fbpx
Wikipedia

Approval voting

Approval voting is an electoral system in which voters can select any number of candidates instead of selecting only one.

On an approval ballot, the voter can select any number of candidates.

Description edit

Approval voting ballots show a list of all the candidates running and each voter indicates support for as many candidates as they see fit. Final tallies show how many votes each candidate received, and the winner is the candidate with the most support.

Effect on elections edit

Approval voting advocates Steven Brams and Dudley R. Herschbach predict that Approval should increase voter participation, prevent minor-party candidates from being spoilers, and reduce negative campaigning.[1] One study showed that Approval would not have chosen the same two winners as plurality voting (Chirac and Le Pen) in the first round of the 2002 French presidential election; it instead would have chosen Chirac and Jospin as the top two candidates to proceed to the runoff.

In the actual election, Le Pen lost by an overwhelming margin in the runoff, 82.2% to 17.8%, a sign that the true top two candidates had not been found. In the approval voting survey primary, Chirac took first place with 36.7%, compared to Jospin at 32.9%. Le Pen, in that study, received 25.1% and so would not have made the cut to the second round. In the real primary election, the top three were Chirac, 19.9%, Le Pen, 16.9%, and Jospin, 16.2%.[2] A study of various "evaluative voting" methods (Approval and score voting) during the 2012 French presidential election showed that "unifying" candidates tended to do better, and polarizing candidates did worse, as compared to under plurality voting.[3]

A generalized version of the Burr dilemma applies to Approval when two candidates are appealing to the same subset of voters. Although Approval differs from the voting system used in the Burr dilemma, Approval can still leave candidates and voters with the generalized dilemma of whether to compete or cooperate.[4][5] But, Approval satisfies the favorite betrayal criterion, which means that it is always safe for a voter to give their true favorite maximum support.

While in the modern era there have been relatively few competitive Approval elections where tactical voting is more likely, Brams argues that Approval usually elects Condorcet winners in practice.[6][7]

Operational impacts edit

  • Simple to tally—Approval ballots can be counted by some existing machines designed for plurality elections, as ballots are cast, so that final tallies are immediately available after the election, with relatively few if any upgrades to equipment.
  • Just one round—Approval can remove the need for multiple rounds of voting, such as a primary or a run-off, simplifying the election process.
  • Avoids Overvotes—Approval voting does not have the notion of overvotes, where voting for one more than allowed will cancel the entire opportunity to vote. In plurality elections, overvotes have to be reviewed and resolved if possible while in approval voting, no time is wasted on this activity.

Usage edit

Current edit

In 2018, Fargo, North Dakota, passed a local ballot initiative adopting Approval for the city's local elections, becoming the first United States city and jurisdiction to adopt Approval.[8][9] Previously in 2015, a Fargo city commissioner election had suffered from six-way vote-splitting, resulting in a candidate winning with an unconvincing 22% plurality of the vote.[10]

The first election was held June 9, 2020, selecting two city commissioners, from seven candidates on the ballot.[11] Both winners received over 50% approval, with an average 2.3 approvals per ballot, and 62% of voters supported the change to Approval in a poll.[12] A poll by opponents of Approval was conducted to test whether voters had in fact voted strategically according to the Burr dilemma.[13] They found that 30% of voters who bullet voted did so for strategic reasons, while 57% did so because it was their sincere opinion.[14][15] Fargo's second Approval election took place in June 2022, for mayor and city commission. The incumbent mayor was re-elected from a field of 7 candidates, with an estimated 65% approval, with voters expressing 1.6 approvals per ballot, and the two commissioners were elected from a field of 15 candidates, with 3.1 approvals per ballot.[16]

In November 2020, St. Louis, Missouri, passed Proposition D with 70% voting to authorize a variant of Approval (unified primary) for municipal offices.[17] The first St. Louis approval primary was held on March 2nd, 2021 and saw Tishaura Jones and Cara Spencer move on to the general with 57% and 46% support. Lewis Reed and Andrew Jones were eliminated with 39% and 14% support, resulting in an average of 1.6 candidates supported by each voter in the 4 person race.[18]

In February 2024, Ben Baker introduced legislation to ban approval and ranked-choice voting state-wide.[19][20] It passed in the House on Apr 15, 2024.[21] In a similar move, the North Dakota legislature passed a bill which intended to ban approval voting. The bill was vetoed by governor Doug Burgum, citing the importance of "home rule" and allowing citizens control over their local government. The legislature attempted to overrule the veto and failed.[22]

The Latvian parliament uses approval voting within open list proportional representation.[23]

History edit

 
Rows of secret approval vote boxes from early 1900s Greece, where the voter drops a marble to the right or left of the box, through a tube, one for each candidate standing

Robert J. Weber coined the term "Approval Voting" in 1971.[24] It was more fully published in 1978 by political scientist Steven Brams and mathematician Peter Fishburn.[25]

Historically, several voting methods that incorporate aspects of Approval have been used:

  • Approval was used for papal conclaves between 1294 and 1621, with an average of about forty cardinals engaging in repeated rounds of voting until one candidate was listed on at least two-thirds of ballots.[26]
  • In the 13th through 18th centuries, the Republic of Venice elected the Doge of Venice using a multi-stage process that featured random selection and voting that allowed approval of multiple candidates and required a supermajority.[27][28]
  • According to Steven J. Brams, Approval was used for unspecified elections in 19th century England.[29]
  • The selection of the Secretary-General of the United Nations has involved "straw poll" rounds of approval polling to help discover and build a consensus before a formal vote is held in the Security Council.[30] The United Nations Secretary-General selection, 2006 indicated that South Korean Foreign Minister Ban Ki-moon was the only candidate to be acceptable to all five permanent members of the Security Council, which led to the withdrawal of India's Shashi Tharoor, who had the highest overall approval rate.[31]
  • Approval was used in Greek legislative elections from 1864 to 1923, when it was replaced with proportional representation.[32]
  • Sequential proportional approval voting was used in Swedish elections in the early 20th century, prior to being replaced by party-list proportional representation.

Political organizations and jurisdictions edit

Approval has been used in privately administered nomination contests by the Independent Party of Oregon in 2011, 2012, 2014, and 2016. Oregon is a fusion voting state, and the party has cross-nominated legislators and statewide officeholders using this method; its 2016 presidential preference primary did not identify a potential nominee due to no candidate earning more than 32% support.[33][34][35] The party switched to using STAR voting in 2020.[36][37]

It is also used in internal elections by the American Solidarity Party;[38] the Green Parties of Texas[39][40] and Ohio;[41] the Libertarian National Committee;[42] the Libertarian parties of Texas,[43] Colorado,[44][45] Arizona,[46] and New York;[47] Alliance 90/The Greens in Germany;[48] and the Czech[49] and German Pirate Party.[50][51]

Other organizations edit

The idea of approval was adopted by X. Hu and Lloyd Shapley in 2003 in studying authority distribution in organizations.[52]

Approval has been adopted by several societies: the Society for Social Choice and Welfare (1992),[53] Mathematical Association of America (1986),[54] the American Mathematical Society,[55] the Institute of Management Sciences (1987) (now the Institute for Operations Research and the Management Sciences),[56] the American Statistical Association (1987),[57] and the Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers (1987). The IEEE board in 2002 rescinded its decision to use Approval. IEEE Executive Director Daniel J. Senese stated that Approval was abandoned because "few of our members were using it and it was felt that it was no longer needed."[7] (It is worth noting that most IEEE elections had only two candidates listed on the ballot.) Because none of these associations report results to their members and the public, it is difficult to evaluate Senese's claim and whether it is also true of other associations; Steven Brams' analysis of the 5-candidate 1987 Mathematical Association of America presidential election shows that 79% of voters cast a ballot for one candidate, 16% for 2 candidates, 5% for 3, and 1% for 4, with the winner earning the approval of 1,267 (32%) of 3,924 voters.[7][58]

Approval also can be used in social scenarios as a fairer system compared to a first-past-the-post equivalent, being able to avoid a spoiler effect while still being very quick to calculate.

Strategic voting edit

Overview edit

Approval voting allows voters to select all the candidates whom they consider to be reasonable choices.

Strategic Approval differs from ranked voting (aka preferential voting) methods where voters might reverse the preference order of two options, which if done on a larger scale can cause an unpopular candidate to win. Strategic Approval, with more than two options, involves the voter changing their approval threshold. The voter decides which options to give the same rating, even if they were to have a preference order between them. This leaves a tactical concern any voter has for approving their second-favorite candidate, in the case that there are three or more candidates. Approving their second-favorite means the voter harms their favorite candidate's chance to win. Not approving their second-favorite means the voter helps the candidate they least desire to beat their second-favorite and perhaps win.

