retrieved 28 October 2013.
  22. ^ Christoph Benzmüller and Bruno Woltzenlogel-Paleo (2014). "Automating Gödel's Ontological Proof of God's Existence with Higher-Order Automated Theorem Provers" (PDF). Proc. European Conference on Artificial Intelligence. Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence and Applications. Vol. 263. IOS Press. pp. 93–98. (PDF) from the original on 2014-07-14.
  23. ^ D. Scott (2004). "Appendix B: Notes in Dana Scott's Hand [1972]". In J.H. Sobel (ed.). Logic and Theism: Arguments for and Against Beliefs in God. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. pp. 145–146. ISBN 978-0511497988.
  24. ^ Christoph Benzmüller and Bruno Woltzenlogel-Paleo (Jul 2016). "The Inconsistency in Gödel's Ontological Argument: — A Success Story for AI in Metaphysics" (PDF). In Subbarao Kambhampati (ed.). Proc. 25th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence. AAAI Press. pp. 936–942. (PDF) from the original on 2016-11-13.
  25. ^ Christoph Benzmüller and David Fuenmayor (May 2017). "Types, Tableaus and Gödel's God in Isabelle/HOL". Archive of Formal Proofs. ISSN 2150-914X.
  26. ^ Quentin Canterel (2015). The Jolly Coroner: A Picaresque Novel. Acorn Independent Press.
  27. ^ Jeffrey Kegler (2007), The God Proof, full text online.

Further reading edit

  • Frode Alfson Bjørdal, "Understanding Gödel's Ontological Argument", in T. Childers (ed.), The Logica Yearbook 1998, Prague 1999, 214-217.
  • Frode Alfson Bjørdal, "All Properties are Divine, or God Exists", in Logic and Logical Philosophy, Vol. 27 No. 3, 2018, pp. 329–350.
  • Bromand, Joachim. "Gödels ontologischer Beweis und andere modallogische Gottesbeweise", in J. Bromand und G. Kreis (Hg.), Gottesbeweise von Anselm bis Gödel, Berlin 2011, 381-491.
  • John W. Dawson Jr (1997). Logical Dilemmas: The Life and Work of Kurt Godel. Wellesley, Mass: AK Peters, Ltd. ISBN 1-56881-025-3.
  • Melvin Fitting, "Types, Tableaus, and Godel's God" Publisher: Dordrecht Kluwer Academic, 2002, ISBN 1-4020-0604-7, ISBN 978-1-4020-0604-3
  • Kurt Gödel (Mar 1995). Solomon Feferman; John W. Dawson jr.; Warren Goldfarb; Charles parsons; Robert M. Solovay (eds.). Unpublished Essays and Lectures (PDF). Collected Works. Vol. III (1st ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-507255-3. — See Chapter "Ontological Proof", pp. 403–404, and Appendix B "Texts Relating to the Ontological Proof", pp. 429–437.
  • Goldman, Randolph R. "Gödel's Ontological Argument", PhD Diss., University of California, Berkeley 2000.
  • Hazen, A. P. "On Gödel's Ontological Proof", Australasian Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 76, No 3, pp. 361–377, September 1998
  • Small, Christopher. (PDF). University of Waterloo. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2009-12-22. Retrieved 2010-08-31.
  • Wang, Hao (1987). Reflections on Kurt Gödel. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-23127-1.
  • Wang, Hao (1996). A Logical Journey: from Gödel to Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-23189-1.

External links edit

  • Oppy, Graham. "Ontological arguments". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Annotated bibliography of studies on Gödel's Ontological Argument
  • Thomas Gawlick, , Jan. 2012 — shows Gödel's original proof manuscript on p. 2-3
  • A Divine Consistency Proof for Mathematics — A submitted work by Harvey Friedman showing that if God exists (in the sense of Gödel), then Mathematics, as formalized by the usual ZFC axioms, is consistent.

