fbpx
Wikipedia

Modus ponens

In propositional logic, modus ponens (/ˈmdəs ˈpnɛnz/; MP), also known as modus ponendo ponens (Latin for "method of putting by placing")[1] or implication elimination or affirming the antecedent,[2] is a deductive argument form and rule of inference.[3] It can be summarized as "P implies Q. P is true. Therefore Q must also be true."

Modus ponens
Type
Field
Statement implies . is true. Therefore must also be true.
Symbolic statement

Modus ponens is closely related to another valid form of argument, modus tollens. Both have apparently similar but invalid forms such as affirming the consequent, denying the antecedent, and evidence of absence. Constructive dilemma is the disjunctive version of modus ponens. Hypothetical syllogism is closely related to modus ponens and sometimes thought of as "double modus ponens."

The history of modus ponens goes back to antiquity.[4] The first to explicitly describe the argument form modus ponens was Theophrastus.[5] It, along with modus tollens, is one of the standard patterns of inference that can be applied to derive chains of conclusions that lead to the desired goal.

Explanation

The form of a modus ponens argument resembles a syllogism, with two premises and a conclusion:

  1. If P, then Q.
  2. P.
  3. Therefore, Q.

The first premise is a conditional ("if–then") claim, namely that P implies Q. The second premise is an assertion that P, the antecedent of the conditional claim, is the case. From these two premises it can be logically concluded that Q, the consequent of the conditional claim, must be the case as well.

An example of an argument that fits the form modus ponens:

  1. If today is Tuesday, then John will go to work.
  2. Today is Tuesday.
  3. Therefore, John will go to work.

This argument is valid, but this has no bearing on whether any of the statements in the argument are actually true; for modus ponens to be a sound argument, the premises must be true for any true instances of the conclusion. An argument can be valid but nonetheless unsound if one or more premises are false; if an argument is valid and all the premises are true, then the argument is sound. For example, John might be going to work on Wednesday. In this case, the reasoning for John's going to work (because it is Wednesday) is unsound. The argument is only sound on Tuesdays (when John goes to work), but valid on every day of the week. A propositional argument using modus ponens is said to be deductive.

In single-conclusion sequent calculi, modus ponens is the Cut rule. The cut-elimination theorem for a calculus says that every proof involving Cut can be transformed (generally, by a constructive method) into a proof without Cut, and hence that Cut is admissible.

The Curry–Howard correspondence between proofs and programs relates modus ponens to function application: if f is a function of type PQ and x is of type P, then f x is of type Q.

In artificial intelligence, modus ponens is often called forward chaining.

Formal notation

The modus ponens rule may be written in sequent notation as

 

where P, Q and PQ are statements (or propositions) in a formal language and is a metalogical symbol meaning that Q is a syntactic consequence of P and PQ in some logical system.

Justification via truth table

The validity of modus ponens in classical two-valued logic can be clearly demonstrated by use of a truth table.

p q pq
T T T
T F F
F T T
F F T

In instances of modus ponens we assume as premises that pq is true and p is true. Only one line of the truth table—the first—satisfies these two conditions (p and pq). On this line, q is also true. Therefore, whenever pq is true and p is true, q must also be true.

Status

While modus ponens is one of the most commonly used argument forms in logic it must not be mistaken for a logical law; rather, it is one of the accepted mechanisms for the construction of deductive proofs that includes the "rule of definition" and the "rule of substitution".[6] Modus ponens allows one to eliminate a conditional statement from a logical proof or argument (the antecedents) and thereby not carry these antecedents forward in an ever-lengthening string of symbols; for this reason modus ponens is sometimes called the rule of detachment[7] or the law of detachment.[8] Enderton, for example, observes that "modus ponens can produce shorter formulas from longer ones",[9] and Russell observes that "the process of the inference cannot be reduced to symbols. Its sole record is the occurrence of ⊦q [the consequent] ... an inference is the dropping of a true premise; it is the dissolution of an implication".[10]

