fbpx
Wikipedia

Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox

The Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen (EPR) paradox is a thought experiment proposed by physicists Albert Einstein, Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen which argues that the description of physical reality provided by quantum mechanics is incomplete.[1] In a 1935 paper titled "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete?", they argued for the existence of "elements of reality" that were not part of quantum theory, and speculated that it should be possible to construct a theory containing these hidden variables. Resolutions of the paradox have important implications for the interpretation of quantum mechanics.

Albert Einstein

The thought experiment involves a pair of particles prepared in what would later become known as an entangled state. Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen pointed out that, in this state, if the position of the first particle were measured, the result of measuring the position of the second particle could be predicted. If instead the momentum of the first particle were measured, then the result of measuring the momentum of the second particle could be predicted. They argued that no action taken on the first particle could instantaneously affect the other, since this would involve information being transmitted faster than light, which is impossible according to the theory of relativity. They invoked a principle, later known as the "EPR criterion of reality", positing that: "If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (i.e., with probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there exists an element of reality corresponding to that quantity." From this, they inferred that the second particle must have a definite value of both position and of momentum prior to either quantity being measured. But quantum mechanics considers these two observables incompatible and thus does not associate simultaneous values for both to any system. Einstein, Podolsky, and Rosen therefore concluded that quantum theory does not provide a complete description of reality.[2]

The "Paradox" paper edit

The term "Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen paradox" or "EPR" arose from a paper written in 1934 after Einstein joined the Institute for Advanced Study, having fled the rise of Nazi Germany.[3][4] The original paper[5] purports to describe what must happen to "two systems I and II, which we permit to interact", and after some time "we suppose that there is no longer any interaction between the two parts." The EPR description involves "two particles, A and B, [which] interact briefly and then move off in opposite directions."[6] According to Heisenberg's uncertainty principle, it is impossible to measure both the momentum and the position of particle B exactly; however, it is possible to measure the exact position of particle A. By calculation, therefore, with the exact position of particle A known, the exact position of particle B can be known. Alternatively, the exact momentum of particle A can be measured, so the exact momentum of particle B can be worked out. As Manjit Kumar writes, "EPR argued that they had proved that ... [particle] B can have simultaneously exact values of position and momentum. ... Particle B has a position that is real and a momentum that is real. EPR appeared to have contrived a means to establish the exact values of either the momentum or the position of B due to measurements made on particle A, without the slightest possibility of particle B being physically disturbed."[6]

EPR tried to set up a paradox to question the range of true application of quantum mechanics: Quantum theory predicts that both values cannot be known for a particle, and yet the EPR thought experiment purports to show that they must all have determinate values. The EPR paper says: "We are thus forced to conclude that the quantum-mechanical description of physical reality given by wave functions is not complete."[6] The EPR paper ends by saying: "While we have thus shown that the wave function does not provide a complete description of the physical reality, we left open the question of whether or not such a description exists. We believe, however, that such a theory is possible." The 1935 EPR paper condensed the philosophical discussion into a physical argument. The authors claim that given a specific experiment, in which the outcome of a measurement is known before the measurement takes place, there must exist something in the real world, an "element of reality", that determines the measurement outcome. They postulate that these elements of reality are, in modern terminology, local, in the sense that each belongs to a certain point in spacetime. Each element may, again in modern terminology, only be influenced by events which are located in the backward light cone of its point in spacetime (i.e. in the past). These claims are founded on assumptions about nature that constitute what is now known as local realism.[7]

 
Article headline regarding the EPR paradox paper in the May 4, 1935, issue of The New York Times.

Though the EPR paper has often been taken as an exact expression of Einstein's views, it was primarily authored by Podolsky, based on discussions at the Institute for Advanced Study with Einstein and Rosen. Einstein later expressed to Erwin Schrödinger that, "it did not come out as well as I had originally wanted; rather, the essential thing was, so to speak, smothered by the formalism."[8] Einstein would later go on to present an individual account of his local realist ideas.[9] Shortly before the EPR paper appeared in the Physical Review, The New York Times ran a news story about it, under the headline "Einstein Attacks Quantum Theory".[10] The story, which quoted Podolsky, irritated Einstein, who wrote to the Times, "Any information upon which the article 'Einstein Attacks Quantum Theory' in your issue of May 4 is based was given to you without authority. It is my invariable practice to discuss scientific matters only in the appropriate forum and I deprecate advance publication of any announcement in regard to such matters in the secular press."[11]: 189 

The Times story also sought out comment from physicist Edward Condon, who said, "Of course, a great deal of the argument hinges on just what meaning is to be attached to the word 'reality' in physics."[11]: 189  The physicist and historian Max Jammer later noted, "[I]t remains a historical fact that the earliest criticism of the EPR paper — moreover, a criticism which correctly saw in Einstein's conception of physical reality the key problem of the whole issue — appeared in a daily newspaper prior to the publication of the criticized paper itself."[11]: 190 

Bohr's reply edit

The publication of the paper prompted a response by Niels Bohr, which he published in the same journal (Physical Review), in the same year, using the same title.[12] (This exchange was only one chapter in a prolonged debate between Bohr and Einstein about the nature of quantum reality.) He argued that EPR had reasoned fallaciously. Bohr said measurements of position and of momentum are complementary, meaning the choice to measure one excludes the possibility of measuring the other. Consequently, a fact deduced regarding one arrangement of laboratory apparatus could not be combined with a fact deduced by means of the other, and so, the inference of predetermined position and momentum values for the second particle was not valid. Bohr concluded that EPR's "arguments do not justify their conclusion that the quantum description turns out to be essentially incomplete."

Einstein's own argument edit

In his own publications and correspondence, Einstein indicated that he was not satisfied with the EPR paper and that Rosen had authored most of it. He later used a different argument to insist that quantum mechanics is an incomplete theory.[13][14][15][16]: 83ff  He explicitly de-emphasized EPR's attribution of "elements of reality" to the position and momentum of particle B, saying that "I couldn't care less" whether the resulting states of particle B allowed one to predict the position and momentum with certainty.[a]

For Einstein, the crucial part of the argument was the demonstration of nonlocality, that the choice of measurement done in particle A, either position or momentum, would lead to two different quantum states of particle B. He argued that, because of locality, the real state of particle B could not depend on which kind of measurement was done in A and that the quantum states therefore cannot be in one-to-one correspondence with the real states.[13] Einstein struggled unsuccessfully for the rest of his life to find a theory that could better comply with his idea of locality.