gödel, ontological, proof, formal, argument, mathematician, kurt, gödel, 1906, 1978, existence, argument, line, development, that, goes, back, anselm, canterbury, 1033, 1109, anselm, ontological, argument, most, succinct, form, follows, definition, that, which. Godel s ontological proof is a formal argument by the mathematician Kurt Godel 1906 1978 for the existence of God The argument is in a line of development that goes back to Anselm of Canterbury 1033 1109 St Anselm s ontological argument in its most succinct form is as follows God by definition is that for which no greater can be conceived God exists in the understanding If God exists in the understanding we could imagine Him to be greater by existing in reality Therefore God must exist A more elaborate version was given by Gottfried Leibniz 1646 1716 this is the version that Godel studied and attempted to clarify with his ontological argument Godel left a fourteen point outline of his philosophical beliefs in his papers 1 Points relevant to the ontological proof include 4 There are other worlds and rational beings of a different and higher kind 5 The world in which we live is not the only one in which we shall live or have lived 13 There is a scientific exact philosophy and theology which deals with concepts of the highest abstractness and this is also most highly fruitful for science 14 Religions are for the most part bad but religion is not Contents 1 History 2 Outline 2 1 Symbolic notation 3 Criticism 4 Computationally verified versions 5 In literature 6 See also 7 Notes 8 References 9 Further reading 10 External linksHistory editThe first version of the ontological proof in Godel s papers is dated around 1941 Godel is not known to have told anyone about his work on the proof until 1970 when he thought he was dying In February he allowed Dana Scott to copy out a version of the proof which circulated privately In August 1970 Godel told Oskar Morgenstern that he was satisfied with the proof but Morgenstern recorded in his diary entry for 29 August 1970 that Godel would not publish because he was afraid that others might think that he actually believes in God whereas he is only engaged in a logical investigation that is in showing that such a proof with classical assumptions completeness etc correspondingly axiomatized is possible 2 Godel died January 14 1978 Another version slightly different from Scott s was found in his papers It was finally published together with Scott s version in 1987 3 In letters to his mother who was not a churchgoer and had raised Kurt and his brother as freethinkers 4 Godel argued at length for a belief in an afterlife 5 He did the same in an interview with a skeptical Hao Wang who said I expressed my doubts as G spoke Godel smiled as he replied to my questions obviously aware that his answers were not convincing me 6 Wang reports that Godel s wife Adele two days after Godel s death told Wang that Godel although he did not go to church was religious and read the Bible in bed every Sunday morning 7 In an unmailed answer to a questionnaire Godel described his religion as baptized Lutheran but not member of any religious congregation My belief is theistic not pantheistic following Leibniz rather than Spinoza note 1 Outline editThe proof 8 10 uses modal logic which distinguishes between necessary truths and contingent truths In the most common semantics for modal logic many possible worlds are considered A truth is necessary if it is true in all possible worlds By contrast if a statement happens to be true in our world but is false in another world then it is a contingent truth A statement that is true in some world not necessarily our own is called a possible truth Furthermore the proof uses higher order modal logic because the definition of God employs an explicit quantification over properties 11 First Godel axiomatizes the notion of a positive property note 2 for each property f either f or its negation f must be positive but not both axiom 2 If a positive property f implies a property ps in each possible world then ps is positive too axiom 1 note 3 Godel then argues that each positive property is possibly exemplified i e applies at least to some object in some world theorem 1 Defining an object to be Godlike if it has all positive properties definition 1 note 4 and