A justification for the "trust in inference is the belief that if the two former assertions [the antecedents] are not in error, the final assertion [the consequent] is not in error".[10] In other words: if one statement or proposition implies a second one, and the first statement or proposition is true, then the second one is also true. If P implies Q and P is true, then Q is true.[11]

Correspondence to other mathematical frameworks

Algebraic semantics

In mathematical logic, algebraic semantics treats every sentence as a name for an element in an ordered set. Typically, the set can be visualized as a lattice-like structure with a single element (the “always-true”) at the top and another single element (the “always-false”) at the bottom. Logical equivalence becomes identity, so that when   and  , for instance, are equivalent (as is standard), then  . Logical implication becomes a matter of relative position:   logically implies   just in case  , i.e., when either   or else   lies below   and is connected to it by an upward path.

In this context, to say that   and   together imply  —that is, to affirm modus ponens as valid—is to say that  . In the semantics for basic propositional logic, the algebra is Boolean, with   construed as the material conditional:  . Confirming that   is then straightforward, because  . With other treatments of  , the semantics becomes more complex, the algebra may be non-Boolean, and the validity of modus ponens cannot be taken for granted.

Probability calculus

Modus ponens represents an instance of the Law of total probability which for a binary variable is expressed as:

 ,

where e.g.   denotes the probability of   and the conditional probability   generalizes the logical implication  . Assume that   is equivalent to   being TRUE, and that   is equivalent to   being FALSE. It is then easy to see that   when   and  . Hence, the law of total probability represents a generalization of modus ponens.[12]

Subjective logic

Modus ponens represents an instance of the binomial deduction operator in subjective logic expressed as:

 ,

where   denotes the subjective opinion about   as expressed by source  , and the conditional opinion   generalizes the logical implication  . The deduced marginal opinion about   is denoted by  . The case where   is an absolute TRUE opinion about   is equivalent to source   saying that   is TRUE, and the case where   is an absolute FALSE opinion about   is equivalent to source   saying that   is FALSE. The deduction operator   of subjective logic produces an absolute TRUE deduced opinion   when the conditional opinion   is absolute TRUE and the antecedent opinion   is absolute TRUE. Hence, subjective logic deduction represents a generalization of both modus ponens and the Law of total probability.[13]

Alleged cases of failure

Philosophers and linguists have identified a variety of cases where modus ponens appears to fail. Vann McGee, for instance, argued that modus ponens can fail for conditionals whose consequents are themselves conditionals.[14] The following is an example:

  1. Either Shakespeare or Hobbes wrote Hamlet.
  2. If either Shakespeare or Hobbes wrote Hamlet, then if Shakespeare didn't do it, Hobbes did.
  3. Therefore, if Shakespeare didn't write Hamlet, Hobbes did it.

Since Shakespeare did write Hamlet, the first premise is true. The second premise is also true, since starting with a set of possible authors limited to just Shakespeare and Hobbes and eliminating one of them leaves only the other. However, the conclusion may seem false, since ruling out Shakespeare as the author of Hamlet would leave numerous possible candidates, many of them more plausible alternatives than Hobbes.

The general form of McGee-type counterexamples to modus ponens is simply  , therefore  ; it is not essential that   be a disjunction, as in the example given. That these kinds of cases constitute failures of modus ponens remains a controversial view among logicians, but opinions vary on how the cases should be disposed of.[15][16][17]

In deontic logic, some examples of conditional obligation also raise the possibility of modus ponens failure. These are cases where the conditional premise describes an obligation predicated on an immoral or imprudent action, e.g., “If Doe murders his mother, he ought to do so gently,” for which the dubious unconditional conclusion would be "Doe ought to gently murder his mother."[18] It would appear to follow that if Doe is in fact gently murdering his mother, then by modus ponens he is doing exactly what he should, unconditionally, be doing. Here again, modus ponens failure is not a popular diagnosis but is sometimes argued for.[19]