Later developments edit

Bohm's variant edit

In 1951, David Bohm proposed a variant of the EPR thought experiment in which the measurements have discrete ranges of possible outcomes, unlike the position and momentum measurements considered by EPR.[17][18][19] The EPR–Bohm thought experiment can be explained using electron–positron pairs. Suppose we have a source that emits electron–positron pairs, with the electron sent to destination A, where there is an observer named Alice, and the positron sent to destination B, where there is an observer named Bob. According to quantum mechanics, we can arrange our source so that each emitted pair occupies a quantum state called a spin singlet. The particles are thus said to be entangled. This can be viewed as a quantum superposition of two states, which we call state I and state II. In state I, the electron has spin pointing upward along the z-axis (+z) and the positron has spin pointing downward along the z-axis (−z). In state II, the electron has spin −z and the positron has spin +z. Because it is in a superposition of states, it is impossible without measuring to know the definite state of spin of either particle in the spin singlet.[20]: 421–422 

 
The EPR thought experiment, performed with electron–positron pairs. A source (center) sends particles toward two observers, electrons to Alice (left) and positrons to Bob (right), who can perform spin measurements.

Alice now measures the spin along the z-axis. She can obtain one of two possible outcomes: +z or −z. Suppose she gets +z. Informally speaking, the quantum state of the system collapses into state I. The quantum state determines the probable outcomes of any measurement performed on the system. In this case, if Bob subsequently measures spin along the z-axis, there is 100% probability that he will obtain −z. Similarly, if Alice gets −z, Bob will get +z. There is nothing special about choosing the z-axis: according to quantum mechanics the spin singlet state may equally well be expressed as a superposition of spin states pointing in the x direction.[21]: 318 

Whatever axis their spins are measured along, they are always found to be opposite. In quantum mechanics, the x-spin and z-spin are "incompatible observables", meaning the Heisenberg uncertainty principle applies to alternating measurements of them: a quantum state cannot possess a definite value for both of these variables. Suppose Alice measures the z-spin and obtains +z, so that the quantum state collapses into state I. Now, instead of measuring the z-spin as well, Bob measures the x-spin. According to quantum mechanics, when the system is in state I, Bob's x-spin measurement will have a 50% probability of producing +x and a 50% probability of -x. It is impossible to predict which outcome will appear until Bob actually performs the measurement. Therefore, Bob's positron will have a definite spin when measured along the same axis as Alice's electron, but when measured in the perpendicular axis its spin will be uniformly random. It seems as if information has propagated (faster than light) from Alice's apparatus to make Bob's positron assume a definite spin in the appropriate axis.

Bell's theorem edit

In 1964, John Stewart Bell published a paper[22] investigating the puzzling situation at that time: on one hand, the EPR paradox purportedly showed that quantum mechanics was nonlocal, and suggested that a hidden-variable theory could heal this nonlocality. On the other hand, David Bohm had recently developed the first successful hidden-variable theory, but it had a grossly nonlocal character.[23][24] Bell set out to investigate whether it was indeed possible to solve the nonlocality problem with hidden variables, and found out that first, the correlations shown in both EPR's and Bohm's versions of the paradox could indeed be explained in a local way with hidden variables, and second, that the correlations shown in his own variant of the paradox couldn't be explained by any local hidden-variable theory. This second result became known as the Bell theorem.

To understand the first result, consider the following toy hidden-variable theory introduced later by J.J. Sakurai:[25]: 239–240  in it, quantum spin-singlet states emitted by the source are actually approximate descriptions for "true" physical states possessing definite values for the z-spin and x-spin. In these "true" states, the positron going to Bob always has spin values opposite to the electron going to Alice, but the values are otherwise completely random. For example, the first pair emitted by the source might be "(+z, −x) to Alice and (−z, +x) to Bob", the next pair "(−z, −x) to Alice and (+z, +x) to Bob", and so forth. Therefore, if Bob's measurement axis is aligned with Alice's, he will necessarily get the opposite of whatever Alice gets; otherwise, he will get "+" and "−" with equal probability.

Bell showed, however, that such models can only reproduce the singlet correlations when Alice and Bob make measurements on the same axis or on perpendicular axes. As soon as other angles between their axes are allowed, local hidden-variable theories become unable to reproduce the quantum mechanical correlations. This difference, expressed using inequalities known as "Bell's inequalities", is in principle experimentally testable. After the publication of Bell's paper, a variety of experiments to test Bell's inequalities were carried out, notably by the group of Alain Aspect in the 1980s;[26] all experiments conducted to date have found behavior in line with the predictions of quantum mechanics. The present view of the situation is that quantum mechanics flatly contradicts Einstein's philosophical postulate that any acceptable physical theory must fulfill "local realism". The fact that quantum mechanics violates Bell inequalities indicates that any hidden-variable theory underlying quantum mechanics must be non-local; whether this should be taken to imply that quantum mechanics itself is non-local is a matter of continuing debate.[27][28]

Steering edit

Inspired by Schrödinger's treatment of the EPR paradox back in 1935,[29][30] Howard M. Wiseman et al. formalised it in 2007 as the phenomenon of quantum steering.[31] They defined steering as the situation where Alice's measurements on a part of an entangled state steer Bob's part of the state. That is, Bob's observations cannot be explained by a local hidden state model, where Bob would have a fixed quantum state in his side, that is classically correlated but otherwise independent of Alice's.

Locality edit

Locality has several different meanings in physics. EPR describe the principle of locality as asserting that physical processes occurring at one place should have no immediate effect on the elements of reality at another location. At first sight, this appears to be a reasonable assumption to make, as it seems to be a consequence of special relativity, which states that energy can never be transmitted faster than the speed of light without violating causality;[20]: 427–428 [32] however, it turns out that the usual rules for combining quantum mechanical and classical descriptions violate EPR's principle of locality without violating special relativity or causality.[20]: 427–428 [32] Causality is preserved because there is no way for Alice to transmit messages (i.e., information) to Bob by manipulating her measurement axis. Whichever axis she uses, she has a 50% probability of obtaining "+" and 50% probability of obtaining "−", completely at random; according to quantum mechanics, it is fundamentally impossible for her to influence what result she gets. Furthermore, Bob is able to perform his measurement only once: there is a fundamental property of quantum mechanics, the no-cloning theorem, which makes it impossible for him to make an arbitrary number of copies of the electron he receives, perform a spin measurement on each, and look at the statistical distribution of the results. Therefore, in the one measurement he is allowed to make, there is a 50% probability of getting "+" and 50% of getting "−", regardless of whether or not his axis is aligned with Alice's.

As a summary, the results of the EPR thought experiment do not contradict the predictions of special relativity. Neither the EPR paradox nor any quantum experiment demonstrates that superluminal signaling is possible; however, the principle of locality appeals powerfully to physical intuition, and Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen were unwilling to abandon it. Einstein derided the quantum mechanical predictions as "spooky action at a distance".[b] The conclusion they drew was that quantum mechanics is not a complete theory.[34]

Mathematical formulation edit

Bohm's variant of the EPR paradox can be expressed mathematically using the quantum mechanical formulation of spin. The spin degree of freedom for an electron is associated with a two-dimensional complex vector space V, with each quantum state corresponding to a vector in that space. The operators corresponding to the spin along the x, y, and z direction, denoted Sx, Sy, and Sz respectively, can be represented using the Pauli matrices:[25]: 9 

 
where   is the reduced Planck constant (or the Planck constant divided by 2π).

