fbpx
Wikipedia

Well-ordering principle

In mathematics, the well-ordering principle states that every non-empty set of positive integers contains a least element.[1] In other words, the set of positive integers is well-ordered by its "natural" or "magnitude" order in which precedes if and only if is either or the sum of and some positive integer (other orderings include the ordering ; and ).

The phrase "well-ordering principle" is sometimes taken to be synonymous with the "well-ordering theorem". On other occasions it is understood to be the proposition that the set of integers contains a well-ordered subset, called the natural numbers, in which every nonempty subset contains a least element.

Properties

Depending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced, this (second order) property of the set of natural numbers is either an axiom or a provable theorem. For example:

  • In Peano arithmetic, second-order arithmetic and related systems, and indeed in most (not necessarily formal) mathematical treatments of the well-ordering principle, the principle is derived from the principle of mathematical induction, which is itself taken as basic.
  • Considering the natural numbers as a subset of the real numbers, and assuming that we know already that the real numbers are complete (again, either as an axiom or a theorem about the real number system), i.e., every bounded (from below) set has an infimum, then also every set   of natural numbers has an infimum, say  . We can now find an integer   such that   lies in the half-open interval  , and can then show that we must have  , and   in  .
  • In axiomatic set theory, the natural numbers are defined as the smallest inductive set (i.e., set containing 0 and closed under the successor operation). One can (even without invoking the regularity axiom) show that the set of all natural numbers   such that "  is well-ordered" is inductive, and must therefore contain all natural numbers; from this property one can conclude that the set of all natural numbers is also well-ordered.

In the second sense, this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form: to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set  , assume the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus contains a smallest counterexample. Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction. This mode of argument is the contrapositive of proof by complete induction. It is known light-heartedly as the "minimal criminal" method[citation needed] and is similar in its nature to Fermat's method of "infinite descent".

Garrett Birkhoff and Saunders Mac Lane wrote in A Survey of Modern Algebra that this property, like the least upper bound axiom for real numbers, is non-algebraic; i.e., it cannot be deduced from the algebraic properties of the integers (which form an ordered integral domain).

References

  1. ^ Apostol, Tom (1976). Introduction to Analytic Number Theory. New York: Springer-Verlag. pp. 13. ISBN 0-387-90163-9.

well, ordering, principle, confused, with, well, ordering, theorem, this, article, needs, additional, citations, verification, please, help, improve, this, article, adding, citations, reliable, sources, unsourced, material, challenged, removed, find, sources, . Not to be confused with Well ordering theorem This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Well ordering principle news newspapers books scholar JSTOR July 2008 Learn how and when to remove this template message In mathematics the well ordering principle states that every non empty set of positive integers contains a least element 1 In other words the set of positive integers is well ordered by its natural or magnitude order in which x displaystyle x precedes y displaystyle y if and only if y displaystyle y is either x displaystyle x or the sum of x displaystyle x and some positive integer other orderings include the ordering 2 4 6 displaystyle 2 4 6 and 1 3 5 displaystyle 1 3 5 The phrase well ordering principle is sometimes taken to be synonymous with the well ordering theorem On other occasions it is understood to be the proposition that the set of integers 2 1 0 1 2 3 displaystyle ldots 2 1 0 1 2 3 ldots contains a well ordered subset called the natural numbers in which every nonempty subset contains a least element Properties EditDepending on the framework in which the natural numbers are introduced this second order property of the set of natural numbers is either an axiom or a provable theorem For example In Peano arithmetic second order arithmetic and related systems and indeed in most not necessarily formal mathematical treatments of the well ordering principle the principle is derived from the principle of mathematical induction which is itself taken as basic Considering the natural numbers as a subset of the real numbers and assuming that we know already that the real numbers are complete again either as an axiom or a theorem about the real number system i e every bounded from below set has an infimum then also every set A displaystyle A of natural numbers has an infimum say a displaystyle a We can now find an integer n displaystyle n such that a displaystyle a lies in the half open interval n 1 n displaystyle n 1 n and can then show that we must have a n displaystyle a n and n displaystyle n in A displaystyle A In axiomatic set theory the natural numbers are defined as the smallest inductive set i e set containing 0 and closed under the successor operation One can even without invoking the regularity axiom show that the set of all natural numbers n displaystyle n such that 0 n displaystyle 0 ldots n is well ordered is inductive and must therefore contain all natural numbers from this property one can conclude that the set of all natural numbers is also well ordered In the second sense this phrase is used when that proposition is relied on for the purpose of justifying proofs that take the following form to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set S displaystyle S assume the contrary which implies that the set of counterexamples is non empty and thus contains a smallest counterexample Then show that for any counterexample there is a still smaller counterexample producing a contradiction This mode of argument is the contrapositive of proof by complete induction It is known light heartedly as the minimal criminal method citation needed and is similar in its nature to Fermat s method of infinite descent Garrett Birkhoff and Saunders Mac Lane wrote in A Survey of Modern Algebra that this property like the least upper bound axiom for real numbers is non algebraic i e it cannot be deduced from the algebraic properties of the integers which form an ordered integral domain References Edit Apostol Tom 1976 Introduction to Analytic Number Theory New York Springer Verlag pp 13 ISBN 0 387 90163 9 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Well ordering principle amp oldid 1092624361, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.