fbpx
Wikipedia

Extreme value theorem

In calculus, the extreme value theorem states that if a real-valued function is continuous on the closed interval , then must attain a maximum and a minimum, each at least once. That is, there exist numbers and in such that:

A continuous function on the closed interval showing the absolute max (red) and the absolute min (blue).

The extreme value theorem is more specific than the related boundedness theorem, which states merely that a continuous function on the closed interval is bounded on that interval; that is, there exist real numbers and such that:

This does not say that and are necessarily the maximum and minimum values of on the interval which is what the extreme value theorem stipulates must also be the case.

The extreme value theorem is used to prove Rolle's theorem. In a formulation due to Karl Weierstrass, this theorem states that a continuous function from a non-empty compact space to a subset of the real numbers attains a maximum and a minimum.

History

The extreme value theorem was originally proven by Bernard Bolzano in the 1830s in a work Function Theory but the work remained unpublished until 1930. Bolzano's proof consisted of showing that a continuous function on a closed interval was bounded, and then showing that the function attained a maximum and a minimum value. Both proofs involved what is known today as the Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem.[1]

Functions to which the theorem does not apply

The following examples show why the function domain must be closed and bounded in order for the theorem to apply. Each fails to attain a maximum on the given interval.

  1.   defined over   is not bounded from above.
  2.   defined over   is bounded but does not attain its least upper bound  .
  3.   defined over   is not bounded from above.
  4.   defined over   is bounded but never attains its least upper bound  .

Defining   in the last two examples shows that both theorems require continuity on  .

Generalization to metric and topological spaces

When moving from the real line   to metric spaces and general topological spaces, the appropriate generalization of a closed bounded interval is a compact set. A set   is said to be compact if it has the following property: from every collection of open sets   such that  , a finite subcollection  can be chosen such that  . This is usually stated in short as "every open cover of   has a finite subcover". The Heine–Borel theorem asserts that a subset of the real line is compact if and only if it is both closed and bounded. Correspondingly, a metric space has the Heine–Borel property if every closed and bounded set is also compact.

The concept of a continuous function can likewise be generalized. Given topological spaces  , a function   is said to be continuous if for every open set  ,   is also open. Given these definitions, continuous functions can be shown to preserve compactness:[2]

Theorem. If   are topological spaces,   is a continuous function, and   is compact, then   is also compact.

In particular, if  , then this theorem implies that   is closed and bounded for any compact set  , which in turn implies that   attains its supremum and infimum on any (nonempty) compact set  . Thus, we have the following generalization of the extreme value theorem:[2]

Theorem. If   is a compact set and   is a continuous function, then   is bounded and there exist   such that   and  .

Slightly more generally, this is also true for an upper semicontinuous function. (see compact space#Functions and compact spaces).

Proving the theorems

We look at the proof for the upper bound and the maximum of  . By applying these results to the function  , the existence of the lower bound and the result for the minimum of   follows. Also note that everything in the proof is done within the context of the real numbers.

We first prove the boundedness theorem, which is a step in the proof of the extreme value theorem. The basic steps involved in the proof of the extreme value theorem are:

  1. Prove the boundedness theorem.
  2. Find a sequence so that its image converges to the supremum of  .
  3. Show that there exists a subsequence that converges to a point in the domain.
  4. Use continuity to show that the image of the subsequence converges to the supremum.

Proof of the boundedness theorem

Statement   If   is continuous on   then it is bounded on  

Suppose the function   is not bounded above on the interval  . Then, for every natural number  , there exists an   such that  . This defines a sequence  . Because   is bounded, the Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem implies that there exists a convergent subsequence   of  . Denote its limit by  . As   is closed, it contains  . Because   is continuous at  , we know that   converges to the real number   (as   is sequentially continuous at  ). But   for every  , which implies that   diverges to  , a contradiction. Therefore,   is bounded above on   

Alternative proof

Statement   If   is continuous on   then it is bounded on  

Proof    Consider the set   of points   in   such that   is bounded on  . We note that   is one such point, for   is bounded on   by the value  . If   is another point, then all points between   and   also belong to  . In other words   is an interval closed at its left end by  .