The eigenstates of Sz are represented as

 
and the eigenstates of Sx are represented as
 

The vector space of the electron-positron pair is  , the tensor product of the electron's and positron's vector spaces. The spin singlet state is

 
where the two terms on the right hand side are what we have referred to as state I and state II above.

From the above equations, it can be shown that the spin singlet can also be written as

 
where the terms on the right hand side are what we have referred to as state Ia and state IIa.

To illustrate the paradox, we need to show that after Alice's measurement of Sz (or Sx), Bob's value of Sz (or Sx) is uniquely determined and Bob's value of Sx (or Sz) is uniformly random. This follows from the principles of measurement in quantum mechanics. When Sz is measured, the system state   collapses into an eigenvector of Sz. If the measurement result is +z, this means that immediately after measurement the system state collapses to

 

Similarly, if Alice's measurement result is −z, the state collapses to

 
The left hand side of both equations show that the measurement of Sz on Bob's positron is now determined, it will be −z in the first case or +z in the second case. The right hand side of the equations show that the measurement of Sx on Bob's positron will return, in both cases, +x or -x with probability 1/2 each.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ "Ob die   und   als Eigenfunktionen von Observabeln   aufgefasst werden können ist mir wurst." Emphasis from the original. "Ist mir wurst" is a German expression that literally translates to "It is a sausage to me", but means "I couldn't care less". Letter from Einstein to Schrödinger, dated 19th June 1935.[14]
  2. ^ "Spukhaften Fernwirkung", in the German original. Used in a letter to Max Born dated March 3, 1947.[33]

References edit

  1. ^ Einstein, A; B Podolsky; N Rosen (1935-05-15). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete?" (PDF). Physical Review. 47 (10): 777–780. Bibcode:1935PhRv...47..777E. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.47.777.
  2. ^ Peres, Asher (2002). Quantum Theory: Concepts and Methods. Kluwer. p. 149.
  3. ^ Robinson, Andrew (2018-04-30). "Did Einstein really say that?". Nature. 557 (7703): 30. Bibcode:2018Natur.557...30R. doi:10.1038/d41586-018-05004-4. S2CID 14013938.
  4. ^ Levenson, Thomas (9 June 1917). "The Scientist and the Fascist". The Atlantic. Retrieved 28 June 2021.
  5. ^ Einstein, Albert; Podolsky, Boris; Rosen, Nathan (May 15, 1935). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?". Physical Review. 47 (10). Princeton, New Jersey: Institute for Advanced Study: 777–780. Bibcode:1935PhRv...47..777E. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.47.777.
  6. ^ a b c Kumar, Manjit (2011). Quantum: Einstein, Bohr, and the Great Debate about the Nature of Reality (Reprint ed.). W. W. Norton & Company. pp. 305–306. ISBN 978-0393339888. Retrieved September 12, 2021 – via Internet Archive.
  7. ^ Jaeger, Gregg (2014). Quantum Objects. Springer Verlag. pp. 9–15. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-37629-0. ISBN 978-3-642-37628-3.
  8. ^ Kaiser, David (1994). "Bringing the human actors back on stage: the personal context of the Einstein-Bohr debate". British Journal for the History of Science. 27 (2): 129–152. doi:10.1017/S0007087400031861. JSTOR 4027432. S2CID 145143635.
  9. ^ Einstein, Albert (1936). "Physik und Realität". Journal of the Franklin Institute. 221 (3): 313–347. doi:10.1016/S0016-0032(36)91045-1. English translation by Jean Piccard, pp 349–382 in the same issue, doi:10.1016/S0016-0032(36)91047-5).
  10. ^ "Einstein Attacks Quantum Theory". The New York Times. 4 May 1935. p. 11. Retrieved 10 January 2021.
  11. ^ a b c Jammer, Max (1974). The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics: The Interpretations of QM in Historical Perspective. John Wiley and Sons. ISBN 0-471-43958-4.
  12. ^ Bohr, N. (1935-10-13). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete?" (PDF). Physical Review. 48 (8): 696–702. Bibcode:1935PhRv...48..696B. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.48.696.
  13. ^ a b Harrigan, Nicholas; Spekkens, Robert W. (2010). "Einstein, incompleteness, and the epistemic view of quantum states". Foundations of Physics. 40 (2): 125. arXiv:0706.2661. Bibcode:2010FoPh...40..125H. doi:10.1007/s10701-009-9347-0. S2CID 32755624.
  14. ^ a b Howard, D. (1985). "Einstein on locality and separability". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A. 16 (3): 171–201. Bibcode:1985SHPSA..16..171H. doi:10.1016/0039-3681(85)90001-9.
  15. ^ Sauer, Tilman (2007-12-01). "An Einstein manuscript on the EPR paradox for spin observables". Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics. 38 (4): 879–887. Bibcode:2007SHPMP..38..879S. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.571.6089. doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2007.03.002. ISSN 1355-2198.
  16. ^ Einstein, Albert (1949). "Autobiographical Notes". In Schilpp, Paul Arthur (ed.). Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist. Open Court Publishing Company.
  17. ^ Bohm, D. (1951). Quantum Theory, Prentice-Hall, Englewood Cliffs, page 29, and Chapter 5 section 3, and Chapter 22 Section 19.
  18. ^ D. Bohm; Y. Aharonov (1957). "Discussion of Experimental Proof for the Paradox of Einstein, Rosen, and Podolsky". Physical Review. 108 (4): 1070. Bibcode:1957PhRv..108.1070B. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.108.1070.
  19. ^ Reid, M. D.; Drummond, P. D.; Bowen, W. P.; Cavalcanti, E. G.; Lam, P. K.; Bachor, H. A.; Andersen, U. L.; Leuchs, G. (2009-12-10). "Colloquium: The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen paradox: From concepts to applications". Reviews of Modern Physics. 81 (4): 1727–1751. arXiv:0806.0270. Bibcode:2009RvMP...81.1727R. doi:10.1103/RevModPhys.81.1727. S2CID 53407634.
  20. ^ a b c Griffiths, David J. (2004). Introduction to Quantum Mechanics (2nd ed.). Prentice Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-111892-8.
  21. ^ Laloe, Franck (2012). "Do We Really Understand Quantum Mechanics". American Journal of Physics. 69 (6): 655–701. arXiv:quant-ph/0209123. Bibcode:2001AmJPh..69..655L. doi:10.1119/1.1356698. S2CID 123349369. (Erratum: doi:10.1119/1.1466818)
  22. ^ Bell, J. S. (1964). "On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox" (PDF). Physics Physique Физика. 1 (3): 195–200. doi:10.1103/PhysicsPhysiqueFizika.1.195.
  23. ^ Bohm, D. (1952). "A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of "Hidden" Variables. I". Physical Review. 85 (2): 166. Bibcode:1952PhRv...85..166B. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.85.166.
  24. ^ Bohm, D. (1952). "A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of "Hidden" Variables. II". Physical Review. 85 (2): 180. Bibcode:1952PhRv...85..180B. doi:10.1103/PhysRev.85.180.
  25. ^ a b Sakurai, J. J.; Napolitano, Jim (2010). Modern Quantum Mechanics (2nd ed.). Addison-Wesley. ISBN 978-0805382914.
  26. ^ Aspect A (1999-03-18). "Bell's inequality test: more ideal than ever" (PDF). Nature. 398 (6724): 189–90. Bibcode:1999Natur.398..189A. doi:10.1038/18296. S2CID 44925917.
  27. ^ Werner, R. F. (2014). "Comment on 'What Bell did'". Journal of Physics A. 47 (42): 424011. Bibcode:2014JPhA...47P4011W. doi:10.1088/1751-8113/47/42/424011. S2CID 122180759.
  28. ^ Żukowski, M.; Brukner, Č. (2014). "Quantum non-locality—it ain't necessarily so...". Journal of Physics A. 47 (42): 424009. arXiv:1501.04618. Bibcode:2014JPhA...47P4009Z. doi:10.1088/1751-8113/47/42/424009. S2CID 119220867.
  29. ^ Schrödinger, E. (October 1936). "Probability relations between separated systems". Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 32 (3): 446–452. Bibcode:1936PCPS...32..446S. doi:10.1017/s0305004100019137. ISSN 0305-0041. S2CID 122822435.
  30. ^ Schrödinger, E. (October 1935). "Discussion of Probability Relations between Separated Systems". Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 31 (4): 555–563. Bibcode:1935PCPS...31..555S. doi:10.1017/s0305004100013554. ISSN 0305-0041. S2CID 121278681.
  31. ^ Wiseman, H. M.; Jones, S. J.; Doherty, A. C. (2007). "Steering, Entanglement, Nonlocality, and the Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Paradox". Physical Review Letters. 98 (14): 140402. arXiv:quant-ph/0612147. Bibcode:2007PhRvL..98n0402W. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.98.140402. ISSN 0031-9007. PMID 17501251. S2CID 30078867.
  32. ^ a b Blaylock, Guy (January 2010). "The EPR paradox, Bell's inequality, and the question of locality". American Journal of Physics. 78 (1): 111–120. arXiv:0902.3827. Bibcode:2010AmJPh..78..111B. doi:10.1119/1.3243279. S2CID 118520639.
  33. ^ Albert Einstein Max Born, Briefwechsel 1916-1955 (in German) (3 ed.). München: Langen Müller. 2005. p. 254.
  34. ^ Bell, John (1981). "Bertlmann's socks and the nature of reality". J. Physique Colloques. C22: 41–62. Bibcode:1988nbpw.conf..245B.