Possible fallacies

The fallacy of affirming the consequent is a common misinterpretation of the modus ponens.[20]

See also

References

  1. ^ Stone, Jon R. (1996). Latin for the Illiterati: Exorcizing the Ghosts of a Dead Language. London: Routledge. p. 60. ISBN 0-415-91775-1.
  2. ^ "Oxford reference: affirming the antecedent". Oxford Reference.
  3. ^ Enderton 2001:110
  4. ^ Susanne Bobzien (2002). "The Development of Modus Ponens in Antiquity", Phronesis 47, No. 4, 2002.
  5. ^ "Ancient Logic: Forerunners of Modus Ponens and Modus Tollens". Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  6. ^ Alfred Tarski 1946:47. Also Enderton 2001:110ff.
  7. ^ Tarski 1946:47
  8. ^ "Modus ponens - Encyclopedia of Mathematics". encyclopediaofmath.org. Retrieved 5 April 2018.
  9. ^ Enderton 2001:111
  10. ^ a b Whitehead and Russell 1927:9
  11. ^ Jago, Mark (2007). Formal Logic. Humanities-Ebooks LLP. ISBN 978-1-84760-041-7. {{cite book}}: External link in |publisher= (help)
  12. ^ Audun Jøsang 2016:2
  13. ^ Audun Jøsang 2016:92
  14. ^ Vann McGee (1985). "A Counterexample to Modus Ponens", The Journal of Philosophy 82, 462–471.
  15. ^ Sinnott-Armstrong, Moor, and Fogelin (1986). "A Defense of Modus Ponens", The Journal of Philosophy 83, 296–300.
  16. ^ D. E. Over (1987). "Assumption and the Supposed Counterexamples to Modus Ponens", Analysis 47, 142–146.
  17. ^ Bledin (2015). "Modus Ponens Defended", The Journal of Philosophy 112, 462–471.
  18. ^ "Deontic Logic". 21 April 2010. Retrieved 30 January 2020. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  19. ^ E.g., by Kolodny and MacFarlane (2010). "Ifs and Oughts", The Journal of Philosophy 107, 115–143.
  20. ^ "Fallacies | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". iep.utm.edu. Retrieved 6 March 2020.

Sources

  • Herbert B. Enderton, 2001, A Mathematical Introduction to Logic Second Edition, Harcourt Academic Press, Burlington MA, ISBN 978-0-12-238452-3.
  • Audun Jøsang, 2016, Subjective Logic; A formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty Springer, Cham, ISBN 978-3-319-42337-1
  • Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell 1927 Principia Mathematica to *56 (Second Edition) paperback edition 1962, Cambridge at the University Press, London UK. No ISBN, no LCCCN.
  • Alfred Tarski 1946 Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences 2nd Edition, reprinted by Dover Publications, Mineola NY. ISBN 0-486-28462-X (pbk).