requiring that property to be positive itself axiom 3 note 5 Godel shows that in some possible world a Godlike object exists theorem 2 called God in the following note 6 Godel proceeds to prove that a Godlike object exists in every possible world To this end he defines essences if x is an object in some world then a property f is said to be an essence of x if f x is true in that world and if f necessarily entails all other properties that x has in that world definition 2 Requiring positive properties being positive in every possible world axiom 4 Godel can show that Godlikeness is an essence of a Godlike object theorem 3 Now x is said to exist necessarily if for every essence f of x there is an element y with property f in every possible world definition 3 Axiom 5 requires necessary existence to be a positive property Hence it must follow from Godlikeness Moreover Godlikeness is an essence of God since it entails all positive properties and any non positive property is the negation of some positive property so God cannot have any non positive properties Since necessary existence is also a positive property axiom 5 it must be a property of every Godlike object as every Godlike object has all the positive properties definition 1 Since any Godlike object is necessarily existent it follows that any Godlike object in one world is a Godlike object in all worlds by the definition of necessary existence Given the existence of a Godlike object in one world proven above we may conclude that there is a Godlike object in every possible world as required theorem 4 Besides axiom 1 5 and definition 1 3 a few other axioms from modal logic clarification needed were tacitly used in the proof From these hypotheses it is also possible to prove that there is only one God in each world by Leibniz s law the identity of indiscernibles two or more objects are identical the same if they have all their properties in common and so there would only be one object in each world that possesses property G Godel did not attempt to do so however as he purposely limited his proof to the issue of existence rather than uniqueness Symbolic notation edit Ax 1 P f x f x ps x P ps Ax 2 P f P f Th 1 P f x f x Df 1 G x f P f f x Ax 3 P G Th 2 x G x Df 2 f ess x f x ps ps x y f y ps y Ax 4 P f P f Th 3 G x G ess x Df 3 E x f f ess x y f y Ax 5 P E Th 4 x G x displaystyle begin array rl text Ax 1 amp left P varphi wedge Box forall x varphi x Rightarrow psi x right Rightarrow P psi text Ax 2 amp P neg varphi Leftrightarrow neg P varphi text Th 1 amp P varphi Rightarrow Diamond exists x varphi x text Df 1 amp G x Leftrightarrow forall varphi P varphi Rightarrow varphi x text Ax 3 amp P G text Th 2 amp Diamond exists x G x text Df 2 amp varphi text ess x Leftrightarrow varphi x wedge forall psi left psi x Rightarrow Box forall y varphi y Rightarrow psi y right text Ax 4 amp P varphi Rightarrow Box P varphi text Th 3 amp G x Rightarrow G text ess x text Df 3 amp E x Leftrightarrow forall varphi varphi text ess x Rightarrow Box exists y varphi y text Ax 5 amp P E text Th 4 amp Box exists x G x end array nbsp Criticism editMost criticism of Godel s proof is aimed at its axioms as with any proof in any logical system if the axioms the proof depends on are doubted then the conclusions can be doubted It is particularly applicable to Godel s proof because it rests on five axioms some of which are considered questionable A proof does not necessitate that the conclusion be correct but rather that by accepting the axioms the conclusion follows logically Many philosophers have called the axioms into question The first layer of criticism is simply that there are no arguments presented that give reasons why the axioms are true A second layer is that these particular axioms lead to unwelcome conclusions This line of thought was argued by Jordan Howard Sobel 12 showing that if the axioms are accepted they lead to a modal collapse where every statement that is true is necessarily true i e the sets of necessary of contingent and of possible truths all coincide provided there are accessible worlds at all note 7 According to Robert Koons 9 9 Sobel suggested in a 2005 conference paper citation needed that Godel might have welcomed modal collapse 13 There are suggested amendments to the proof presented by C Anthony Anderson 