Approval allows for bullet voting and compromising, while it is immune to push-over and burying.

Bullet voting occurs when a voter approves only candidate "a" instead of both "a" and "b" for the reason that voting for "b" can cause "a" to lose. The voter would be satisfied with either "a" or "b" but has a moderate preference for "a". Were "b" to win, this hypothetical voter would still be satisfied. If supporters of both "a" and "b" do this, it could cause candidate "c" to win. This creates the "chicken dilemma", as supporters of "a" and "b" are playing chicken as to which will stop strategic voting first, before both of these candidates lose.

Compromising occurs when a voter approves an additional candidate who is otherwise considered unacceptable to the voter to prevent an even worse alternative from winning.

Sincere voting edit

Approval experts describe sincere votes as those "... that directly reflect the true preferences of a voter, i.e., that do not report preferences 'falsely.'"[59] They also give a specific definition of a sincere approval vote in terms of the voter's ordinal preferences as being any vote that, if it votes for one candidate, it also votes for any more preferred candidate. This definition allows a sincere vote to treat strictly preferred candidates the same, ensuring that every voter has at least one sincere vote. The definition also allows a sincere vote to treat equally preferred candidates differently. When there are two or more candidates, every voter has at least three sincere approval votes to choose from. Two of those sincere approval votes do not distinguish between any of the candidates: vote for none of the candidates and vote for all of the candidates. When there are three or more candidates, every voter has more than one sincere approval vote that distinguishes between the candidates.

Examples edit

Based on the definition above, if there are four candidates, A, B, C, and D, and a voter has a strict preference order, preferring A to B to C to D, then the following are the voter's possible sincere approval votes:

  • vote for A, B, C, and D
  • vote for A, B, and C
  • vote for A and B
  • vote for A
  • vote for no candidates

If the voter instead equally prefers B and C, while A is still the most preferred candidate and D is the least preferred candidate, then all of the above votes are sincere and the following combination is also a sincere vote:

  • vote for A and C

The decision between the above ballots is equivalent to deciding an arbitrary "approval cutoff." All candidates preferred to the cutoff are approved, all candidates less preferred are not approved, and any candidates equal to the cutoff may be approved or not arbitrarily.

Sincere strategy with ordinal preferences edit

A sincere voter with multiple options for voting sincerely still has to choose which sincere vote to use. Voting strategy is a way to make that choice, in which case strategic Approval includes sincere voting, rather than being an alternative to it.[60] This differs from other voting systems that typically have a unique sincere vote for a voter.

When there are three or more candidates, the winner of an Approval election can change, depending on which sincere votes are used. In some cases, Approval can sincerely elect any one of the candidates, including a Condorcet winner and a Condorcet loser, without the voter preferences changing. To the extent that electing a Condorcet winner and not electing a Condorcet loser is considered desirable outcomes for a voting system, Approval can be considered vulnerable to sincere, strategic voting.[61] In one sense, conditions where this can happen are robust and are not isolated cases.[62] On the other hand, the variety of possible outcomes has also been portrayed as a virtue of Approval, representing the flexibility and responsiveness of Approval, not just to voter ordinal preferences, but cardinal utilities as well.[63]

Dichotomous preferences edit

Approval avoids the issue of multiple sincere votes in special cases when voters have dichotomous preferences. For a voter with dichotomous preferences, Approval is strategy-proof (also known as strategy-free).[64] When all voters have dichotomous preferences and vote the sincere, strategy-proof vote, Approval is guaranteed to elect the Condorcet winner, if one exists.[65] However, having dichotomous preferences when there are three or more candidates is not typical. It is an unlikely situation for all voters to have dichotomous preferences when there are more than a few voters.[60]

Having dichotomous preferences means that a voter has bi-level preferences for the candidates. All of the candidates are divided into two groups such that the voter is indifferent between any two candidates in the same group and any candidate in the top-level group is preferred to any candidate in the bottom-level group.[66] A voter that has strict preferences between three candidates—prefers A to B and B to C—does not have dichotomous preferences.

Being strategy-proof for a voter means that there is a unique way for the voter to vote that is a strategically best way to vote, regardless of how others vote. In Approval, the strategy-proof vote, if it exists, is a sincere vote.[59]

Approval threshold edit

Another way to deal with multiple sincere votes is to augment the ordinal preference model with an approval or acceptance threshold. An approval threshold divides all of the candidates into two sets, those the voter approves of and those the voter does not approve of. A voter can approve of more than one candidate and still prefer one approved candidate to another approved candidate. Acceptance thresholds are similar. With such a threshold, a voter simply votes for every candidate that meets or exceeds the threshold.[60]

With threshold voting, it is still possible to not elect the Condorcet winner and instead elect the Condorcet loser when they both exist. However, according to Steven Brams, this represents a strength rather than a weakness of Approval. Without providing specifics, he argues that the pragmatic judgements of voters about which candidates are acceptable should take precedence over the Condorcet criterion and other social choice criteria.[67]

Strategy with cardinal utilities edit

Voting strategy under approval is guided by two competing features of Approval. On the one hand, Approval fails the later-no-harm criterion, so voting for a candidate can cause that candidate to win instead of a candidate more preferred by that voter. On the other hand, Approval satisfies the monotonicity criterion, so not voting for a candidate can never help that candidate win, but can cause that candidate to lose to a less preferred candidate. Either way, the voter can risk getting a less preferred election winner. A voter can balance the risk-benefit trade-offs by considering the voter's cardinal utilities, particularly via the von Neumann–Morgenstern utility theorem, and the probabilities of how others vote.

A rational voter model described by Myerson and Weber specifies an Approval strategy that votes for those candidates that have a positive prospective rating.[68] This strategy is optimal in the sense that it maximizes the voter's expected utility, subject to the constraints of the model and provided the number of other voters is sufficiently large.

An optimal approval vote always votes for the most preferred candidate and not for the least preferred candidate. However, an optimal vote can require voting for a candidate and not voting for a more preferred candidate if there 4 candidates or more.[69]

Other strategies are also available and coincide with the optimal strategy in special situations. For example:

  • Vote for the candidates that have above average utility. This strategy coincides with the optimal strategy if the voter thinks that all pairwise ties are equally likely[70]
  • Vote for any candidate that is more preferred than the expected winner and also vote for the expected winner if the expected winner is more preferred than the expected runner-up. This strategy coincides with the optimal strategy if there are three or fewer candidates or if the pivot probability for a tie between the expected winner and expected runner-up is sufficiently large compared to the other pivot probabilities. This strategy, if used by all voters implies at equilibrium the election of the Condorcet winner whenever it exists.[71]
  • Vote for the most preferred candidate only. This strategy coincides with the optimal strategy when there is only one candidate with a positive prospective rating.

Another strategy is to vote for the top half of the candidates, the candidates that have an above-median utility. When the voter thinks that others are balancing their votes randomly and evenly, the strategy maximizes the voter's power or efficacy, meaning that it maximizes the probability that the voter will make a difference in deciding which candidate wins.[72]

Optimal strategic Approval fails to satisfy the Condorcet criterion and can elect a Condorcet loser. Strategic Approval can guarantee electing the Condorcet winner in some special circumstances. For example, if all voters are rational and cast a strategically optimal vote based on a common knowledge of how all the other voters vote except for small-probability, statistically independent errors in recording the votes, then the winner will be the Condorcet winner, if one exists.[73]

Strategy examples edit

In the example election described here, assume that the voters in each faction share the following von Neumann–Morgenstern utilities, fitted to the interval between 0 and 100. The utilities are consistent with the rankings given earlier and reflect a strong preference each faction has for choosing its city, compared to weaker preferences for other factors such as the distance to the other cities.

Voter utilities for each candidate city
Fraction of voters (living close to) Candidates Average
Memphis Nashville Chattanooga Knoxville
Memphis (42%) 100 15 10 0 31.25
Nashville (26%) 0 100 20 15 33.75
Chattanooga (15%) 0 15 100 35 37.5
Knoxville (17%) 0 15 40 100 38.75

Using these utilities, voters choose their optimal strategic votes based on what they think the various pivot probabilities are for pairwise ties. In each of the scenarios summarized below, all voters share a common set of pivot probabilities.

Approval Voting results for scenarios using optimal strategic voting
Strategy scenario Winner Runner-up Candidate vote totals
Memphis Nashville Chattanooga Knoxville
Zero-info Memphis Chattanooga 42 26 32 17
Memphis leading Chattanooga Three-way tie 42 58 58 58
Chattanooga leading Knoxville Chattanooga Nashville 42 68 83 17
Chattanooga leading Nashville Nashville Memphis 42 68 32 17
Nashville leading Memphis Nashville Memphis 42 58 32 32

In the first scenario, voters all choose their votes based on the assumption that all pairwise ties are equally likely. As a result, they vote for any candidate with an above-average utility. Most voters vote for only their first choice. Only the Knoxville faction also votes for its second choice, Chattanooga. As a result, the winner is Memphis, the Condorcet loser, with Chattanooga coming in second place. In this scenario, the winner has minority approval (more voters disapproved than approved) and all the others had even less support, reflecting the position that no choice gave an above-average utility to a majority of voters.