Now   is continuous on the right at  , hence there exists   such that   for all   in  . Thus   is bounded by   and   on the interval   so that all these points belong to  .

So far, we know that   is an interval of non-zero length, closed at its left end by  .

Next,   is bounded above by  . Hence the set   has a supremum in   ; let us call it  . From the non-zero length of   we can deduce that  .

Suppose  . Now   is continuous at  , hence there exists   such that   for all   in   so that   is bounded on this interval. But it follows from the supremacy of   that there exists a point belonging to  ,   say, which is greater than  . Thus   is bounded on   which overlaps   so that   is bounded on  . This however contradicts the supremacy of  .

We must therefore have  . Now   is continuous on the left at  , hence there exists   such that   for all   in   so that   is bounded on this interval. But it follows from the supremacy of   that there exists a point belonging to  ,   say, which is greater than  . Thus   is bounded on   which overlaps   so that   is bounded on  .  

Proof of the extreme value theorem

By the boundedness theorem, f is bounded from above, hence, by the Dedekind-completeness of the real numbers, the least upper bound (supremum) M of f exists. It is necessary to find a point d in [a, b] such that M = f(d). Let n be a natural number. As M is the least upper bound, M – 1/n is not an upper bound for f. Therefore, there exists dn in [a, b] so that M – 1/n < f(dn). This defines a sequence {dn}. Since M is an upper bound for f, we have M – 1/n < f(dn) ≤ M for all n. Therefore, the sequence {f(dn)} converges to M.

The Bolzano–Weierstrass theorem tells us that there exists a subsequence { }, which converges to some d and, as [a, b] is closed, d is in [a, b]. Since f is continuous at d, the sequence {f( )} converges to f(d). But {f(dnk)} is a subsequence of {f(dn)} that converges to M, so M = f(d). Therefore, f attains its supremum M at d

Alternative proof of the extreme value theorem

The set {yR : y = f(x) for some x ∈ [a,b]} is a bounded set. Hence, its least upper bound exists by least upper bound property of the real numbers. Let M = sup(f(x)) on [a, b]. If there is no point x on [ab] so that f(x) = M ,then f(x) < M on [ab]. Therefore, 1/(Mf(x)) is continuous on [a, b].

However, to every positive number ε, there is always some x in [ab] such that Mf(x) < ε because M is the least upper bound. Hence, 1/(Mf(x)) > 1/ε, which means that 1/(Mf(x)) is not bounded. Since every continuous function on a [a, b] is bounded, this contradicts the conclusion that 1/(Mf(x)) was continuous on [ab]. Therefore, there must be a point x in [ab] such that f(x) = M.

Proof using the hyperreals

In the setting of non-standard calculus, let N  be an infinite hyperinteger. The interval [0, 1] has a natural hyperreal extension. Consider its partition into N subintervals of equal infinitesimal length 1/N, with partition points xi = i /N as i "runs" from 0 to N. The function ƒ  is also naturally extended to a function ƒ* defined on the hyperreals between 0 and 1. Note that in the standard setting (when N  is finite), a point with the maximal value of ƒ can always be chosen among the N+1 points xi, by induction. Hence, by the transfer principle, there is a hyperinteger i0 such that 0 ≤ i0 ≤ N and    for all i = 0, ..., N. Consider the real point

 
where st is the standard part function. An arbitrary real point x lies in a suitable sub-interval of the partition, namely  , so that  st(xi) = x. Applying st to the inequality  , we obtain  . By continuity of ƒ  we have
 .

Hence ƒ(c) ≥ ƒ(x), for all real x, proving c to be a maximum of ƒ.[3]

Proof from first principles

Statement      If   is continuous on   then it attains its supremum on  

Proof      By the Boundedness Theorem,   is bounded above on   and by the completeness property of the real numbers has a supremum in  . Let us call it  , or  . It is clear that the restriction of   to the subinterval   where   has a supremum   which is less than or equal to  , and that   increases from   to   as   increases from   to  .