14 but argued to be refutable by Anderson and Michael Gettings 15 Sobel s proof of modal collapse has been questioned by Koons 9 note 8 but a counter defence by Sobel has been given citation needed Godel s proof has also been questioned by Graham Oppy 16 asking whether many other almost gods would also be proven through Godel s axioms This counter argument has been questioned by Gettings 17 who agrees that the axioms might be questioned but disagrees that Oppy s particular counter example can be shown from Godel s axioms Religious scholar Fr Robert J Spitzer accepted Godel s proof calling it an improvement over the Anselmian Ontological Argument which does not work 18 There are however many more criticisms most of them focusing on the question of whether these axioms must be rejected to avoid odd conclusions The broader criticism is that even if the axioms cannot be shown to be false that does not mean that they are true Hilbert s famous remark about interchangeability of the primitives names applies to those in Godel s ontological axioms positive god like essence as well as to those in Hilbert s geometry axioms point line plane According to Andre Fuhrmann 2005 it remains to show that the dazzling notion prescribed by traditions and often believed to be essentially mysterious satisfies Godel s axioms This is not a mathematical but a theological task 19 364 366 It is this task which decides which religion s god has been proven to exist Computationally verified versions editChristoph Benzmuller and Bruno Woltzenlogel Paleo formalized Godel s proof to a level that is suitable for automated theorem proving or at least computational verification via proof assistants 20 The effort made headlines in German newspapers According to the authors of this effort they were inspired by Melvin Fitting s book 21 In 2014 they computationally verified Godel s proof in the above version 22 97 note 9 They also proved that this version s axioms are consistent note 10 but imply modal collapse note 11 thus confirming Sobel s 1987 argument In the same paper they suspected Godel s original version of the axioms note 12 to be inconsistent as they failed to prove their consistency note 13 In 2016 they gave an automated proof that the original version implies displaystyle Diamond Box bot nbsp i e is inconsistent in every modal logic with a reflexive or symmetric accessibility relation 24 940 lf Moreover they gave an argument that this version is inconsistent in every logic at all note 14 but failed to duplicate it by automated provers note 15 However they were able to verify Melvin Fitting s reformulation of the argument and guarantee its consistency 25 In literature editA humorous variant of Godel s ontological proof is mentioned in Quentin Canterel s novel The Jolly Coroner 26 page needed The proof is also mentioned in the TV series Hand of God specify Jeffrey Kegler s 2007 novel The God Proof depicts the fictional rediscovery of Godel s lost notebook about the ontological proof 27 See also editExistence of God Philosophy of religion Theism Ontological argumentNotes edit Godel s answer to a special questionnaire sent him by the sociologist Burke Grandjean This answer is quoted directly in Wang 1987 p 18 and indirectly in Wang 1996 p 112 It s also quoted directly in Dawson 1997 p 6 who cites Wang 1987 The Grandjean questionnaire is perhaps the most extended autobiographical item in Godel s papers Godel filled it out in pencil and wrote a cover letter but he never returned it Theistic is italicized in both Wang 1987 and Wang 1996 It is possible that this italicization is Wang s and not Godel s The quote follows Wang 1987 with two corrections taken from Wang 1996 Wang 1987 reads Baptist Lutheran where Wang 1996 has baptized Lutheran Baptist Lutheran makes no sense especially in context and was presumably a typo or mistranscription Wang 1987 has rel cong which in Wang 1996 is expanded to religious congregation It assumes that it is possible to single out positive properties from among all properties Godel comments that Positive means positive in the moral aesthetic sense independently of the accidental structure of the world It may also mean pure attribution as opposed to privation or containing privation Godel 1995 see also manuscript in Gawlick 2012 As a profane example if the property