In the second scenario, all of the voters expect that Memphis is the likely winner, that Chattanooga is the likely runner-up, and that the pivot probability for a Memphis-Chattanooga tie is much larger than the pivot probabilities of any other pair-wise ties. As a result, each voter votes for any candidate they prefer more than the leading candidate, and also vote for the leading candidate if they prefer that candidate more than the expected runner-up. Each remaining scenario follows a similar pattern of expectations and voting strategies.

In the second scenario, there is a three-way tie for first place. This happens because the expected winner, Memphis, was the Condorcet loser and was also ranked last by any voter that did not rank it first.

Only in the last scenario does the actual winner and runner-up match the expected winner and runner-up. As a result, this can be considered a stable strategic voting scenario. In the language of game theory, this is an "equilibrium." In this scenario, the winner is also the Condorcet winner.

Dichotomous cutoff edit

As this voting method is cardinal rather than ordinal, it is possible to model voters in a way that does not simplify to an ordinal method. Modelling voters with a 'dichotomous cutoff' assumes a voter has an immovable approval cutoff, while having meaningful cardinal preferences. This means that rather than voting for their top 3 candidates, or all candidates above the average approval (which may result in their vote changing if one candidate drops out, resulting in a system that does not satisfy IIA), they instead vote for all candidates above a certain approval 'cutoff' that they have decided. This cutoff does not change, regardless of which and how many candidates are running, so when all available alternatives are either above or below the cutoff, the voter votes for all or none of the candidates, despite preferring some over others. This could be imagined to reflect a case where many voters become disenfranchised and apathetic if they see no candidates they approve of. In a case such as this, many voters may have an internal cutoff, and would not simply vote for their top 3, or the above average candidates, although that is not to say that it is necessarily entirely immovable.

For example, in this scenario, voters are voting for candidates with approval above 50% (bold signifies that the voters voted for the candidate):

Proportion of electorate Approval of Candidate A Approval of Candidate B Approval of Candidate C Approval of Candidate D Average approval
25% 90% 60% 40% 10% 50%
35% 10% 90% 60% 40% 50%
30% 40% 10% 90% 60% 50%
10% 60% 40% 10% 90% 50%

C wins with 65% of the voters' approval, beating B with 60%, D with 40% and A with 35%

If voters' threshold for receiving a vote is that the candidate has an above average approval, or they vote for their two most approved of candidates, this is not a dichotomous cutoff, as this can change if candidates drop out. On the other hand, if voters' threshold for receiving a vote is fixed (say 50%), this is a dichotomous cutoff, and satisfies IIA as shown below:

A drops out, candidates voting for above average approval
Proportion of electorate Approval of Candidate A Approval of Candidate B Approval of Candidate C Approval of Candidate D Average approval
25% 60% 40% 10% 37%
35% 90% 60% 40% 63%
30% 10% 90% 60% 53%
10% 40% 10% 90% 47%

B now wins with 60%, beating C with 55% and D with 40%

A drops out, candidates voting for approval > 50%
Proportion of electorate Approval of Candidate A Approval of Candidate B Approval of Candidate C Approval of Candidate D Average approval
25% 60% 40% 10% 37%
35% 90% 60% 40% 63%
30% 10% 90% 60% 53%
10% 40% 10% 90% 47%

With dichotomous cutoff, C still wins.

D drops out, candidates voting for top 2 candidates
Proportion of electorate Approval of Candidate A Approval of Candidate B Approval of Candidate C Approval of Candidate D Average approval
25% 90% 60% 40% 63%
35% 10% 90% 60% 53%
30% 40% 10% 90% 47%
10% 60% 40% 10% 37%

B now wins with 70%, beating C and A with 65%

D drops out, candidates voting for approval > 50%
Proportion of electorate Approval of Candidate A Approval of Candidate B Approval of Candidate C Approval of Candidate D Average approval
25% 90% 60% 40% 63%
35% 10% 90% 60% 53%
30% 40% 10% 90% 47%
10% 60% 40% 10% 37%

With dichotomous cutoff, C still wins.

Compliance with voting system criteria edit

Most of the mathematical criteria by which voting systems are compared were formulated for voters with ordinal preferences. In this case, approval voting requires voters to make an additional decision of where to put their approval cutoff (see examples above). Depending on how this decision is made, Approval satisfies different sets of criteria.

There is no ultimate authority on which criteria should be considered, but the following are criteria that many voting theorists accept and consider desirable:

  • Unrestricted domain—A voter may have any preference ordering among the alternatives.
  • Non-dictatorship—There does not exist a single voter whose preference for the alternatives always determines the outcome regardless of other voters' preferences.
  • Pareto efficiency—If every voter prefers candidate A to all other candidates, then A must be elected. (from Arrow's impossibility theorem)
  • Majority criterion—If there exists a majority that ranks (or rates) a single candidate higher than all other candidates, does that candidate always win?
  • Monotonicity criterion—Is it impossible to cause a winning candidate to lose by ranking that candidate higher, or to cause a losing candidate to win by ranking that candidate lower?
  • Consistency criterion—If the electorate is divided in two and a choice wins in both parts, does it always win overall?
  • Participation criterion—Is voting honestly always better than not voting at all? (This is grouped with the distinct but similar Consistency Criterion in the table below.[a])
  • Condorcet criterion—If a candidate beats every other candidate in pairwise comparison, does that candidate always win? (This implies the majority criterion, above)
  • Condorcet loser criterion—If a candidate loses to every other candidate in pairwise comparison, does that candidate always lose?
  • Independence of irrelevant alternatives—Is the outcome the same after adding or removing non-winning candidates?
  • Independence of clones criterion—Is the outcome the same if candidates identical to existing candidates are added?
  • Reversal symmetry—If individual preferences of each voter are inverted, does the original winner never win?
Unrestricted domain Non-dictatorship Pareto efficiency Majority Monotone Consistency & Participation Condorcet Condorcet loser IIA Clone independence Reversal symmetry
Cardinal preferences Zero information, rational voters Yes Yes No[b] No Yes Yes No No No No Yes
Imperfect information, rational voters Yes Yes No No Yes Yes No No No No Yes
Strong Nash equilibrium (Perfect information, rational voters, and perfect strategy) Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes No Yes No[c] No Yes Yes
Absolute cutoff Yes No[d] Yes[e] No Yes Yes No No Yes[f] Yes Yes
Dichotomous preferences Rational voters No[g] Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes

Approval satisfies the mutual majority criterion and Smith criterion when voters' preferences are dichotomous; this is because the winner will be someone that the most voters prefer above all others, or that ties with other candidates but the group of tied candidates is preferred by more voters than any candidate not in the group.

See also edit

Some variants and generalizations of approval voting are:

Notes edit

  1. ^ Consistency implies participation, but not vice versa. For example, Score Voting complies with participation and consistency, but median ratings satisfies participation and fails consistency.
  2. ^ When the criterion is failed, the result is always a tie between the alternative preferred by all voters and one or more other alternatives. The criterion can only be failed when the tied candidates are approved on every ballot cast in the election.
  3. ^ The probability of failing this criterion vanishes asymptotically as the number of voters grows.
  4. ^ If voters are forced to determine their approval cutoff without knowing the available alternatives prior to an election, there can exist two alternatives for which one voter's preference determines the winner regardless of another voter's preference. For example, consider a cardinal scale from 0 to 1, with 0.5 as the cutoff. The criterion is personal wealth for voter A and quality of drinking water for voter B. There can exist two candidates, such that voter A's cardinal preferences are 0.49 and 0.51, while voter B's preferences are 0 and 0.49. Voter A's preferences, despite how trivial, determine the outcome of the election regardless of voter B's preferences, because voter B is forced to abstain, even while having a stronger preference.
  5. ^ Pareto efficiency is implied by, and is weaker than the combination of Monotonicity, IIA and Non-Imposition (that every possible societal preference order should be achievable by some set of individual preference orders, which is the case in all of these scenarios). These three conditions were in fact specified in the original statement of Arrow's impossibility theorem
  6. ^ The model assumes a voter has an immovable approval cutoff while also having meaningful cardinal preferences. When all available alternatives are either above or below the cutoff, the voter votes for all or none of the candidates, despite preferring some over others.
  7. ^ In a dichotomous preference society, voters do not have a preferred ordering for the alternatives, such as A>B>C. Each voter has a binary "yes" or "no" rating for any alternative, while having no degree of preference among alternatives with either rating.