If   then we are done. Suppose therefore that   and let  . Consider the set   of points   in   such that  .

Clearly   ; moreover if   is another point in   then all points between   and   also belong to   because   is monotonic increasing. Hence   is a non-empty interval, closed at its left end by  .

Now   is continuous on the right at  , hence there exists   such that   for all   in  . Thus   is less than   on the interval   so that all these points belong to  .

Next,   is bounded above by   and has therefore a supremum in  : let us call it  . We see from the above that  . We will show that   is the point we are seeking i.e. the point where   attains its supremum, or in other words  .

Suppose the contrary viz.  . Let   and consider the following two cases:

  1.  .   As   is continuous at  , there exists   such that   for all   in  . This means that   is less than   on the interval  . But it follows from the supremacy of   that there exists a point,   say, belonging to   which is greater than  . By the definition of  ,  . Let   then for all   in  ,  . Taking   to be the minimum of   and  , we have   for all   in  .
    Hence   so that  . This however contradicts the supremacy of   and completes the proof.
  2.  .   As   is continuous on the left at  , there exists   such that   for all   in  . This means that   is less than   on the interval  . But it follows from the supremacy of   that there exists a point,   say, belonging to   which is greater than  . By the definition of  ,  . Let   then for all   in  ,  . Taking   to be the minimum of   and  , we have   for all   in  . This contradicts the supremacy of   and completes the proof.

Extension to semi-continuous functions

If the continuity of the function f is weakened to semi-continuity, then the corresponding half of the boundedness theorem and the extreme value theorem hold and the values –∞ or +∞, respectively, from the extended real number line can be allowed as possible values. More precisely:

Theorem: If a function f : [a, b] → [–∞, ∞) is upper semi-continuous, meaning that

 
for all x in [a,b], then f is bounded above and attains its supremum.

Proof: If f(x) = –∞ for all x in [a,b], then the supremum is also –∞ and the theorem is true. In all other cases, the proof is a slight modification of the proofs given above. In the proof of the boundedness theorem, the upper semi-continuity of f at x only implies that the limit superior of the subsequence {f(xnk)} is bounded above by f(x) < ∞, but that is enough to obtain the contradiction. In the proof of the extreme value theorem, upper semi-continuity of f at d implies that the limit superior of the subsequence {f(dnk)} is bounded above by f(d), but this suffices to conclude that f(d) = M

Applying this result to −f proves:

Theorem: If a function f : [a, b] → (–∞, ∞] is lower semi-continuous, meaning that

 
for all x in [a,b], then f is bounded below and attains its infimum.

A real-valued function is upper as well as lower semi-continuous, if and only if it is continuous in the usual sense. Hence these two theorems imply the boundedness theorem and the extreme value theorem.

References

  1. ^ Rusnock, Paul; Kerr-Lawson, Angus (2005). "Bolzano and Uniform Continuity". Historia Mathematica. 32 (3): 303–311. doi:10.1016/j.hm.2004.11.003.
  2. ^ a b Rudin, Walter (1976). Principles of Mathematical Analysis. New York: McGraw Hill. pp. 89–90. ISBN 0-07-054235-X.
  3. ^ Keisler, H. Jerome (1986). Elementary Calculus : An Infinitesimal Approach (PDF). Boston: Prindle, Weber & Schmidt. p. 164. ISBN 0-87150-911-3.