External links

modus, ponens, forward, reasoning, redirects, here, other, uses, forward, chaining, propositional, logic, modus, ponens, also, known, modus, ponendo, ponens, latin, method, putting, placing, implication, elimination, affirming, antecedent, deductive, argument,. Forward reasoning redirects here For other uses see Forward chaining In propositional logic modus ponens ˈ m oʊ d e s ˈ p oʊ n ɛ n z MP also known as modus ponendo ponens Latin for method of putting by placing 1 or implication elimination or affirming the antecedent 2 is a deductive argument form and rule of inference 3 It can be summarized as P implies Q P is true Therefore Q must also be true Modus ponensTypeDeductive argument form Rule of inferenceFieldClassical logic Propositional calculusStatementP displaystyle P implies Q displaystyle Q P displaystyle P is true Therefore Q displaystyle Q must also be true Symbolic statementP Q P Q displaystyle P to Q P vdash Q Modus ponens is closely related to another valid form of argument modus tollens Both have apparently similar but invalid forms such as affirming the consequent denying the antecedent and evidence of absence Constructive dilemma is the disjunctive version of modus ponens Hypothetical syllogism is closely related to modus ponens and sometimes thought of as double modus ponens The history of modus ponens goes back to antiquity 4 The first to explicitly describe the argument form modus ponens was Theophrastus 5 It along with modus tollens is one of the standard patterns of inference that can be applied to derive chains of conclusions that lead to the desired goal Contents 1 Explanation 2 Formal notation 3 Justification via truth table 4 Status 5 Correspondence to other mathematical frameworks 5 1 Algebraic semantics 5 2 Probability calculus 5 3 Subjective logic 6 Alleged cases of failure 7 Possible fallacies 8 See also 9 References 10 Sources 11 External linksExplanation EditThe form of a modus ponens argument resembles a syllogism with two premises and a conclusion If P then Q P Therefore Q The first premise is a conditional if then claim namely that P implies Q The second premise is an assertion that P the antecedent of the conditional claim is the case From these two premises it can be logically concluded that Q the consequent of the conditional claim must be the case as well An example of an argument that fits the form modus ponens If today is Tuesday then John will go to work Today is Tuesday Therefore John will go to work This argument is valid but this has no bearing on whether any of the statements in the argument are actually true for modus ponens to be a sound argument the premises must be true for any true instances of the conclusion An argument can be valid but nonetheless unsound if one or more premises are false if an argument is valid and all the premises are true then the argument is sound For example John might be going to work on Wednesday In this case the reasoning for John s going to work because it is Wednesday is unsound The argument is only sound on Tuesdays when John goes to work but valid on every day of the week A propositional argument using modus ponens is said to be deductive In single conclusion sequent calculi modus ponens is the Cut rule The cut elimination theorem for a calculus says that every proof involving Cut can be transformed generally by a constructive method into a proof without Cut and hence that Cut is admissible The Curry Howard correspondence between proofs and programs relates modus ponens to function application if f is a function of type P Q and x is of type P then f x is of type Q In artificial intelligence modus ponens is often called forward chaining Formal notation EditThe modus ponens rule may be written in sequent notation as P Q P Q displaystyle P to Q P vdash Q where P Q and P Q are statements or propositions in a formal language and is a metalogical symbol meaning that Q is a syntactic consequence of P and P Q in some logical system Justification via truth table EditThe validity of modus ponens in classical two valued logic can be clearly demonstrated by use of a truth table p q p qT T TT F FF T TF F TIn instances of modus ponens we assume as premises that p q is true and p is true Only one line of the truth table the first satisfies these two conditions p and p q On this line q is also true Therefore whenever p q is true and p is true q must also be true Status EditWhile modus ponens is one of the most commonly used argument forms in logic it must not be mistaken for a logical law rather it is one of the accepted mechanisms for the construction of deductive proofs that includes the rule of definition and the rule of substitution 6 Modus ponens allows one to