Selected papers edit

  • Eberhard, P. H. (1977). "Bell's theorem without hidden variables". Il Nuovo Cimento B. Series 11. 38 (1): 75–80. arXiv:quant-ph/0010047. Bibcode:1977NCimB..38...75E. doi:10.1007/bf02726212. ISSN 1826-9877. S2CID 51759163.
  • Eberhard, P. H. (1978). "Bell's theorem and the different concepts of locality". Il Nuovo Cimento B. Series 11. 46 (2): 392–419. Bibcode:1978NCimB..46..392E. doi:10.1007/bf02728628. ISSN 1826-9877. S2CID 118836806.
  • Einstein, A.; Podolsky, B.; Rosen, N. (1935-05-15). "Can Quantum-Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete?" (PDF). Physical Review. 47 (10): 777–780. Bibcode:1935PhRv...47..777E. doi:10.1103/physrev.47.777. ISSN 0031-899X.
  • Fine, Arthur (1982-02-01). "Hidden Variables, Joint Probability, and the Bell Inequalities". Physical Review Letters. 48 (5): 291–295. Bibcode:1982PhRvL..48..291F. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.48.291. ISSN 0031-9007.
  • A. Fine, Do Correlations need to be explained?, in Philosophical Consequences of Quantum Theory: Reflections on Bell's Theorem, edited by Cushing & McMullin (University of Notre Dame Press, 1986).
  • Hardy, Lucien (1993-09-13). "Nonlocality for two particles without inequalities for almost all entangled states". Physical Review Letters. 71 (11): 1665–1668. Bibcode:1993PhRvL..71.1665H. doi:10.1103/physrevlett.71.1665. ISSN 0031-9007. PMID 10054467.
  • M. Mizuki, A classical interpretation of Bell's inequality. Annales de la Fondation Louis de Broglie 26 683 (2001)
  • Peres, Asher (2005). "Einstein, Podolsky, Rosen, and Shannon". Foundations of Physics. 35 (3): 511–514. arXiv:quant-ph/0310010. Bibcode:2005FoPh...35..511P. doi:10.1007/s10701-004-1986-6. ISSN 0015-9018. S2CID 119556878.
  • P. Pluch, "Theory for Quantum Probability", PhD Thesis University of Klagenfurt (2006)
  • Rowe, M. A.; Kielpinski, D.; Meyer, V.; Sackett, C. A.; Itano, W. M.; Monroe, C.; Wineland, D. J. (2001). "Experimental violation of a Bell's inequality with efficient detection". Nature. 409 (6822): 791–794. Bibcode:2001Natur.409..791R. doi:10.1038/35057215. hdl:2027.42/62731. ISSN 0028-0836. PMID 11236986. S2CID 205014115.
  • Smerlak, Matteo; Rovelli, Carlo (2007-02-03). "Relational EPR". Foundations of Physics. 37 (3): 427–445. arXiv:quant-ph/0604064. Bibcode:2007FoPh...37..427S. doi:10.1007/s10701-007-9105-0. ISSN 0015-9018. S2CID 11816650.

Books edit

  • Bell, John S. (1987). Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-36869-3.
  • Fine, Arthur (1996). The Shaky Game: Einstein, Realism and the Quantum Theory. 2nd ed. Univ. of Chicago Press.
  • Gribbin, John (1984). In Search of Schrödinger's Cat. Black Swan. ISBN 978-0-552-12555-0
  • Leaderman, Leon; Teresi, Dick (1993). The God Particle: If the Universe Is the Answer, What Is the Question? Houghton Mifflin Company, pp. 21, 187–189.
  • Selleri, Franco (1988). Quantum Mechanics Versus Local Realism: The Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen Paradox. New York: Plenum Press. ISBN 0-306-42739-7.