Further reading

External links

extreme, value, theorem, this, article, about, calculus, concept, statistical, concept, fisher, tippett, gnedenko, theorem, this, article, includes, list, general, references, lacks, sufficient, corresponding, inline, citations, please, help, improve, this, ar. This article is about the calculus concept For the statistical concept see Fisher Tippett Gnedenko theorem This article includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this article by introducing more precise citations June 2012 Learn how and when to remove this template message In calculus the extreme value theorem states that if a real valued function f f is continuous on the closed interval a b a b then f f must attain a maximum and a minimum each at least once That is there exist numbers c c and d d in a b a b such that A continuous function f x f x on the closed interval a b a b showing the absolute max red and the absolute min blue f c f x f d x a b displaystyle f c geq f x geq f d quad forall x in a b The extreme value theorem is more specific than the related boundedness theorem which states merely that a continuous function f f on the closed interval a b a b is bounded on that interval that is there exist real numbers m m and M M such that m f x M x a b displaystyle m leq f x leq M quad forall x in a b This does not say that M M and m m are necessarily the maximum and minimum values of f f on the interval a b a b which is what the extreme value theorem stipulates must also be the case The extreme value theorem is used to prove Rolle s theorem In a formulation due to Karl Weierstrass this theorem states that a continuous function from a non empty compact space to a subset of the real numbers attains a maximum and a minimum Contents 1 History 2 Functions to which the theorem does not apply 3 Generalization to metric and topological spaces 4 Proving the theorems 4 1 Proof of the boundedness theorem 4 2 Alternative proof 4 3 Proof of the extreme value theorem 4 4 Alternative proof of the extreme value theorem 4 5 Proof using the hyperreals 4 6 Proof from first principles 5 Extension to semi continuous functions 6 References 7 Further reading 8 External linksHistory EditThe extreme value theorem was originally proven by Bernard Bolzano in the 1830s in a work Function Theory but the work remained unpublished until 1930 Bolzano s proof consisted of showing that a continuous function on a closed interval was bounded and then showing that the function attained a maximum and a minimum value Both proofs involved what is known today as the Bolzano Weierstrass theorem 1 Functions to which the theorem does not apply EditThe following examples show why the function domain must be closed and bounded in order for the theorem to apply Each fails to attain a maximum on the given interval f x x displaystyle f x x defined over 0 0 infty is not bounded from above f x x 1 x displaystyle f x frac x 1 x defined over 0 0 infty is bounded but does not attain its least upper bound 1 1 f x 1 x displaystyle f x frac 1 x defined over 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 is not bounded from above f x 1 x displaystyle f x 1 x defined over 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 is bounded but never attains its least upper bound 1 1 Defining f 0 0 f 0 0 in the last two examples shows that both theorems require continuity on a b a b Generalization to metric and topological spaces EditWhen moving from the real line R mathbb R to metric spaces and general topological spaces the appropriate generalization of a closed bounded interval is a compact set A set K K is said to be compact if it has the following property from every collection of open sets U a U alpha such that U a K textstyle bigcup U alpha supset K a finite subcollection U a 1 U a n displaystyle U alpha 1 ldots U alpha n can be chosen such that i 1 n U a i K textstyle bigcup i 1 n U alpha i supset K This is usually stated in short as every open cover of K K has a finite subcover The Heine Borel theorem asserts that a subset of the real line is compact if and only if it is both closed and bounded Correspondingly a metric space has the Heine Borel property if every closed and bounded set is also compact The concept of a continuous function can likewise be generalized Given topological spaces V W displaystyle V W a function f V W f V to W is said to be continuous if for every open set U W displaystyle U subset W f 1 U V displaystyle f 1 U subset V is also open Given these definitions continuous functions