of being green is positive that of not being red is too by axiom 1 hence that of being red is negative by axiom 2 More generally at most one color can be considered positive Continuing the color example a godlike object must have the unique color that is considered positive or no color at all both alternatives may seem counter intuitive If one considers the partial order displaystyle preceq nbsp defined by f ps displaystyle varphi preceq psi nbsp if y f y ps y displaystyle square forall y varphi y to psi y nbsp then Axioms 1 3 can be summarized by saying that positive properties form an ultrafilter on this ordering Definition 1 and Axiom 4 are needed to establish the Godlike property as principal element of the ultrafilter By removing all modal operators from axioms definitions proofs and theorems a modified version of theorem 2 is obtained saying x G x i e There exists an object which has all positive but no negative properties Nothing more than axioms 1 3 definition 1 and theorems 1 2 needs to be considered for this result Formally p p displaystyle p Rightarrow Box p nbsp for all p implies p p displaystyle Diamond p Rightarrow p nbsp for all p by indirect proof and p p displaystyle Box p Rightarrow Diamond p nbsp holds for all p whenever there are accessible worlds Since Sobel s proof of modal collapse uses lambda abstraction but Godel s proof does not Koons suggests to forbid this property construction operation as the most conservative measure before rejecting or emending axioms as Anderson does Lines T3 in Fig 2 and item 3 in section 4 Main findings Their theorem T3 corresponds to Th 4 shown above Line CO in Fig 2 and item 1 in section 4 p 97 Line MC in Fig 2 and item 6 in section 4 p 97 The version shown here is by Dana Scott 23 It differs from Godel s original by omitting the first conjunct f x displaystyle varphi x nbsp in Df 2 Lines CO in Fig 2 and item 5 in section 4 p 97 Item 8 in section 4 1 Informal argument p 940 See the detailed discussion in section 4 Intuitive Inconsistency Argument p 939 941 References edit In Wang Hao A Logical Journey From Godel to Philosophy A Bradford Book 1997 Print p 316 Quoted in Godel 1995 p 388 The German original is quoted in Dawson 1997 p 307 The nested parentheses are in Morgenstern s original diary entry as quoted by Dawson The publication history of the proof in this paragraph is from Godel 1995 p 388 Dawson 1997 pp 6 Dawson 1997 pp 210 212 Wang 1996 p 317 The ellipsis is Wikipedia s Wang 1996 p 51 Godel s proof is reprinted on p 403 404 429 437 of Kurt Godel Mar 1995 Solomon Feferman and John W Dawson jr and Warren Goldfarb and Charles Parsons and Robert M Solovay ed Unpublished Essays and Lectures PDF Collected Works Vol III 1st ed Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 0 19 507255 3 a b c Robert C Koons Jul 2005 Sobel on Godel s Ontological Proof PDF Unpublished Paper University of Texas at Austin Archived from the original PDF on 2020 08 02 The presentation below follows that in Koons 2005 9 p 3 7 Fitting 2002 p 139 Jordan Howard Sobel Nov 1987 Godel s ontological proof In Judith Jarvis Thomson ed On Being and Saying Essays for Richard Cartwright Cambridge MA amp London England MIT Press pp 241 261 ISBN 978 0262200639 Kurt Godel Mar 1995 Texts Relating to the Ontological Proof App B In Solomon Feferman John W Dawson jr Warren Goldfarb Charles Parsons Robert M Solovay eds Unpublished Essays and Lectures PDF Collected Works Vol III 1st ed Oxford Oxford University Press pp 429 437 ISBN 0 19 507255 3 Here p 435 probably Sobel referred to Godel s note 4 If f x f x displaystyle varphi x Rightarrow Box varphi x nbsp is assumed as following from the essence of x displaystyle x nbsp but that is the inferior way Rather f x f x displaystyle varphi x Rightarrow Box varphi x nbsp should follow first from the existence of God The note might indicate that Godel was aware of his axioms implying modal collapse Curtis Anthony Anderson Jul 1990 Some Emendations of Godel s Ontological Proof PDF Faith and Philosophy 7 3 291 303 doi 10 5840 faithphil19907325 Archived PDF from the original on 2015 06 04 Curtis Anthony Anderson and Michael Gettings Aug 1996 Godel s ontological proof revisited In Petr Hajek ed Proc Godel 96 Logical Foundations of Mathematics Computer Science and Physics Kurt Godel s Legacy