External links edit

  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: The Einstein–Podolsky–Rosen Argument in Quantum Theory; 1.2 The argument in the text
  • Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy: "The Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen Argument and the Bell Inequalities"
  • Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: Abner Shimony (2019) "Bell's Theorem"
  • EPR, Bell & Aspect: The Original References
  • Does Bell's Inequality Principle rule out local theories of quantum mechanics? from the Usenet Physics FAQ
  • Effective use of EPR in cryptography
  • EPR experiment with single photons interactive
  • Spooky Actions At A Distance?: Oppenheimer Lecture by Prof. Mermin
  • Original paper

einstein, podolsky, rosen, paradox, einstein, podolsky, rosen, paradox, thought, experiment, proposed, physicists, albert, einstein, boris, podolsky, nathan, rosen, which, argues, that, description, physical, reality, provided, quantum, mechanics, incomplete, . The Einstein Podolsky Rosen EPR paradox is a thought experiment proposed by physicists Albert Einstein Boris Podolsky and Nathan Rosen which argues that the description of physical reality provided by quantum mechanics is incomplete 1 In a 1935 paper titled Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete they argued for the existence of elements of reality that were not part of quantum theory and speculated that it should be possible to construct a theory containing these hidden variables Resolutions of the paradox have important implications for the interpretation of quantum mechanics Albert Einstein The thought experiment involves a pair of particles prepared in what would later become known as an entangled state Einstein Podolsky and Rosen pointed out that in this state if the position of the first particle were measured the result of measuring the position of the second particle could be predicted If instead the momentum of the first particle were measured then the result of measuring the momentum of the second particle could be predicted They argued that no action taken on the first particle could instantaneously affect the other since this would involve information being transmitted faster than light which is impossible according to the theory of relativity They invoked a principle later known as the EPR criterion of reality positing that If without in any way disturbing a system we can predict with certainty i e with probability equal to unity the value of a physical quantity then there exists an element of reality corresponding to that quantity From this they inferred that the second particle must have a definite value of both position and of momentum prior to either quantity being measured But quantum mechanics considers these two observables incompatible and thus does not associate simultaneous values for both to any system Einstein Podolsky and Rosen therefore concluded that quantum theory does not provide a complete description of reality 2 Contents 1 The Paradox paper 1 1 Bohr s reply 1 2 Einstein s own argument 2 Later developments 2 1 Bohm s variant 2 2 Bell s theorem 3 Steering 4 Locality 5 Mathematical formulation 6 See also 7 Notes 8 References 8 1 Selected papers 8 2 Books 9 External linksThe Paradox paper editThe term Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox or EPR arose from a paper written in 1934 after Einstein joined the Institute for Advanced Study having fled the rise of Nazi Germany 3 4 The original paper 5 purports to describe what must happen to two systems I and II which we permit to interact and after some time we suppose that there is no longer any interaction between the two parts The EPR description involves two particles A and B which interact briefly and then move off in opposite directions 6 According to Heisenberg s uncertainty principle it is impossible to measure both the momentum and the position of particle B exactly however it is possible to measure the exact position of particle A By calculation therefore with the exact position of particle A known the exact position of particle B can be known Alternatively the exact momentum of particle A can be measured so the exact momentum of particle B can be worked out As Manjit Kumar writes EPR argued that they had proved that particle B can have simultaneously exact values of position and momentum Particle B has a position that is real and a momentum that is real EPR appeared to have contrived a means to establish the exact values of either the momentum or the position of B due to measurements made on particle A without the slightest possibility of particle B being physically disturbed 6 EPR tried to set up a paradox to question the range of true application of quantum mechanics Quantum theory predicts that both values cannot be known for a particle and yet the EPR thought experiment purports to show that they must all have determinate values The EPR paper says We are thus forced to conclude that the quantum mechanical description of physical reality given by wave functions is not complete 6 The EPR paper ends by saying While we have thus shown that the wave function does not provide a complete description of the physical reality we left open the question of whether or not such a description exists We believe however that such a theory is possible The 1935 EPR paper condensed the philosophical discussion into a physical argument The authors claim that given a specific experiment in which the outcome of a measurement is known before the measurement takes place there must exist something in the real world an element of reality that determines the measurement outcome They postulate that these elements of reality are in modern terminology local in the sense that each belongs to a certain point in spacetime Each element may again in modern terminology only be influenced by events which are located in the backward light cone of its point in spacetime i e in the past These claims are founded on assumptions about nature that constitute what is now known as local realism 7 nbsp Article headline regarding the EPR paradox paper in the May 4 1935 issue of The New York Times Though the EPR paper has often been taken as an exact expression of Einstein s views it was primarily authored by Podolsky based on discussions at the Institute for Advanced Study with Einstein and Rosen Einstein later expressed to Erwin Schrodinger that it did not come out as well as I had originally wanted rather the essential thing was so to speak smothered by the formalism 8 Einstein would later go on to present an individual account of his local realist ideas 9 Shortly before the EPR paper appeared in the Physical Review The New York Times ran a news story about it under the headline Einstein Attacks Quantum Theory 10 The story which quoted Podolsky irritated Einstein who wrote to the Times Any information upon which the article Einstein Attacks Quantum Theory in your issue of May 4 is based was given to you without authority It is my invariable practice to discuss scientific matters only in the appropriate forum and I deprecate advance publication of any announcement in regard to such matters in the secular press 11 189 The Times story also sought out comment from physicist Edward Condon who said Of course a great deal of the argument hinges on just what meaning is to be attached to the word reality in physics 11 189 The physicist and historian Max Jammer later noted I t remains a historical fact that the earliest criticism of the EPR paper moreover a criticism which correctly saw in Einstein s conception of physical reality the key problem of the whole issue appeared in a daily newspaper prior to the publication of the criticized paper itself 11 190 Bohr s reply edit The publication of the paper prompted a response by Niels Bohr which he published in the same journal Physical Review in the same year using the same title 12 This exchange was only one chapter in a prolonged debate