can be shown to preserve compactness 2 Theorem If V W displaystyle V W are topological spaces f V W f V to W is a continuous function and K V displaystyle K subset V is compact then f K W displaystyle f K subset W is also compact In particular if W R displaystyle W mathbb R then this theorem implies that f K f K is closed and bounded for any compact set K K which in turn implies that f f attains its supremum and infimum on any nonempty compact set K K Thus we have the following generalization of the extreme value theorem 2 Theorem If K K is a compact set and f K R displaystyle f K to mathbb R is a continuous function then f f is bounded and there exist p q K displaystyle p q in K such that f p sup x K f x textstyle f p sup x in K f x and f q inf x K f x textstyle f q inf x in K f x Slightly more generally this is also true for an upper semicontinuous function see compact space Functions and compact spaces Proving the theorems EditWe look at the proof for the upper bound and the maximum of f f By applying these results to the function f f the existence of the lower bound and the result for the minimum of f f follows Also note that everything in the proof is done within the context of the real numbers We first prove the boundedness theorem which is a step in the proof of the extreme value theorem The basic steps involved in the proof of the extreme value theorem are Prove the boundedness theorem Find a sequence so that its image converges to the supremum of f f Show that there exists a subsequence that converges to a point in the domain Use continuity to show that the image of the subsequence converges to the supremum Proof of the boundedness theorem Edit Statement If f x f x is continuous on a b a b then it is bounded on a b a b Suppose the function f f is not bounded above on the interval a b a b Then for every natural number n n there exists an x n a b displaystyle x n in a b such that f x n gt n displaystyle f x n gt n This defines a sequence x n n N displaystyle x n n in mathbb N Because a b a b is bounded the Bolzano Weierstrass theorem implies that there exists a convergent subsequence x n k k N displaystyle x n k k in mathbb N of x n displaystyle x n Denote its limit by x x As a b a b is closed it contains x x Because f f is continuous at x x we know that f x n k displaystyle f x n k converges to the real number f x f x as f f is sequentially continuous at x x But f x n k gt n k k displaystyle f x n k gt n k geq k for every k k which implies that f x n k displaystyle f x n k diverges to displaystyle infty a contradiction Therefore f f is bounded above on a b a b Box Alternative proof Edit Statement If f x f x is continuous on a b a b then it is bounded on a b a b Proof Consider the set B B of points p p in a b a b such that f x f x is bounded on a p displaystyle a p We note that a a is one such point for f x f x is bounded on a a displaystyle a a by the value f a f a If e gt a displaystyle e gt a is another point then all points between a a and e e also belong to B B In other words B B is an interval closed at its left end by a a Now f f is continuous on the right at a a hence there exists d gt 0 delta gt 0 such that f x f a lt 1 displaystyle f x f a lt 1 for all x x in a a d displaystyle a a delta Thus f f is bounded by f a 1 displaystyle f a 1 and f a 1 displaystyle f a 1 on the interval a a d displaystyle a a delta so that all these points belong to B B So far we know that B B is an interval of non zero length closed at its left end by a a Next B B is bounded above by b b Hence the set B B has a supremum in a b a b let us call it s s From the non zero length of B B we can deduce that s gt a displaystyle s gt a Suppose s lt b displaystyle s lt b Now f f is continuous at s s hence there exists d gt 0 delta gt 0 such that f x f s lt 1 displaystyle f x f s lt 1 for all x x in s d s d displaystyle s delta s delta so that f f is bounded on this interval But it follows from the supremacy of s s that there exists a point belonging to B B e e say which is greater than s d 2 displaystyle s delta 2 Thus f f is bounded on a e displaystyle a e which overlaps s d s d displaystyle s delta s delta so that f f is bounded on a s d displaystyle a s delta This however contradicts the supremacy of s s We must therefore have s b displaystyle s b Now f f is continuous on the left at s s hence there exists d gt 0 delta gt 0 such that f x f s lt 1 displaystyle f x f s lt 1 for all x x in s d s displaystyle s delta s so that f f is bounded on this interval But it follows from the