Lecture Notes in Logic Vol 6 Springer pp 167 172 Graham Oppy Oct 1996 Godelian ontological arguments Analysis 54 4 226 230 doi 10 1093 analys 56 4 226 Longer version 2005 Gettings Michael 1999 Godel s ontological argument a reply to Oppy Analysis 59 264 309 313 doi 10 1111 1467 8284 00184 inactive 31 January 2024 a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a CS1 maint DOI inactive as of January 2024 link Godel s Theorem and the Existence of God Magis Center 2017 04 26 Retrieved 2018 05 23 Andre Fuhrmann 2005 Existenz und Notwendigkeit Kurt Godels axiomatische Theologie Existence and Necessity Kurt Godel s Axiomatic Theology PDF In W Spohn ed Logik in der Philosophie Logic in Philosophy in German Heidelberg Synchron pp 349 374 Archived PDF from the original on 2016 05 18 FormalTheology GoedelGod GitHub 28 June 2021 Knight David 23 October 2013 Scientists Use Computer to Mathematically Prove Godel s God Theorem Der Spiegel Retrieved 28 October 2013 Christoph Benzmuller and Bruno Woltzenlogel Paleo 2014 Automating Godel s Ontological Proof of God s Existence with Higher Order Automated Theorem Provers PDF Proc European Conference on Artificial Intelligence Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence and Applications Vol 263 IOS Press pp 93 98 Archived PDF from the original on 2014 07 14 D Scott 2004 Appendix B Notes in Dana Scott s Hand 1972 In J H Sobel ed Logic and Theism Arguments for and Against Beliefs in God Cambridge Cambridge University Press pp 145 146 ISBN 978 0511497988 Christoph Benzmuller and Bruno Woltzenlogel Paleo Jul 2016 The Inconsistency in Godel s Ontological Argument A Success Story for AI in Metaphysics PDF In Subbarao Kambhampati ed Proc 25th International Joint Conference on Artificial Intelligence AAAI Press pp 936 942 Archived PDF from the original on 2016 11 13 Christoph Benzmuller and David Fuenmayor May 2017 Types Tableaus and Godel s God in Isabelle HOL Archive of Formal Proofs ISSN 2150 914X Quentin Canterel 2015 The Jolly Coroner A Picaresque Novel Acorn Independent Press Jeffrey Kegler 2007 The God Proof full text online Further reading editFrode Alfson Bjordal Understanding Godel s Ontological Argument in T Childers ed The Logica Yearbook 1998 Prague 1999 214 217 Frode Alfson Bjordal All Properties are Divine or God Exists in Logic and Logical Philosophy Vol 27 No 3 2018 pp 329 350 Bromand Joachim Godels ontologischer Beweis und andere modallogische Gottesbeweise in J Bromand und G Kreis Hg Gottesbeweise von Anselm bis Godel Berlin 2011 381 491 John W Dawson Jr 1997 Logical Dilemmas The Life and Work of Kurt Godel Wellesley Mass AK Peters Ltd ISBN 1 56881 025 3 Melvin Fitting Types Tableaus and Godel s God Publisher Dordrecht Kluwer Academic 2002 ISBN 1 4020 0604 7 ISBN 978 1 4020 0604 3 Kurt Godel Mar 1995 Solomon Feferman John W Dawson jr Warren Goldfarb Charles parsons Robert M Solovay eds Unpublished Essays and Lectures PDF Collected Works Vol III 1st ed Oxford Oxford University Press ISBN 0 19 507255 3 See Chapter Ontological Proof pp 403 404 and Appendix B Texts Relating to the Ontological Proof pp 429 437 Goldman Randolph R Godel s Ontological Argument PhD Diss University of California Berkeley 2000 Hazen A P On Godel s Ontological Proof Australasian Journal of Philosophy Vol 76 No 3 pp 361 377 September 1998 Small Christopher Reflections on Godel s Ontological Argument PDF University of Waterloo Archived from the original PDF on 2009 12 22 Retrieved 2010 08 31 Wang Hao 1987 Reflections on Kurt Godel Cambridge Mass MIT Press ISBN 0 262 23127 1 Wang Hao 1996 A Logical Journey from Godel to Philosophy Cambridge Mass MIT Press ISBN 0 262 23189 1 External links editOppy Graham Ontological arguments In Zalta Edward N ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Annotated bibliography of studies on Godel s Ontological Argument Thomas Gawlick Was sind und was sollen mathematische Gottesbeweise Jan 2012 shows Godel s original proof manuscript on p 2 3 A Divine Consistency Proof for Mathematics A submitted work by Harvey Friedman showing that if God exists in the sense of Godel then Mathematics as formalized by the usual ZFC axioms is consistent Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Godel 27s ontological proof amp oldid 1218382624, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.