between Bohr and Einstein about the nature of quantum reality He argued that EPR had reasoned fallaciously Bohr said measurements of position and of momentum are complementary meaning the choice to measure one excludes the possibility of measuring the other Consequently a fact deduced regarding one arrangement of laboratory apparatus could not be combined with a fact deduced by means of the other and so the inference of predetermined position and momentum values for the second particle was not valid Bohr concluded that EPR s arguments do not justify their conclusion that the quantum description turns out to be essentially incomplete Einstein s own argument edit In his own publications and correspondence Einstein indicated that he was not satisfied with the EPR paper and that Rosen had authored most of it He later used a different argument to insist that quantum mechanics is an incomplete theory 13 14 15 16 83ff He explicitly de emphasized EPR s attribution of elements of reality to the position and momentum of particle B saying that I couldn t care less whether the resulting states of particle B allowed one to predict the position and momentum with certainty a For Einstein the crucial part of the argument was the demonstration of nonlocality that the choice of measurement done in particle A either position or momentum would lead to two different quantum states of particle B He argued that because of locality the real state of particle B could not depend on which kind of measurement was done in A and that the quantum states therefore cannot be in one to one correspondence with the real states 13 Einstein struggled unsuccessfully for the rest of his life to find a theory that could better comply with his idea of locality Later developments editBohm s variant edit In 1951 David Bohm proposed a variant of the EPR thought experiment in which the measurements have discrete ranges of possible outcomes unlike the position and momentum measurements considered by EPR 17 18 19 The EPR Bohm thought experiment can be explained using electron positron pairs Suppose we have a source that emits electron positron pairs with the electron sent to destination A where there is an observer named Alice and the positron sent to destination B where there is an observer named Bob According to quantum mechanics we can arrange our source so that each emitted pair occupies a quantum state called a spin singlet The particles are thus said to be entangled This can be viewed as a quantum superposition of two states which we call state I and state II In state I the electron has spin pointing upward along the z axis z and the positron has spin pointing downward along the z axis z In state II the electron has spin z and the positron has spin z Because it is in a superposition of states it is impossible without measuring to know the definite state of spin of either particle in the spin singlet 20 421 422 nbsp The EPR thought experiment performed with electron positron pairs A source center sends particles toward two observers electrons to Alice left and positrons to Bob right who can perform spin measurements Alice now measures the spin along the z axis She can obtain one of two possible outcomes z or z Suppose she gets z Informally speaking the quantum state of the system collapses into state I The quantum state determines the probable outcomes of any measurement performed on the system In this case if Bob subsequently measures spin along the z axis there is 100 probability that he will obtain z Similarly if Alice gets z Bob will get z There is nothing special about choosing the z axis according to quantum mechanics the spin singlet state may equally well be expressed as a superposition of spin states pointing in the x direction 21 318 Whatever axis their spins are measured along they are always found to be opposite In quantum mechanics the x spin and z spin are incompatible observables meaning the Heisenberg uncertainty principle applies to alternating measurements of them a quantum state cannot possess a definite value for both of these variables Suppose Alice measures the z spin and obtains z so that the quantum state collapses into state I Now instead of measuring the z spin as well Bob measures the x spin According to quantum mechanics when the system is in state I Bob s x spin measurement will have a 50 probability of producing x and a 50 probability of x It is impossible to predict which outcome will appear until Bob actually performs the measurement Therefore Bob s positron will have a definite spin when measured along the same axis as Alice s electron but when measured in the perpendicular axis its spin will be uniformly random It seems as if information has propagated faster than light from Alice s apparatus to make Bob s positron assume a definite spin in the appropriate axis Bell s theorem edit Main article Bell s theorem In 1964 John Stewart Bell published a paper 22 investigating the puzzling situation at that time on one hand the EPR paradox purportedly showed that quantum mechanics was nonlocal and suggested that a hidden variable theory could heal this nonlocality On the other hand David Bohm had recently developed the first successful hidden variable theory but it had a grossly nonlocal character 23 24 Bell set out to investigate whether it was indeed possible to solve the nonlocality problem with hidden variables and found out that first the correlations shown in both EPR s and Bohm s versions of the paradox could indeed be explained in a local way with hidden variables and second that the correlations shown in his own variant of the paradox couldn t be explained by any local hidden variable theory This second result became known as the Bell theorem To understand the first result consider the following toy hidden variable theory introduced later by J J Sakurai 25 239 240 in it quantum spin singlet states emitted by the source are actually approximate descriptions for true physical states possessing definite values for the z spin and x spin In these true states the positron going to Bob always has spin values opposite to the electron going to Alice but the values are otherwise completely random For example the first pair emitted by the source might be z x to Alice and z x to Bob the next pair z x to Alice and z x to Bob and so forth Therefore if Bob s measurement axis is aligned with Alice s he will necessarily get the opposite of whatever Alice gets otherwise he will get and with equal probability Bell showed however that such models can only reproduce the singlet correlations when Alice and Bob make measurements on the same axis or on perpendicular axes As soon as other angles between their axes are allowed local hidden variable theories become unable to reproduce the quantum mechanical correlations This difference expressed using inequalities known as Bell s inequalities is in principle experimentally testable After the publication of Bell s paper a variety of experiments to test Bell s inequalities were carried out notably by the group of Alain Aspect in the 1980s 26 all experiments conducted to date have found behavior in line with the predictions of quantum mechanics The present view of the situation is that quantum mechanics flatly contradicts Einstein s philosophical postulate that any acceptable physical theory must fulfill local realism The fact that quantum mechanics violates Bell inequalities indicates that any hidden variable theory underlying quantum mechanics must be non local whether this should be taken to imply that quantum mechanics itself is non local is a matter of continuing debate 27 28 Steering editMain article Quantum steering Inspired by Schrodinger s treatment of the EPR paradox back in 1935 29 30 Howard M Wiseman et al formalised it in 2007 as the phenomenon of quantum steering 31 They defined steering as the situation where Alice s measurements on a part of an entangled state steer Bob s part of the state That is Bob s observations cannot