supremacy of s s that there exists a point belonging to B B e e say which is greater than s d 2 displaystyle s delta 2 Thus f f is bounded on a e displaystyle a e which overlaps s d s displaystyle s delta s so that f f is bounded on a s displaystyle a s Proof of the extreme value theorem Edit By the boundedness theorem f is bounded from above hence by the Dedekind completeness of the real numbers the least upper bound supremum M of f exists It is necessary to find a point d in a b such that M f d Let n be a natural number As M is the least upper bound M 1 n is not an upper bound for f Therefore there exists dn in a b so that M 1 n lt f dn This defines a sequence dn Since M is an upper bound for f we have M 1 n lt f dn M for all n Therefore the sequence f dn converges to M The Bolzano Weierstrass theorem tells us that there exists a subsequence d n k d n k which converges to some d and as a b is closed d is in a b Since f is continuous at d the sequence f d n k d n k converges to f d But f dnk is a subsequence of f dn that converges to M so M f d Therefore f attains its supremum M at d Alternative proof of the extreme value theorem Edit The set y R y f x for some x a b is a bounded set Hence its least upper bound exists by least upper bound property of the real numbers Let M sup f x on a b If there is no point x on a b so that f x M then f x lt M on a b Therefore 1 M f x is continuous on a b However to every positive number e there is always some x in a b such that M f x lt e because M is the least upper bound Hence 1 M f x gt 1 e which means that 1 M f x is not bounded Since every continuous function on a a b is bounded this contradicts the conclusion that 1 M f x was continuous on a b Therefore there must be a point x in a b such that f x M Proof using the hyperreals Edit In the setting of non standard calculus let N be an infinite hyperinteger The interval 0 1 has a natural hyperreal extension Consider its partition into N subintervals of equal infinitesimal length 1 N with partition points xi i N as i runs from 0 to N The function ƒ is also naturally extended to a function ƒ defined on the hyperreals between 0 and 1 Note that in the standard setting when N is finite a point with the maximal value of ƒ can always be chosen among the N 1 points xi by induction Hence by the transfer principle there is a hyperinteger i0 such that 0 i0 N and f x i 0 f x i f x i 0 geq f x i for all i 0 N Consider the real pointc s t x i 0 displaystyle c mathbf st x i 0 where st is the standard part function An arbitrary real point x lies in a suitable sub interval of the partition namely x x i x i 1 x in x i x i 1 so that st xi x Applying st to the inequality f x i 0 f x i f x i 0 geq f x i we obtain s t f x i 0 s t f x i mathbf st f x i 0 geq mathbf st f x i By continuity of ƒ we have s t f x i 0 f s t x i 0 f c mathbf st f x i 0 f mathbf st x i 0 f c Hence ƒ c ƒ x for all real x proving c to be a maximum of ƒ 3 Proof from first principles Edit Statement If f x f x is continuous on a b a b then it attains its supremum on a b a b Proof By the Boundedness Theorem f x f x is bounded above on a b a b and by the completeness property of the real numbers has a supremum in a b a b Let us call it M M or M a b displaystyle M a b It is clear that the restriction of f f to the subinterval a x displaystyle a x where x b displaystyle x leq b has a supremum M a x displaystyle M a x which is less than or equal to M M and that M a x displaystyle M a x increases from f a f a to M M as x x increases from a a to b b If f a M displaystyle f a M then we are done Suppose therefore that f a lt M displaystyle f a lt M and let d M f a displaystyle d M f a Consider the set L L of points x x in a b a b such that M a x lt M displaystyle M a x lt M Clearly a L displaystyle a in L moreover if e gt a displaystyle e gt a is another point in L L then all points between a a and e e also belong to L L because M a x displaystyle M a x is monotonic increasing Hence L L is a non empty interval closed at its left end by a a Now f f is continuous on the right at a a hence there exists d gt 0 delta gt 0 such that f x f a lt d 2 displaystyle f x f a lt d 2 for all x x in a a d displaystyle a a delta Thus f f is less than M d 2 displaystyle M d 2 on the interval a a d displaystyle a a delta so that all these points belong to L L Next L L is bounded above by b b and has therefore a supremum in a b a b let us call it s s We see from the above that s gt a displaystyle s gt a We will show that s s is the point we are seeking i e