eliminate a conditional statement from a logical proof or argument the antecedents and thereby not carry these antecedents forward in an ever lengthening string of symbols for this reason modus ponens is sometimes called the rule of detachment 7 or the law of detachment 8 Enderton for example observes that modus ponens can produce shorter formulas from longer ones 9 and Russell observes that the process of the inference cannot be reduced to symbols Its sole record is the occurrence of q the consequent an inference is the dropping of a true premise it is the dissolution of an implication 10 A justification for the trust in inference is the belief that if the two former assertions the antecedents are not in error the final assertion the consequent is not in error 10 In other words if one statement or proposition implies a second one and the first statement or proposition is true then the second one is also true If P implies Q and P is true then Q is true 11 Correspondence to other mathematical frameworks EditAlgebraic semantics Edit In mathematical logic algebraic semantics treats every sentence as a name for an element in an ordered set Typically the set can be visualized as a lattice like structure with a single element the always true at the top and another single element the always false at the bottom Logical equivalence becomes identity so that when P Q displaystyle neg P wedge Q and P Q displaystyle neg P vee neg Q for instance are equivalent as is standard then P Q P Q displaystyle neg P wedge Q neg P vee neg Q Logical implication becomes a matter of relative position P displaystyle P logically implies Q displaystyle Q just in case P Q displaystyle P leq Q i e when either P Q displaystyle P Q or else P displaystyle P lies below Q displaystyle Q and is connected to it by an upward path In this context to say that P textstyle P and P Q displaystyle P rightarrow Q together imply Q displaystyle Q that is to affirm modus ponens as valid is to say that P P Q Q displaystyle P wedge P rightarrow Q leq Q In the semantics for basic propositional logic the algebra is Boolean with displaystyle rightarrow construed as the material conditional P Q P Q displaystyle P rightarrow Q neg P vee Q Confirming that P P Q Q displaystyle P wedge P rightarrow Q leq Q is then straightforward because P P Q P Q displaystyle P wedge P rightarrow Q P wedge Q With other treatments of displaystyle rightarrow the semantics becomes more complex the algebra may be non Boolean and the validity of modus ponens cannot be taken for granted Probability calculus Edit Modus ponens represents an instance of the Law of total probability which for a binary variable is expressed as Pr Q Pr Q P Pr P Pr Q P Pr P displaystyle Pr Q Pr Q mid P Pr P Pr Q mid lnot P Pr lnot P where e g Pr Q displaystyle Pr Q denotes the probability of Q displaystyle Q and the conditional probability Pr Q P displaystyle Pr Q mid P generalizes the logical implication P Q displaystyle P to Q Assume that Pr Q 1 displaystyle Pr Q 1 is equivalent to Q displaystyle Q being TRUE and that Pr Q 0 displaystyle Pr Q 0 is equivalent to Q displaystyle Q being FALSE It is then easy to see that Pr Q 1 displaystyle Pr Q 1 when Pr Q P 1 displaystyle Pr Q mid P 1 and Pr P 1 displaystyle Pr P 1 Hence the law of total probability represents a generalization of modus ponens 12 Subjective logic Edit Modus ponens represents an instance of the binomial deduction operator in subjective logic expressed as w Q P A w Q P A w Q P A w P A displaystyle omega Q P A omega Q P A omega Q lnot P A circledcirc omega P A where w P A displaystyle omega P A denotes the subjective opinion about P displaystyle P as expressed by source A displaystyle A and the conditional opinion w Q P A displaystyle omega Q P A generalizes the logical implication P Q displaystyle P to Q The deduced marginal opinion about Q displaystyle Q is denoted by w Q P A displaystyle omega Q P A The case where w P A displaystyle omega P A is an absolute TRUE opinion about P displaystyle P is equivalent to source A displaystyle A saying that P displaystyle P is TRUE and the case where w P A displaystyle omega P A is an absolute FALSE opinion about P displaystyle P is equivalent to source A displaystyle A saying that P displaystyle P is FALSE The deduction operator displaystyle circledcirc of subjective logic produces an absolute TRUE deduced opinion w Q P A displaystyle omega Q P A when the conditional opinion w Q P A displaystyle omega Q P A is absolute TRUE and the antecedent opinion w P A displaystyle omega P A is absolute TRUE Hence subjective logic deduction represents a generalization of both modus ponens and the Law of total probability 13 Alleged cases of failure EditPhilosophers