be explained by a local hidden state model where Bob would have a fixed quantum state in his side that is classically correlated but otherwise independent of Alice s Locality editLocality has several different meanings in physics EPR describe the principle of locality as asserting that physical processes occurring at one place should have no immediate effect on the elements of reality at another location At first sight this appears to be a reasonable assumption to make as it seems to be a consequence of special relativity which states that energy can never be transmitted faster than the speed of light without violating causality 20 427 428 32 however it turns out that the usual rules for combining quantum mechanical and classical descriptions violate EPR s principle of locality without violating special relativity or causality 20 427 428 32 Causality is preserved because there is no way for Alice to transmit messages i e information to Bob by manipulating her measurement axis Whichever axis she uses she has a 50 probability of obtaining and 50 probability of obtaining completely at random according to quantum mechanics it is fundamentally impossible for her to influence what result she gets Furthermore Bob is able to perform his measurement only once there is a fundamental property of quantum mechanics the no cloning theorem which makes it impossible for him to make an arbitrary number of copies of the electron he receives perform a spin measurement on each and look at the statistical distribution of the results Therefore in the one measurement he is allowed to make there is a 50 probability of getting and 50 of getting regardless of whether or not his axis is aligned with Alice s As a summary the results of the EPR thought experiment do not contradict the predictions of special relativity Neither the EPR paradox nor any quantum experiment demonstrates that superluminal signaling is possible however the principle of locality appeals powerfully to physical intuition and Einstein Podolsky and Rosen were unwilling to abandon it Einstein derided the quantum mechanical predictions as spooky action at a distance b The conclusion they drew was that quantum mechanics is not a complete theory 34 Mathematical formulation editBohm s variant of the EPR paradox can be expressed mathematically using the quantum mechanical formulation of spin The spin degree of freedom for an electron is associated with a two dimensional complex vector space V with each quantum state corresponding to a vector in that space The operators corresponding to the spin along the x y and z direction denoted Sx Sy and Sz respectively can be represented using the Pauli matrices 25 9 S x ℏ 2 0 1 1 0 S y ℏ 2 0 i i 0 S z ℏ 2 1 0 0 1 displaystyle S x frac hbar 2 begin bmatrix 0 amp 1 1 amp 0 end bmatrix quad S y frac hbar 2 begin bmatrix 0 amp i i amp 0 end bmatrix quad S z frac hbar 2 begin bmatrix 1 amp 0 0 amp 1 end bmatrix nbsp where ℏ displaystyle hbar nbsp is the reduced Planck constant or the Planck constant divided by 2p The eigenstates of Sz are represented as z 1 0 z 0 1 displaystyle left z right rangle leftrightarrow begin bmatrix 1 0 end bmatrix quad left z right rangle leftrightarrow begin bmatrix 0 1 end bmatrix nbsp and the eigenstates of Sx are represented as x 1 2 1 1 x 1 2 1 1 displaystyle left x right rangle leftrightarrow frac 1 sqrt 2 begin bmatrix 1 1 end bmatrix quad left x right rangle leftrightarrow frac 1 sqrt 2 begin bmatrix 1 1 end bmatrix nbsp The vector space of the electron positron pair is V V displaystyle V otimes V nbsp the tensor product of the electron s and positron s vector spaces The spin singlet state is ps 1 2 z z z z displaystyle left psi right rangle frac 1 sqrt 2 biggl left z right rangle otimes left z right rangle left z right rangle otimes left z right rangle biggr nbsp where the two terms on the right hand side are what we have referred to as state I and state II above From the above equations it can be shown that the spin singlet can also be written as ps 1 2 x x x x displaystyle left psi right rangle frac 1 sqrt 2 biggl left x right rangle otimes left x right rangle left x right rangle otimes left x right rangle biggr nbsp where the terms on the right hand side are what we have referred to as state Ia and state IIa To illustrate the paradox we need to show that after Alice s measurement of Sz or Sx Bob s value of Sz or Sx is uniquely determined and Bob s value of Sx or Sz is uniformly random This follows from the principles of measurement in quantum mechanics When Sz is measured the system state ps displaystyle psi rangle nbsp collapses into an eigenvector of Sz If the measurement result is z this means that immediately after measurement the system state collapses to z z z x x 2 displaystyle left z right rangle otimes left z right rangle left z right rangle otimes frac left x right rangle left x right rangle sqrt 2 nbsp Similarly if Alice s measurement result is z the state collapses to z z z x x 2 displaystyle left z right rangle otimes left z right rangle left z right rangle otimes frac left x right rangle left x right rangle sqrt 2 nbsp The left hand side of both equations show that the measurement of Sz on Bob s positron is now determined it will be z in the first case or z in the second case The right hand side of the equations show that the measurement of Sx on Bob s positron will return in both cases x or x with probability 1 2 each See also editAspect s experiment Bohr Einstein debates The argument of EPR CHSH inequality Coherence Correlation does not imply causation ER EPR GHZ experiment Measurement problem Philosophy of information Philosophy of physics Popper s experiment Superdeterminism Quantum entanglement Quantum information Quantum pseudo telepathy Quantum teleportation Quantum Zeno effect Synchronicity Ward s probability amplitudeNotes edit Ob die ps B displaystyle psi B nbsp und ps B displaystyle psi underline B nbsp als Eigenfunktionen von Observabeln B B displaystyle B underline B nbsp aufgefasst werden konnen ist mir wurst Emphasis from the original Ist mir wurst is a German expression that literally translates to It is a sausage to me but means I couldn t care less Letter from Einstein to Schrodinger dated 19th June 1935 14 Spukhaften Fernwirkung in the German original Used in a letter to Max Born dated March 3 1947 33 References edit Einstein A B Podolsky N Rosen 1935 05 15 Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete PDF Physical Review 47 10 777 780 Bibcode 1935PhRv 47 777E doi 10 1103 PhysRev 47 777 Peres Asher 2002 Quantum Theory Concepts and Methods Kluwer p 149 Robinson Andrew 2018 04 30 Did Einstein really say that Nature 557 7703 30 Bibcode 2018Natur 557 30R doi 10 1038 d41586 018 05004 4 S2CID 14013938 Levenson Thomas 9 June 1917 The Scientist and the Fascist The Atlantic Retrieved 28 June 2021 Einstein Albert Podolsky Boris Rosen Nathan May 15 1935 Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete Physical Review 47 10 Princeton New Jersey Institute for Advanced Study 777 780 Bibcode 1935PhRv 47 777E doi 10 1103 PhysRev 47 777 a b c Kumar Manjit 2011 Quantum Einstein Bohr and the Great Debate about the Nature of Reality Reprint ed W W Norton amp Company pp 305 306 ISBN 978 0393339888 Retrieved September 12 2021 via Internet Archive Jaeger Gregg 2014 Quantum Objects Springer Verlag pp 9 15 doi 10 1007 978 3 642 37629 0 ISBN 978 3 642 37628 3 Kaiser David 1994 Bringing the human actors back on stage the personal context of the Einstein Bohr debate British Journal for the History of Science 27 2 129 152 doi 10 1017 S0007087400031861 JSTOR 4027432 S2CID 145143635 Einstein Albert 1936 Physik und Realitat Journal of the Franklin Institute 221 3 313 347 doi 10 1016 S0016 0032 36 91045 1 English translation by Jean Piccard pp 349 382 in the same issue doi 10 1016 S0016 0032 36 91047 5 Einstein Attacks Quantum Theory The New York Times 4 May 1935 p 11 Retrieved 10 January 2021 a b c Jammer Max 1974 The