References edit

  1. ^ Brams, Steven J.; Herschbach, Dudley R. (2001). "The Science of Elections". Science. 292 (5521): 1449. doi:10.1126/science.292.5521.1449. JSTOR 3083781. PMID 11379606. S2CID 28262658.
  2. ^ Laslier, Jean-François; Vander Straeten, Karine (April 2003). (PDF). p. 6. Archived from the original (PDF) on May 7, 2005. Retrieved July 8, 2014.
  3. ^ Baujard, Antoinette; Igersheim, Herrade; Lebon, Isabelle; Gavrel, Frédéric; Laslier, Jean-François (2014-06-01). "Who's favored by evaluative voting? An experiment conducted during the 2012 French presidential election" (PDF). Electoral Studies. 34: 131–145. doi:10.1016/j.electstud.2013.11.003. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  4. ^ Nagel, J. H. (2007). (PDF). The Journal of Politics. 69 (1): 43–58. doi:10.1111/j.1468-2508.2007.00493.x. S2CID 154179804. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2007-06-21. Retrieved 2007-06-06.
  5. ^ Nagel, J. H. (2006). "A Strategic Problem in Approval Voting". Mathematics and Democracy. Studies in Choice and Welfare: 133–150. doi:10.1007/3-540-35605-3_10. ISBN 978-3-540-35603-5.
  6. ^ Brams, Steven J. (2008). Mathematics and Democracy: Designing Better Voting and Fair-Division Procedures. Princeton University Press. p. 16. ISBN 9780691133218.
  7. ^ a b c Brams, Steven J.; Fishburn, Peter C. (August 2003). (PDF). Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association. American Political Science Association. Archived from the original (PDF) on December 18, 2018. Retrieved May 8, 2010.
  8. ^ One of America's Most Famous Towns Becomes First in the Nation to Adopt Approval Voting 2018-11-07 at the Wayback Machine, accessed November 7, 2018
  9. ^ Moen, Mike (2020-06-10). "Fargo Becomes First U.S. City to Try Approval Voting". Public News Service. Retrieved 2020-12-03.
  10. ^ Piper, Kelsey (2018-11-15). "This city just approved a new election system never tried before in America". Vox. Retrieved 2020-07-08.
  11. ^ Amundson, Barry (Jun 9, 2020). "Strand and Preston emerge as leaders in Fargo City Commission race". INFORUM. from the original on 2020-06-10. Retrieved 2020-07-08.
  12. ^ "Fargo's First Approval Voting Election: Results and Voter Experience". The Center for Election Science. 2020-06-17. Retrieved 2020-07-08.
  13. ^ Nagel, Jack H. (2007). "The Burr Dilemma in Approval Voting". The Journal of Politics. 69 (1): 43–58. doi:10.1111/j.1468-2508.2007.00493.x. ISSN 0022-3816. S2CID 154179804.
  14. ^ RCV for Colorado. "Approval Voting Case Study". Google Docs. from the original on 2021-11-24. Retrieved 2021-03-04.
  15. ^ "Guest opinion: Emma Donahue and Linda S. Templin: Ballot issue 2E just makes sense - Ranked Choice Voting for Colorado". RCV for Colorado. from the original on 2020-11-30. Retrieved 2021-03-04. Triton Polling called Fargo voters and found that a significant number had gamed that voting method by bullet voting, just like the experts said they would.
  16. ^ Hamlin, Aaron (2022-06-16). "Fargo's Second Approval Voting Election Runs Smoothly". The Center for Election Science. Retrieved 2022-07-06.
  17. ^ "St. Louis Voters Approve Nonpartisan Elections". U.S. News & World Report. 2020-11-04. from the original on 2021-06-14. Retrieved 2020-12-03.
  18. ^ Clancy, Sam (2021-03-02). "Tishaura Jones, Cara Spencer advance to general election in race for St. Louis Mayor". KSDK. St. Louis, MO. Retrieved 2024-05-22.
  19. ^ Nelson, Alisa (2023-05-04). "Should Missouri ban ranked choice and approval voting?". Missourinet. Retrieved 2024-01-23.
  20. ^ es_admin (2024-04-19). "CES Urges Missouri Legislature to Oppose HJR 104, Which Aims to Suppress Voter Voices by Prohibiting Approval Voting and RCV". The Center for Election Science. Retrieved 2024-04-21.
  21. ^ "Bill tracking in Missouri - HJR 104 (2024 legislative session) - FastDemocracy". fastdemocracy.com. Retrieved 2024-04-21.
  22. ^ Carvel, Tasha (2023-04-19). "Fargo approval voting survives after Senate fails to override Burgum veto of ban". The Mighty 790 KFGO. Fargo, ND. Retrieved 2024-05-22.
  23. ^ "Latvia - How to vote". European elections 2024: all you need to know. Retrieved 2024-03-28.
  24. ^ Brams, Steven J.; Fishburn, Peter C. (2007), Approval Voting, Springer-Verlag, p. xv, ISBN 978-0-387-49895-9
  25. ^ Brams, Steven; Fishburn, Peter (1978). "Approval Voting". American Political Science Review. 72 (3): 831–847. doi:10.2307/1955105. JSTOR 1955105. S2CID 251092061.
  26. ^ Colomer, Josep M.; McLean, Iain (1998). "Electing Popes: Approval Balloting and Qualified-Majority Rule". The Journal of Interdisciplinary History. 29 (1): 1–22. doi:10.1162/002219598551616. JSTOR 205972. S2CID 145296691.
  27. ^ Lines, Marji (1986). "Approval Voting and Strategy Analysis: A Venetian Example". Theory and Decision. 20 (2): 155–172. doi:10.1007/BF00135090. S2CID 121512308.
  28. ^ Mowbray, Miranda; Gollmann, Dieter (July 2007). Electing the Doge of Venice: analysis of a 13th Century protocol (PDF). IEEE Computer Security Foundations Symposium. Venice, Italy. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  29. ^ Brams, Steven J. (April 1, 2006). (PDF) (Speech). Presidential Address to Public Choice Society. New Orleans, Louisiana. Archived from the original (PDF) on May 31, 2010. Retrieved May 8, 2010.
  30. ^ (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on February 27, 2008. Retrieved November 30, 2007.
  31. ^ Tharoor, Shashi (October 21, 2016). . OPEN Magazine. Archived from the original on July 21, 2019. Retrieved March 6, 2019.
  32. ^ Mavrogordatos, George Th. (1983). Stillborn Republic: Social Coalitions and Party Strategies in Greece 1922–1936. University of California Press. pp. 351–352.
  33. ^ Peralta, Sal (June 17, 2016). "Following tense primary, Independent Party plans presidential preference vote (OPINION)". The Oregonian. Retrieved June 26, 2018.
  34. ^ Radnovich, Connor (April 21, 2018). "Independent Party's internal conflict highlighted in Oregon governor race". Statesman Journal. Retrieved June 26, 2018.
  35. ^ Richie, Rob (December 14, 2016). "New Lessons from Problems with Approval Voting in Practice". FairVote.