the point where f f attains its supremum or in other words f s M displaystyle f s M Suppose the contrary viz f s lt M displaystyle f s lt M Let d M f s displaystyle d M f s and consider the following two cases s lt b displaystyle s lt b As f f is continuous at s s there exists d gt 0 delta gt 0 such that f x f s lt d 2 displaystyle f x f s lt d 2 for all x x in s d s d displaystyle s delta s delta This means that f f is less than M d 2 displaystyle M d 2 on the interval s d s d displaystyle s delta s delta But it follows from the supremacy of s s that there exists a point e e say belonging to L L which is greater than s d displaystyle s delta By the definition of L L M a e lt M displaystyle M a e lt M Let d 1 M M a e displaystyle d 1 M M a e then for all x x in a e displaystyle a e f x M d 1 displaystyle f x leq M d 1 Taking d 2 d 2 to be the minimum of d 2 d 2 and d 1 d 1 we have f x M d 2 displaystyle f x leq M d 2 for all x x in a s d displaystyle a s delta Hence M a s d lt M displaystyle M a s delta lt M so that s d L displaystyle s delta in L This however contradicts the supremacy of s s and completes the proof s b displaystyle s b As f f is continuous on the left at s s there exists d gt 0 delta gt 0 such that f x f s lt d 2 displaystyle f x f s lt d 2 for all x x in s d s displaystyle s delta s This means that f f is less than M d 2 displaystyle M d 2 on the interval s d s displaystyle s delta s But it follows from the supremacy of s s that there exists a point e e say belonging to L L which is greater than s d displaystyle s delta By the definition of L L M a e lt M displaystyle M a e lt M Let d 1 M M a e displaystyle d 1 M M a e then for all x x in a e displaystyle a e f x M d 1 displaystyle f x leq M d 1 Taking d 2 d 2 to be the minimum of d 2 d 2 and d 1 d 1 we have f x M d 2 displaystyle f x leq M d 2 for all x x in a b a b This contradicts the supremacy of M M and completes the proof Extension to semi continuous functions EditIf the continuity of the function f is weakened to semi continuity then the corresponding half of the boundedness theorem and the extreme value theorem hold and the values or respectively from the extended real number line can be allowed as possible values More precisely Theorem If a function f a b is upper semi continuous meaning thatlim sup y x f y f x displaystyle limsup y to x f y leq f x for all x in a b then f is bounded above and attains its supremum Proof If f x for all x in a b then the supremum is also and the theorem is true In all other cases the proof is a slight modification of the proofs given above In the proof of the boundedness theorem the upper semi continuity of f at x only implies that the limit superior of the subsequence f xnk is bounded above by f x lt but that is enough to obtain the contradiction In the proof of the extreme value theorem upper semi continuity of f at d implies that the limit superior of the subsequence f dnk is bounded above by f d but this suffices to conclude that f d M Applying this result to f proves Theorem If a function f a b is lower semi continuous meaning thatlim inf y x f y f x displaystyle liminf y to x f y geq f x for all x in a b then f is bounded below and attains its infimum A real valued function is upper as well as lower semi continuous if and only if it is continuous in the usual sense Hence these two theorems imply the boundedness theorem and the extreme value theorem References Edit Rusnock Paul Kerr Lawson Angus 2005 Bolzano and Uniform Continuity Historia Mathematica 32 3 303 311 doi 10 1016 j hm 2004 11 003 a b Rudin Walter 1976 Principles of Mathematical Analysis New York McGraw Hill pp 89 90 ISBN 0 07 054235 X Keisler H Jerome 1986 Elementary Calculus An Infinitesimal Approach PDF Boston Prindle Weber amp Schmidt p 164 ISBN 0 87150 911 3 Further reading EditAdams Robert A 1995 Calculus A Complete Course Reading Addison Wesley pp 706 707 ISBN 0 201 82823 5 Protter M H Morrey C B 1977 The Boundedness and Extreme Value Theorems A First Course in Real Analysis New York Springer pp 71 73 ISBN 0 387 90215 5 External links EditA Proof for extreme value theorem at cut the knot Extreme Value Theorem by Jacqueline Wandzura with additional contributions by Stephen Wandzura the Wolfram Demonstrations Project Weisstein Eric W Extreme Value Theorem MathWorld Mizar system proof http mizar org version current html weierstr html T15 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Extreme value theorem amp oldid 1164724948, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.