Philosophy of Quantum Mechanics The Interpretations of QM in Historical Perspective John Wiley and Sons ISBN 0 471 43958 4 Bohr N 1935 10 13 Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality be Considered Complete PDF Physical Review 48 8 696 702 Bibcode 1935PhRv 48 696B doi 10 1103 PhysRev 48 696 a b Harrigan Nicholas Spekkens Robert W 2010 Einstein incompleteness and the epistemic view of quantum states Foundations of Physics 40 2 125 arXiv 0706 2661 Bibcode 2010FoPh 40 125H doi 10 1007 s10701 009 9347 0 S2CID 32755624 a b Howard D 1985 Einstein on locality and separability Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A 16 3 171 201 Bibcode 1985SHPSA 16 171H doi 10 1016 0039 3681 85 90001 9 Sauer Tilman 2007 12 01 An Einstein manuscript on the EPR paradox for spin observables Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 38 4 879 887 Bibcode 2007SHPMP 38 879S CiteSeerX 10 1 1 571 6089 doi 10 1016 j shpsb 2007 03 002 ISSN 1355 2198 Einstein Albert 1949 Autobiographical Notes In Schilpp Paul Arthur ed Albert Einstein Philosopher Scientist Open Court Publishing Company Bohm D 1951 Quantum Theory Prentice Hall Englewood Cliffs page 29 and Chapter 5 section 3 and Chapter 22 Section 19 D Bohm Y Aharonov 1957 Discussion of Experimental Proof for the Paradox of Einstein Rosen and Podolsky Physical Review 108 4 1070 Bibcode 1957PhRv 108 1070B doi 10 1103 PhysRev 108 1070 Reid M D Drummond P D Bowen W P Cavalcanti E G Lam P K Bachor H A Andersen U L Leuchs G 2009 12 10 Colloquium The Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox From concepts to applications Reviews of Modern Physics 81 4 1727 1751 arXiv 0806 0270 Bibcode 2009RvMP 81 1727R doi 10 1103 RevModPhys 81 1727 S2CID 53407634 a b c Griffiths David J 2004 Introduction to Quantum Mechanics 2nd ed Prentice Hall ISBN 978 0 13 111892 8 Laloe Franck 2012 Do We Really Understand Quantum Mechanics American Journal of Physics 69 6 655 701 arXiv quant ph 0209123 Bibcode 2001AmJPh 69 655L doi 10 1119 1 1356698 S2CID 123349369 Erratum doi 10 1119 1 1466818 Bell J S 1964 On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox PDF Physics Physique Fizika 1 3 195 200 doi 10 1103 PhysicsPhysiqueFizika 1 195 Bohm D 1952 A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of Hidden Variables I Physical Review 85 2 166 Bibcode 1952PhRv 85 166B doi 10 1103 PhysRev 85 166 Bohm D 1952 A Suggested Interpretation of the Quantum Theory in Terms of Hidden Variables II Physical Review 85 2 180 Bibcode 1952PhRv 85 180B doi 10 1103 PhysRev 85 180 a b Sakurai J J Napolitano Jim 2010 Modern Quantum Mechanics 2nd ed Addison Wesley ISBN 978 0805382914 Aspect A 1999 03 18 Bell s inequality test more ideal than ever PDF Nature 398 6724 189 90 Bibcode 1999Natur 398 189A doi 10 1038 18296 S2CID 44925917 Werner R F 2014 Comment on What Bell did Journal of Physics A 47 42 424011 Bibcode 2014JPhA 47P4011W doi 10 1088 1751 8113 47 42 424011 S2CID 122180759 Zukowski M Brukner C 2014 Quantum non locality it ain t necessarily so Journal of Physics A 47 42 424009 arXiv 1501 04618 Bibcode 2014JPhA 47P4009Z doi 10 1088 1751 8113 47 42 424009 S2CID 119220867 Schrodinger E October 1936 Probability relations between separated systems Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 32 3 446 452 Bibcode 1936PCPS 32 446S doi 10 1017 s0305004100019137 ISSN 0305 0041 S2CID 122822435 Schrodinger E October 1935 Discussion of Probability Relations between Separated Systems Mathematical Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 31 4 555 563 Bibcode 1935PCPS 31 555S doi 10 1017 s0305004100013554 ISSN 0305 0041 S2CID 121278681 Wiseman H M Jones S J Doherty A C 2007 Steering Entanglement Nonlocality and the Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox Physical Review Letters 98 14 140402 arXiv quant ph 0612147 Bibcode 2007PhRvL 98n0402W doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 98 140402 ISSN 0031 9007 PMID 17501251 S2CID 30078867 a b Blaylock Guy January 2010 The EPR paradox Bell s inequality and the question of locality American Journal of Physics 78 1 111 120 arXiv 0902 3827 Bibcode 2010AmJPh 78 111B doi 10 1119 1 3243279 S2CID 118520639 Albert Einstein Max Born Briefwechsel 1916 1955 in German 3 ed Munchen Langen Muller 2005 p 254 Bell John 1981 Bertlmann s socks and the nature of reality J Physique Colloques C22 41 62 Bibcode 1988nbpw conf 245B Selected papers edit Eberhard P H 1977 Bell s theorem without hidden variables Il Nuovo Cimento B Series 11 38 1 75 80 arXiv quant ph 0010047 Bibcode 1977NCimB 38 75E doi 10 1007 bf02726212 ISSN 1826 9877 S2CID 51759163 Eberhard P H 1978 Bell s theorem and the different concepts of locality Il Nuovo Cimento B Series 11 46 2 392 419 Bibcode 1978NCimB 46 392E doi 10 1007 bf02728628 ISSN 1826 9877 S2CID 118836806 Einstein A Podolsky B Rosen N 1935 05 15 Can Quantum Mechanical Description of Physical Reality Be Considered Complete PDF Physical Review 47 10 777 780 Bibcode 1935PhRv 47 777E doi 10 1103 physrev 47 777 ISSN 0031 899X Fine Arthur 1982 02 01 Hidden Variables Joint Probability and the Bell Inequalities Physical Review Letters 48 5 291 295 Bibcode 1982PhRvL 48 291F doi 10 1103 physrevlett 48 291 ISSN 0031 9007 A Fine Do Correlations need to be explained in Philosophical Consequences of Quantum Theory Reflections on Bell s Theorem edited by Cushing amp McMullin University of Notre Dame Press 1986 Hardy Lucien 1993 09 13 Nonlocality for two particles without inequalities for almost all entangled states Physical Review Letters 71 11 1665 1668 Bibcode 1993PhRvL 71 1665H doi 10 1103 physrevlett 71 1665 ISSN 0031 9007 PMID 10054467 M Mizuki A classical interpretation of Bell s inequality Annales de la Fondation Louis de Broglie 26 683 2001 Peres Asher 2005 Einstein Podolsky Rosen and Shannon Foundations of Physics 35 3 511 514 arXiv quant ph 0310010 Bibcode 2005FoPh 35 511P doi 10 1007 s10701 004 1986 6 ISSN 0015 9018 S2CID 119556878 P Pluch Theory for Quantum Probability PhD Thesis University of Klagenfurt 2006 Rowe M A Kielpinski D Meyer V Sackett C A Itano W M Monroe C Wineland D J 2001 Experimental violation of a Bell s inequality with efficient detection Nature 409 6822 791 794 Bibcode 2001Natur 409 791R doi 10 1038 35057215 hdl 2027 42 62731 ISSN 0028 0836 PMID 11236986 S2CID 205014115 Smerlak Matteo Rovelli Carlo 2007 02 03 Relational EPR Foundations of Physics 37 3 427 445 arXiv quant ph 0604064 Bibcode 2007FoPh 37 427S doi 10 1007 s10701 007 9105 0 ISSN 0015 9018 S2CID 11816650 Books edit Bell John S 1987 Speakable and Unspeakable in Quantum Mechanics Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 36869 3 Fine Arthur 1996 The Shaky Game Einstein Realism and the Quantum Theory 2nd ed Univ of Chicago Press Gribbin John 1984 In Search of Schrodinger s Cat Black Swan ISBN 978 0 552 12555 0 Leaderman Leon Teresi Dick 1993 The God Particle If the Universe Is the Answer What Is the Question Houghton Mifflin Company pp 21 187 189 Selleri Franco 1988 Quantum Mechanics Versus Local Realism The Einstein Podolsky Rosen Paradox New York Plenum Press ISBN 0 306 42739 7 External links edit nbsp Wikiquote has quotations related to Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy The Einstein Podolsky Rosen Argument in Quantum Theory 1 2 The argument in the text Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy The Einstein Podolsky Rosen Argument and the Bell Inequalities Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Abner Shimony 2019 Bell s Theorem EPR Bell amp Aspect The Original References Does Bell s Inequality Principle rule out local theories of quantum mechanics from the Usenet Physics FAQ Theoretical use of EPR in teleportation Effective use of EPR in cryptography EPR experiment with single photons interactive Spooky Actions At A Distance Oppenheimer Lecture by Prof Mermin Original paper Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox amp oldid 1224219393, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.