  36. ^ "STAR VOTING ANNOUNCEMENT". Independent Party of Oregon. Salem. 2020-04-07. Retrieved 2020-04-11.
  37. ^ "Independent Party of Oregon to utilize STAR system for primary". Herald and News. Apr 8, 2020. Retrieved 2020-04-10.
  38. ^ Covich, Skylar. . American Solidarity Party. Archived from the original on June 22, 2018. Retrieved June 21, 2018.
  39. ^ "Platform". Green Party of Texas. Retrieved January 31, 2017. We support switching to a preferential voting method, such as approval voting.
  40. ^ . Green Party of Texas. Archived from the original on January 29, 2017. Retrieved January 31, 2017. The Co-Chair, Treasurer, and Secretary positions shall be filled by using approval voting.
  41. ^ . Ohio Green Party. Archived from the original on February 26, 2021. Retrieved January 31, 2017. We have agreed to use "approval voting" as opposed to "instant runoff voting" to make the Ohio Green Party choice for president
  42. ^ "MEETING MINUTES LIBERTARIAN NATIONAL COMMITTEE" (PDF). October 4, 2020. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09. VOTING METHOD: Approval Voting per OpaVote. Vote for as many candidates as desired.
  43. ^ . Libertarian Party of Texas. Archived from the original on January 30, 2017. Retrieved January 31, 2017. We also believe that all races should be decided by Approval Voting
  44. ^ "Document:Colorado State Party Bylaws 2021". LPedia. Retrieved 2022-09-24. For any partisan offices, Convention Delegates shall vote by approval voting
  45. ^ "Colorado Convention 2018". LPedia. Retrieved 2022-09-24. All candidates were selected by approval voting via standing vote.
  46. ^ "Bylaws". Arizona Libertarian Party. Retrieved 2022-09-24. The remaining Delegates … shall be elected by approval voting … should there be more Delegate Candidates than allotted seats.
  47. ^ "Rules of the Libertarian Party" (PDF). Libertarian Party of New York. November 7, 2021. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09. All elections shall be held with approval voting
  48. ^ [Statutes of the city association - Alliance 90/The Greens Munich-City District Association] (in German). 2017-01-18. Archived from the original on 2017-01-18. Retrieved 2023-03-05. Delegierte für Bundes, Landes- und Bezirksversammlungen werden per Zustimmungsblockwahl gewählt. Jede*r Stimmberechtigte hat so viele Stimmen, wie Bewerber*innen zur Wahl stehen, und kann jeder*m Bewerber*in eine oder keine Stimme geben.
  49. ^ "Jednací řád celostátního fóra". Pirati.CZ (in Czech). Retrieved 2021-11-16.
  50. ^ "Bundesparteitag 2010.1/Geschäftsordnung" (in German). German Pirate Party. Retrieved June 24, 2018.
  51. ^ . The Center for Election Science. Archived from the original on 2019-02-19. Retrieved 2022-09-24.
  52. ^ Hu, Xingwei; Shapley, Lloyd S. (2003). "On Authority Distributions in Organizations". Games and Economic Behavior. 45 (1): 132–170. doi:10.1016/S0899-8256(03)00130-1.
  53. ^ "Statutes of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare" (PDF). Society for Social Choice and Welfare. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09. Retrieved January 28, 2020.
  54. ^ "MAA Bylaws". Mathematical Association of America. August 7, 2010. Retrieved November 6, 2014.
  55. ^ "2015 American Mathematical Society Elections" (PDF). American Mathematical Society. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09. Retrieved August 19, 2015.
  56. ^ "Constitution of the Institute for Operations Research and the Management Sciences" (PDF). Institute for Operations Research and the Management Sciences. August 2017. p. 7. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  57. ^ "Bylaws of the American Statistical Association" (PDF). American Statistical Association. September 19, 2018. Retrieved January 28, 2020.
  58. ^ Brams, Steven J.; Fishburn, Peter C. (2010). "Going from Theory to Practice: The Mixed Success of Approval Voting". In Laslier, Jean-François; Sanver, M. Remzi (eds.). Handbook on Approval Voting. Studies in Choice and Welfare. Springer Berlin Heidelberg. pp. 19–37. doi:10.1007/978-3-642-02839-7_3. ISBN 9783642028380.
  59. ^ a b Brams & Fishburn 1983, p. 29.
  60. ^ a b c Niemi, R. G. (1984). "The Problem of Strategic Behavior under Approval Voting". American Political Science Review. 78 (4): 952–958. doi:10.2307/1955800. JSTOR 1955800. S2CID 146976380.
  61. ^ Yilmaz, M. R. (1999). "Can we improve upon approval voting?". European Journal of Political Economy. 15 (1): 89–100. doi:10.1016/S0176-2680(98)00043-3.
  62. ^ Saari, Donald G.; Van Newenhizen, Jill (2004). "The problem of indeterminancy in approval, multiple, and truncated voting systems". Public Choice. 59 (2): 101–120. doi:10.1007/BF00054447. JSTOR 30024954. S2CID 154705078.
  63. ^ Saari, Donald G.; Van Newenhizen, Jill (2004). "Is approval voting an 'unmitigated evil?' A response to Brams, Fishburn, and Merrill". Public Choice. 59 (2): 133–147. doi:10.1007/BF00054449. JSTOR 30024956. S2CID 154007278.
  64. ^ Brams & Fishburn 1983, p. 31.
  65. ^ Brams & Fishburn 1983, p. 38.
  66. ^ Brams & Fishburn 1983, p. 16–17.
  67. ^ Brams, S. J.; Remzi Sanver, M. (2005). "Critical strategies under approval voting: Who gets ruled in and ruled out". Electoral Studies. 25 (2): 287–305. doi:10.1016/j.electstud.2005.05.007.
  68. ^ Myerson, R.; Weber, R. J. (1993). "A theory of Voting Equilibria" (PDF). American Political Science Review. 87 (1): 102–114. doi:10.2307/2938959. hdl:10419/221141. JSTOR 2938959. S2CID 143828854. Archived (PDF) from the original on 2022-10-09.
  69. ^ Dutta, B; De Sinopoli, F.; Laslier, J.-F. (2006). "Approval voting: three examples". International Journal of Game Theory. 35: 27–38. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.365.8090. doi:10.1007/s00182-006-0053-2. S2CID 801286.
  70. ^ Brams & Fishburn 1983, p. 85.
  71. ^ Laslier, J.-F. (2009). "The Leader rule: a model of strategic approval voting in a large electorate". Journal of Theoretical Politics. 21 (1): 113–136. doi:10.1177/0951629808097286. S2CID 153790214.
  72. ^ Brams & Fishburn 1983, p. 74, 81.
  73. ^ Laslier, J.-F. (2006) "Strategic approval voting in a large electorate," IDEP Working Papers No. 405 (Marseille, France: Institut D'Economie Publique)