and linguists have identified a variety of cases where modus ponens appears to fail Vann McGee for instance argued that modus ponens can fail for conditionals whose consequents are themselves conditionals 14 The following is an example Either Shakespeare or Hobbes wrote Hamlet If either Shakespeare or Hobbes wrote Hamlet then if Shakespeare didn t do it Hobbes did Therefore if Shakespeare didn t write Hamlet Hobbes did it Since Shakespeare did write Hamlet the first premise is true The second premise is also true since starting with a set of possible authors limited to just Shakespeare and Hobbes and eliminating one of them leaves only the other However the conclusion may seem false since ruling out Shakespeare as the author of Hamlet would leave numerous possible candidates many of them more plausible alternatives than Hobbes The general form of McGee type counterexamples to modus ponens is simply P P Q R displaystyle P P rightarrow Q rightarrow R therefore Q R displaystyle Q rightarrow R it is not essential that P displaystyle P be a disjunction as in the example given That these kinds of cases constitute failures of modus ponens remains a controversial view among logicians but opinions vary on how the cases should be disposed of 15 16 17 In deontic logic some examples of conditional obligation also raise the possibility of modus ponens failure These are cases where the conditional premise describes an obligation predicated on an immoral or imprudent action e g If Doe murders his mother he ought to do so gently for which the dubious unconditional conclusion would be Doe ought to gently murder his mother 18 It would appear to follow that if Doe is in fact gently murdering his mother then by modus ponens he is doing exactly what he should unconditionally be doing Here again modus ponens failure is not a popular diagnosis but is sometimes argued for 19 Possible fallacies EditThe fallacy of affirming the consequent is a common misinterpretation of the modus ponens 20 See also EditCondensed detachment Import Export logic Latin phrases Modus tollens Rule of logical inference Modus vivendi Arrangement that allows conflicting parties to coexist in peace Stoic logic System of propositional logic developed by the Stoic philosophers What the Tortoise Said to Achilles Allegorical dialogue by Lewis CarrollReferences Edit Stone Jon R 1996 Latin for the Illiterati Exorcizing the Ghosts of a Dead Language London Routledge p 60 ISBN 0 415 91775 1 Oxford reference affirming the antecedent Oxford Reference Enderton 2001 110 Susanne Bobzien 2002 The Development of Modus Ponens in Antiquity Phronesis 47 No 4 2002 Ancient Logic Forerunners of Modus Ponens and Modus Tollens Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Alfred Tarski 1946 47 Also Enderton 2001 110ff Tarski 1946 47 Modus ponens Encyclopedia of Mathematics encyclopediaofmath org Retrieved 5 April 2018 Enderton 2001 111 a b Whitehead and Russell 1927 9 Jago Mark 2007 Formal Logic Humanities Ebooks LLP ISBN 978 1 84760 041 7 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a External link in code class cs1 code publisher code help Audun Josang 2016 2 Audun Josang 2016 92 Vann McGee 1985 A Counterexample to Modus Ponens The Journal of Philosophy 82 462 471 Sinnott Armstrong Moor and Fogelin 1986 A Defense of Modus Ponens The Journal of Philosophy 83 296 300 D E Over 1987 Assumption and the Supposed Counterexamples to Modus Ponens Analysis 47 142 146 Bledin 2015 Modus Ponens Defended The Journal of Philosophy 112 462 471 Deontic Logic 21 April 2010 Retrieved 30 January 2020 Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy E g by Kolodny and MacFarlane 2010 Ifs and Oughts The Journal of Philosophy 107 115 143 Fallacies Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy iep utm edu Retrieved 6 March 2020 Sources EditHerbert B Enderton 2001 A Mathematical Introduction to Logic Second Edition Harcourt Academic Press Burlington MA ISBN 978 0 12 238452 3 Audun Josang 2016 Subjective Logic A formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty Springer Cham ISBN 978 3 319 42337 1 Alfred North Whitehead and Bertrand Russell 1927 Principia Mathematica to 56 Second Edition paperback edition 1962 Cambridge at the University Press London UK No ISBN no LCCCN Alfred Tarski 1946 Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences 2nd Edition reprinted by Dover Publications Mineola NY ISBN 0 486 28462 X pbk External links Edit Modus ponens Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 Modus ponens at PhilPapers Modus ponens at Wolfram MathWorld Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Modus ponens amp oldid 1122149716, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.