Sources edit

  • Brams, Steven J.; Fishburn, Peter C. (1983). Approval Voting. Boston: Birkhäuser. ISBN 3764331240.

External links edit

  • Approval Voting Article by The Center for Election Science
  • Could Approval Voting Prevent Electoral Disaster? Video by Big Think
  • Approval Voting on Dichotomous Preferences Article by Marc Vorsatz.
  • Scoring Rules on Dichotomous Preferences Article by Marc Vorsatz.
  • The Arithmetic of Voting article by Guy Ottewell
  • Critical Strategies Under Approval Voting: Who Gets Ruled In And Ruled Out Article by Steven J. Brams and M. Remzi Sanver.
  • Quick and Easy Voting for Normal People YouTube video

approval, voting, electoral, system, which, voters, select, number, candidates, instead, selecting, only, approval, ballot, voter, select, number, candidates, contents, description, effect, elections, operational, impacts, usage, current, history, political, o. Approval voting is an electoral system in which voters can select any number of candidates instead of selecting only one On an approval ballot the voter can select any number of candidates Contents 1 Description 2 Effect on elections 2 1 Operational impacts 3 Usage 3 1 Current 3 2 History 3 3 Political organizations and jurisdictions 3 4 Other organizations 4 Strategic voting 4 1 Overview 4 2 Sincere voting 4 2 1 Examples 4 3 Sincere strategy with ordinal preferences 4 3 1 Dichotomous preferences 4 3 2 Approval threshold 4 4 Strategy with cardinal utilities 4 5 Strategy examples 4 6 Dichotomous cutoff 5 Compliance with voting system criteria 6 See also 7 Notes 8 References 8 1 Sources 9 External linksDescription editApproval voting ballots show a list of all the candidates running and each voter indicates support for as many candidates as they see fit Final tallies show how many votes each candidate received and the winner is the candidate with the most support Effect on elections editApproval voting advocates Steven Brams and Dudley R Herschbach predict that Approval should increase voter participation prevent minor party candidates from being spoilers and reduce negative campaigning 1 One study showed that Approval would not have chosen the same two winners as plurality voting Chirac and Le Pen in the first round of the 2002 French presidential election it instead would have chosen Chirac and Jospin as the top two candidates to proceed to the runoff In the actual election Le Pen lost by an overwhelming margin in the runoff 82 2 to 17 8 a sign that the true top two candidates had not been found In the approval voting survey primary Chirac took first place with 36 7 compared to Jospin at 32 9 Le Pen in that study received 25 1 and so would not have made the cut to the second round In the real primary election the top three were Chirac 19 9 Le Pen 16 9 and Jospin 16 2 2 A study of various evaluative voting methods Approval and score voting during the 2012 French presidential election showed that unifying candidates tended to do better and polarizing candidates did worse as compared to under plurality voting 3 A generalized version of the Burr dilemma applies to Approval when two candidates are appealing to the same subset of voters Although Approval differs from the voting system used in the Burr dilemma Approval can still leave candidates and voters with the generalized dilemma of whether to compete or cooperate 4 5 But Approval satisfies the favorite betrayal criterion which means that it is always safe for a voter to give their true favorite maximum support While in the modern era there have been relatively few competitive Approval elections where tactical voting is more likely Brams argues that Approval usually elects Condorcet winners in practice 6 7 Operational impacts edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed June 2019 Learn how and when to remove this message Simple to tally Approval ballots can be counted by some existing machines designed for plurality elections as ballots are cast so that final tallies are immediately available after the election with relatively few if any upgrades to equipment Just one round Approval can remove the need for multiple rounds of voting such as a primary or a run off simplifying the election process Avoids Overvotes Approval voting does not have the notion of overvotes where voting for one more than allowed will cancel the entire opportunity to vote In plurality elections overvotes have to be reviewed and resolved if possible while in approval voting no time is wasted on this activity Usage editCurrent edit In 2018 Fargo North Dakota passed a local ballot initiative adopting Approval for the city s local elections becoming the first United States city and jurisdiction to adopt Approval 8 9 Previously in 2015 a Fargo city commissioner election had suffered from six way vote splitting resulting in a candidate winning with an unconvincing 22 plurality of the vote 10 The first election was held June 9 2020 selecting two city commissioners from seven candidates on the ballot 11 Both winners received over 50 approval with an average 2 3 approvals per ballot and 62 of voters supported the change to Approval in a poll 12 A poll by opponents of Approval was conducted to test whether voters had in fact voted strategically according to the Burr dilemma 13 They found that 30 of voters who bullet voted did so for strategic reasons while 57 did so because it was their sincere opinion 14 15 Fargo s second Approval election took place in June 2022 for mayor and city commission The incumbent mayor was re elected from a field of 7 candidates with an estimated 65 approval with voters expressing 1 6 approvals per ballot and the two commissioners were elected from a field of 15 candidates with 3 1 approvals per ballot 16 In November 2020 St Louis Missouri passed Proposition D with 70 voting to authorize a variant of Approval unified primary for municipal offices 17 The first St Louis approval primary was held on March 2nd 2021 and saw Tishaura Jones and Cara Spencer move on to the general with 57 and 46 support Lewis Reed and Andrew Jones were eliminated with 39 and 14 support resulting in an average of 1 6 candidates supported by each voter in the 4 person race 18 In February 2024 Ben Baker introduced legislation to ban approval and ranked choice voting state wide 19 20 It passed in the House on Apr 15 2024 21 In a similar move the North Dakota legislature passed a bill which intended to ban approval voting The bill was vetoed by governor Doug Burgum citing the importance of home rule and allowing citizens control over their local government The legislature attempted to overrule the veto and failed 22 The Latvian parliament uses approval voting within open list proportional representation 23 History edit nbsp Rows of secret approval vote boxes from early 1900s Greece where the voter drops a marble to the right or left of the box through a tube one for each candidate standing Robert J Weber coined the term Approval Voting in 1971 24 It was more fully published in 1978 by political scientist Steven Brams and mathematician Peter Fishburn 25 Historically several voting methods that incorporate aspects of Approval have been used Approval was used for papal conclaves between 1294 and 1621 with an average of about forty cardinals engaging in repeated rounds of voting until one candidate was listed on at least two thirds of ballots 26 In the 13th through 18th centuries the Republic of Venice elected the Doge of Venice using a multi stage process that featured random selection and voting that allowed approval of multiple candidates and required a supermajority 27 28 According to Steven J Brams Approval was used for unspecified elections in 19th century England 29 The selection of the Secretary General of the United Nations has involved straw poll rounds of approval polling to help discover and build a consensus before a formal vote is held in the Security Council 30 The United Nations Secretary General selection 2006 indicated that South Korean Foreign Minister Ban Ki moon was the only candidate to be acceptable to all five permanent members of the Security Council which led to the withdrawal of India s Shashi Tharoor who had the highest overall approval rate 31 Approval was used in Greek legislative elections from 1864 to 1923 when it was replaced with proportional representation 32 Sequential proportional approval voting was used in Swedish elections in the early 20th century prior to being replaced by party list proportional representation Political organizations and jurisdictions edit Approval has been used in privately administered nomination contests by the Independent Party of Oregon in 2011 2012 2014 and 2016 Oregon is a fusion voting state and the party has cross nominated legislators and statewide officeholders using this method its 2016 presidential preference primary did not identify a potential nominee due to no candidate earning more than 32 support 33 34 35 The party switched to using STAR voting in 2020 36 37 It is also used in internal elections by the American Solidarity Party 38 the Green Parties of Texas 39 40 and Ohio 41 the Libertarian National Committee 42 the Libertarian parties of Texas 43 Colorado 44 45 Arizona 46 and New York 47 Alliance 90 The Greens in Germany 48 and the Czech 49 and German Pirate Party 50 51 Other organizations edit The idea of approval was adopted by X Hu and Lloyd Shapley in 2003 in studying authority distribution in organizations 52 Approval has been adopted by several societies the Society for Social Choice and Welfare 1992 53 Mathematical Association of America 1986 54 the American Mathematical Society 55 the Institute of Management Sciences 1987 now the Institute for Operations Research and the Management Sciences 56 the American Statistical Association 1987 57 and the Institute of Electrical and Electronics Engineers 1987 The IEEE board in 2002 rescinded its decision to use Approval IEEE Executive Director Daniel J Senese stated that Approval was abandoned because few of our members were using it and it was felt that it was no longer needed 7 It is worth noting that most IEEE elections had only two candidates listed on the ballot Because none of these associations report results to their members and the public it is difficult to evaluate Senese s claim and whether it is also true of other associations Steven Brams analysis of the 5 candidate 1987 Mathematical Association of America presidential election shows that 79 of voters cast a ballot for one candidate 16 for 2 candidates 5 for 3 and 1 for 4 with the winner earning the approval of 1 267 32 of 3 924 voters 7 58 Approval also can be used in social scenarios as a fairer system compared to a first past the post equivalent being able to avoid a spoiler effect while still being very quick to calculate Strategic voting editSee also Tactical voting Approval voting Overview edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed June 2019 Learn how and when to remove this message Approval voting allows voters to select all the candidates whom they consider to be reasonable choices Strategic Approval differs from ranked voting aka preferential voting methods where voters might reverse the preference order of two options which if done on a larger scale can cause an unpopular candidate to win Strategic Approval with more than two options involves the voter changing their approval threshold The voter decides which options to give the same rating even if they were to have a preference order between them This leaves a tactical concern any voter has for approving their second favorite candidate in the case that there are three or more candidates Approving their second favorite means the voter harms their favorite candidate s chance to win Not approving their second favorite means the voter helps the candidate they least desire to beat their second favorite and perhaps win Approval allows for bullet voting and compromising while it is immune to push over and burying Bullet voting occurs when a voter approves only candidate a instead of both a and b for the reason that voting for b can cause a to lose The voter would be satisfied with either a or b but has a moderate preference for a Were b to win this hypothetical voter would still be satisfied If supporters of both a and b do this it could cause candidate c to win This creates the chicken dilemma as supporters of a and b are playing chicken as to which will stop strategic voting first before both of these candidates lose Compromising occurs when a voter approves an additional candidate who is otherwise considered unacceptable to the voter to prevent an even worse alternative from winning Sincere voting edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed June 2019 Learn how and when to remove this message Approval experts describe sincere votes as those that directly reflect the true preferences of a voter i e that do not report preferences falsely 59 They also give a specific definition of a sincere approval vote in terms of the voter s ordinal preferences as being any vote that if it votes for one candidate it also votes for any more preferred candidate This definition allows a sincere vote to treat strictly preferred candidates the same ensuring that every voter has at least one sincere vote The definition also allows a sincere vote to treat equally preferred candidates differently When there are two or more candidates every voter has at least three sincere approval votes to choose from Two of those sincere approval votes do not distinguish between any of the candidates vote for none of the candidates and vote for all of the candidates When there are three or more candidates every voter has more than one sincere approval vote that distinguishes between the candidates Examples edit Based on the definition above if there are four candidates A B C and D and a voter has a strict preference order preferring A to B to C to D then the following are the voter s possible sincere approval votes vote for A B C and D vote for A B and C vote for A and B vote for A vote for no candidates If the voter instead equally prefers B and C while A is still the most preferred candidate and D is the least preferred candidate then all of the above votes are sincere and the following combination is also a sincere vote vote for A and C The decision between the above ballots is equivalent to deciding an arbitrary approval cutoff All candidates preferred to the cutoff are approved all candidates less preferred are not approved and any candidates equal to the cutoff may be approved or not arbitrarily Sincere strategy with ordinal preferences edit A sincere voter with multiple options for voting sincerely still has to choose which sincere vote to use Voting strategy is a way to make that choice in which case strategic Approval includes sincere voting rather than being an alternative to it 60 This differs from other voting systems that typically have a unique sincere vote for a voter When there are three or more candidates the winner of an Approval election can change depending on which sincere votes are used In some cases Approval can sincerely elect any one of the candidates including a Condorcet winner and a Condorcet loser without the voter preferences changing To the extent that electing a Condorcet winner and not electing a Condorcet loser is considered desirable outcomes for a voting system Approval can be considered vulnerable to sincere strategic voting 61 In one sense conditions where this can happen are robust and are not isolated cases 62 On the other hand the variety of possible outcomes has also been portrayed as a virtue of Approval representing the flexibility and responsiveness of Approval not just to voter ordinal preferences but cardinal utilities as well 63 Dichotomous preferences edit Approval avoids the issue of multiple sincere votes in special cases when voters have dichotomous preferences For a voter with dichotomous preferences Approval is strategy proof also known as strategy free 64 When all voters have dichotomous preferences and vote the sincere strategy proof vote Approval is guaranteed to elect the Condorcet winner if one exists 65 However having dichotomous preferences when there are three or more candidates is not typical It is an unlikely situation for all voters to have dichotomous preferences when there are more than a few voters 60 Having dichotomous preferences means that a voter has bi level preferences for the candidates All of the candidates are divided into two groups such that the voter is indifferent between any two candidates in the same group and any candidate in the top level group is preferred to any candidate in the bottom level group 66 A voter that has strict preferences between three candidates prefers A to B and B to C does not have dichotomous preferences Being strategy proof for a voter means that there is a unique way for the voter to vote that is a strategically best way to vote regardless of how others vote In Approval the strategy proof vote if it exists is a sincere vote 59 Approval threshold edit Another way to deal with multiple sincere votes is to augment the ordinal preference model with an approval or acceptance threshold An approval threshold divides all of the candidates into two sets those the voter approves of and those the voter does not approve of A voter can approve of more than one candidate and still prefer one approved candidate to another approved candidate Acceptance thresholds are similar With such a threshold a voter simply votes for every candidate that meets or exceeds the threshold 60 With threshold voting it is still possible to not elect the Condorcet winner and instead elect the Condorcet loser when they both exist However according to Steven Brams this represents a strength rather than a weakness of Approval Without providing specifics he argues that the pragmatic judgements of voters about which candidates are acceptable should take precedence over the Condorcet criterion and other social choice criteria 67 Strategy with cardinal utilities edit Voting strategy under approval is guided by two competing features of Approval On the one hand Approval fails the later no harm criterion so voting for a candidate can cause that candidate to win instead of a candidate more preferred by that voter On the other hand Approval satisfies the monotonicity criterion so not voting for a candidate can never help that candidate win but can cause that candidate to lose to a less preferred candidate Either way the voter can risk getting a less preferred election winner A voter can balance the risk benefit trade offs by considering the voter s cardinal utilities particularly via the von Neumann Morgenstern utility theorem and the probabilities of how others vote A rational voter model described by Myerson and Weber specifies an Approval strategy that votes for those candidates that have a positive prospective rating 68 This strategy is optimal in the sense that it maximizes the voter s expected utility subject to the constraints of the model and provided the number of other voters is sufficiently large An optimal approval vote always votes for the most preferred candidate and not for the least preferred candidate However an optimal vote can require voting for a candidate and not voting for a more preferred candidate if there 4 candidates or more 69 Other strategies are also available and coincide with the optimal strategy in special situations For example Vote for the candidates that have above average utility This strategy coincides with the optimal strategy if the voter thinks that all pairwise ties are equally likely 70 Vote for any candidate that is more preferred than the expected winner and also vote for the expected winner if the expected winner is more preferred than the expected runner up This strategy coincides with the optimal strategy if there are three or fewer candidates or if the pivot probability for a tie between the expected winner and expected runner up is sufficiently large compared to the other pivot probabilities This strategy if used by all voters implies at equilibrium the election of the Condorcet winner whenever it exists 71 Vote for the most preferred candidate only This strategy coincides with the optimal strategy when there is only one candidate with a positive prospective rating Another strategy is to vote for the top half of the candidates the candidates that have an above median utility When the voter thinks that others are balancing their votes randomly and evenly the strategy maximizes the voter s power or efficacy meaning that it maximizes the probability that the voter will make a difference in deciding which candidate wins 72 Optimal strategic Approval fails to satisfy the Condorcet criterion and can elect a Condorcet loser Strategic Approval can guarantee electing the Condorcet winner in some special circumstances For example if all voters are rational and cast a strategically optimal vote based on a common knowledge of how all the other voters vote except for small probability statistically independent errors in recording the votes then the winner will be the Condorcet winner if one exists 73 Strategy examples edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed June 2019 Learn how and when to remove this message In the example election described here assume that the voters in each faction share the following von Neumann Morgenstern utilities fitted to the interval between 0 and 100 The utilities are consistent with the rankings given earlier and reflect a strong preference each faction has for choosing its city compared to weaker preferences for other factors such as the distance to the other cities Voter utilities for each candidate city Fraction of voters living close to Candidates Average Memphis Nashville Chattanooga Knoxville Memphis 42 100 15 10 0 31 25 Nashville 26 0 100 20 15 33 75 Chattanooga 15 0 15 100 35 37 5 Knoxville 17 0 15 40 100 38 75 Using these utilities voters choose their optimal strategic votes based on what they think the various pivot probabilities are for pairwise ties In each of the scenarios summarized below all voters share a common set of pivot probabilities Approval Voting results for scenarios using optimal strategic voting Strategy scenario Winner Runner up Candidate vote totals Memphis Nashville Chattanooga Knoxville Zero info Memphis Chattanooga 42 26 32 17 Memphis leading Chattanooga Three way tie 42 58 58 58 Chattanooga leading Knoxville Chattanooga Nashville 42 68 83 17 Chattanooga leading Nashville Nashville Memphis 42 68 32 17 Nashville leading Memphis Nashville Memphis 42 58 32 32 In the first scenario voters all choose their votes based on the assumption that all pairwise ties are equally likely As a result they vote for any candidate with an above average utility Most voters vote for only their first choice Only the Knoxville faction also votes for its second choice Chattanooga As a result the winner is Memphis the Condorcet loser with Chattanooga coming in second place In this scenario the winner has minority approval more voters disapproved than approved and all the others had even less support reflecting the position that no choice gave an above average utility to a majority of voters In the second scenario all of the voters expect that Memphis is the likely winner that Chattanooga is the likely runner up and that the pivot probability for a Memphis Chattanooga tie is much larger than the pivot probabilities of any other pair wise ties As a result each voter votes for any candidate they prefer more than the leading candidate and also vote for the leading candidate if they prefer that candidate more than the expected runner up Each remaining scenario follows a similar pattern of expectations and voting strategies In the second scenario there is a three way tie for first place This happens because the expected winner Memphis was the Condorcet loser and was also ranked last by any voter that did not rank it first Only in the last scenario does the actual winner and runner up match the expected winner and runner up As a result this can be considered a stable strategic voting scenario In the language of game theory this is an equilibrium In this scenario the winner is also the Condorcet winner Dichotomous cutoff edit This section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed June 2019 Learn how and when to remove this message As this voting method is cardinal rather than ordinal it is possible to model voters in a way that does not simplify to an ordinal method Modelling voters with a dichotomous cutoff assumes a voter has an immovable approval cutoff while having meaningful cardinal preferences This means that rather than voting for their top 3 candidates or all candidates above the average approval which may result in their vote changing if one candidate drops out resulting in a system that does not satisfy IIA they instead vote for all candidates above a certain approval cutoff that they have decided This cutoff does not change regardless of which and how many candidates are running so when all available alternatives are either above or below the cutoff the voter votes for all or none of the candidates despite preferring some over others This could be imagined to reflect a case where many voters become disenfranchised and apathetic if they see no candidates they approve of In a case such as this many voters may have an internal cutoff and would not simply vote for their top 3 or the above average candidates although that is not to say that it is necessarily entirely immovable For example in this scenario voters are voting for candidates with approval above 50 bold signifies that the voters voted for the candidate Proportion of electorate Approval of Candidate A Approval of Candidate B Approval of Candidate C Approval of Candidate D Average approval 25 90 60 40 10 50 35 10 90 60 40 50 30 40 10 90 60 50 10 60 40 10 90 50 C wins with 65 of the voters approval beating B with 60 D with 40 and A with 35 If voters threshold for receiving a vote is that the candidate has an above average approval or they vote for their two most approved of candidates this is not a dichotomous cutoff as this can change if candidates drop out On the other hand if voters threshold for receiving a vote is fixed say 50 this is a dichotomous cutoff and satisfies IIA as shown below A drops out candidates voting for above average approval Proportion of electorate Approval of Candidate A Approval of Candidate B Approval of Candidate C Approval of Candidate D Average approval 25 60 40 10 37 35 90 60 40 63 30 10 90 60 53 10 40 10 90 47 B now wins with 60 beating C with 55 and D with 40 A drops out candidates voting for approval gt 50 Proportion of electorate Approval of Candidate A Approval of Candidate B Approval of Candidate C Approval of Candidate D Average approval 25 60 40 10 37 35 90 60 40 63 30 10 90 60 53 10 40 10 90 47 With dichotomous cutoff C still wins D drops out candidates voting for top 2 candidates Proportion of electorate Approval of Candidate A Approval of Candidate B Approval of Candidate C Approval of Candidate D Average approval 25 90 60 40 63 35 10 90 60 53 30 40 10 90 47 10 60 40 10 37 B now wins with 70 beating C and A with 65 D drops out candidates voting for approval gt 50 Proportion of electorate Approval of Candidate A Approval of Candidate B Approval of Candidate C Approval of Candidate D Average approval 25 90 60 40 63 35 10 90 60 53 30 40 10 90 47 10 60 40 10 37 With dichotomous cutoff C still wins Compliance with voting system criteria editThis section needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources in this section Unsourced material may be challenged and removed June 2019 Learn how and when to remove this message Most of the mathematical criteria by which voting systems are compared were formulated for voters with ordinal preferences In this case approval voting requires voters to make an additional decision of where to put their approval cutoff see examples above Depending on how this decision is made Approval satisfies different sets of criteria There is no ultimate authority on which criteria should be considered but the following are criteria that many voting theorists accept and consider desirable Unrestricted domain A voter may have any preference ordering among the alternatives Non dictatorship There does not exist a single voter whose preference for the alternatives always determines the outcome regardless of other voters preferences Pareto efficiency If every voter prefers candidate A to all other candidates then A must be elected from Arrow s impossibility theorem Majority criterion If there exists a majority that ranks or rates a single candidate higher than all other candidates does that candidate always win Monotonicity criterion Is it impossible to cause a winning candidate to lose by ranking that candidate higher or to cause a losing candidate to win by ranking that candidate lower Consistency criterion If the electorate is divided in two and a choice wins in both parts does it always win overall Participation criterion Is voting honestly always better than not voting at all This is grouped with the distinct but similar Consistency Criterion in the table below a Condorcet criterion If a candidate beats every other candidate in pairwise comparison does that candidate always win This implies the majority criterion above Condorcet loser criterion If a candidate loses to every other candidate in pairwise comparison does that candidate always lose Independence of irrelevant alternatives Is the outcome the same after adding or removing non winning candidates Independence of clones criterion Is the outcome the same if candidates identical to existing candidates are added Reversal symmetry If individual preferences of each voter are inverted does the original winner never win Unrestricted domain Non dictatorship Pareto efficiency Majority Monotone Consistency amp Participation Condorcet Condorcet loser IIA Clone independence Reversal symmetry Cardinal preferences Zero information rational voters Yes Yes No b No Yes Yes No No No No Yes Imperfect information rational voters Yes Yes No No Yes Yes No No No No Yes Strong Nash equilibrium Perfect information rational voters and perfect strategy Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes No Yes No c No Yes Yes Absolute cutoff Yes No d Yes e No Yes Yes No No Yes f Yes Yes Dichotomous preferences Rational voters No g Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Yes Approval satisfies the mutual majority criterion and Smith criterion when voters preferences are dichotomous this is because the winner will be someone that the most voters prefer above all others or that ties with other candidates but the group of tied candidates is preferred by more voters than any candidate not in the group See also edit nbsp Politics portalSome variants and generalizations of approval voting are Multiwinner approval voting multiple candidates may be elected instead of just one Fractional approval voting the election outcome is a distribution assigning a fraction to each candidate Score voting also called range voting is simply approval voting where voters can give a wider range of scores than 0 or 1 e g 0 5 or 0 7 Combined approval voting form of score voting with three levels that uses a scale of 1 0 1 or 0 1 2 D21 Janecek method limited to two approval and one negative vote per voter Notes edit Consistency implies participation but not vice versa For example Score Voting complies with participation and consistency but median ratings satisfies participation and fails consistency When the criterion is failed the result is always a tie between the alternative preferred by all voters and one or more other alternatives The criterion can only be failed when the tied candidates are approved on every ballot cast in the election The probability of failing this criterion vanishes asymptotically as the number of voters grows If voters are forced to determine their approval cutoff without knowing the available alternatives prior to an election there can exist two alternatives for which one voter s preference determines the winner regardless of another voter s preference For example consider a cardinal scale from 0 to 1 with 0 5 as the cutoff The criterion is personal wealth for voter A and quality of drinking water for voter B There can exist two candidates such that voter A s cardinal preferences are 0 49 and 0 51 while voter B s preferences are 0 and 0 49 Voter A s preferences despite how trivial determine the outcome of the election regardless of voter B s preferences because voter B is forced to abstain even while having a stronger preference Pareto efficiency is implied by and is weaker than the combination of Monotonicity IIA and Non Imposition that every possible societal preference order should be achievable by some set of individual preference orders which is the case in all of these scenarios These three conditions were in fact specified in the original statement of Arrow s impossibility theorem The model assumes a voter has an immovable approval cutoff while also having meaningful cardinal preferences When all available alternatives are either above or below the cutoff the voter votes for all or none of the candidates despite preferring some over others In a dichotomous preference society voters do not have a preferred ordering for the alternatives such as A gt B gt C Each voter has a binary yes or no rating for any alternative while having no degree of preference among alternatives with either rating References edit Brams Steven J Herschbach Dudley R 2001 The Science of Elections Science 292 5521 1449 doi 10 1126 science 292 5521 1449 JSTOR 3083781 PMID 11379606 S2CID 28262658 Laslier Jean Francois Vander Straeten Karine April 2003 Approval Voting An Experiment during the French 2002 Presidential Election PDF p 6 Archived from the original PDF on May 7 2005 Retrieved July 8 2014 Baujard Antoinette Igersheim Herrade Lebon Isabelle Gavrel Frederic Laslier Jean Francois 2014 06 01 Who s favored by evaluative voting An experiment conducted during the 2012 French presidential election PDF Electoral Studies 34 131 145 doi 10 1016 j electstud 2013 11 003 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Nagel J H 2007 The Burr Dilemma in Approval Voting PDF The Journal of Politics 69 1 43 58 doi 10 1111 j 1468 2508 2007 00493 x S2CID 154179804 Archived from the original PDF on 2007 06 21 Retrieved 2007 06 06 Nagel J H 2006 A Strategic Problem in Approval Voting Mathematics and Democracy Studies in Choice and Welfare 133 150 doi 10 1007 3 540 35605 3 10 ISBN 978 3 540 35603 5 Brams Steven J 2008 Mathematics and Democracy Designing Better Voting and Fair Division Procedures Princeton University Press p 16 ISBN 9780691133218 a b c Brams Steven J Fishburn Peter C August 2003 Going from Theory to Practice The Mixed Success of Approval Voting PDF Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association American Political Science Association Archived from the original PDF on December 18 2018 Retrieved May 8 2010 One of America s Most Famous Towns Becomes First in the Nation to Adopt Approval Voting Archived 2018 11 07 at the Wayback Machine accessed November 7 2018 Moen Mike 2020 06 10 Fargo Becomes First U S City to Try Approval Voting Public News Service Retrieved 2020 12 03 Piper Kelsey 2018 11 15 This city just approved a new election system never tried before in America Vox Retrieved 2020 07 08 Amundson Barry Jun 9 2020 Strand and Preston emerge as leaders in Fargo City Commission race INFORUM Archived from the original on 2020 06 10 Retrieved 2020 07 08 Fargo s First Approval Voting Election Results and Voter Experience The Center for Election Science 2020 06 17 Retrieved 2020 07 08 Nagel Jack H 2007 The Burr Dilemma in Approval Voting The Journal of Politics 69 1 43 58 doi 10 1111 j 1468 2508 2007 00493 x ISSN 0022 3816 S2CID 154179804 RCV for Colorado Approval Voting Case Study Google Docs Archived from the original on 2021 11 24 Retrieved 2021 03 04 Guest opinion Emma Donahue and Linda S Templin Ballot issue 2E just makes sense Ranked Choice Voting for Colorado RCV for Colorado Archived from the original on 2020 11 30 Retrieved 2021 03 04 Triton Polling called Fargo voters and found that a significant number had gamed that voting method by bullet voting just like the experts said they would Hamlin Aaron 2022 06 16 Fargo s Second Approval Voting Election Runs Smoothly The Center for Election Science Retrieved 2022 07 06 St Louis Voters Approve Nonpartisan Elections U S News amp World Report 2020 11 04 Archived from the original on 2021 06 14 Retrieved 2020 12 03 Clancy Sam 2021 03 02 Tishaura Jones Cara Spencer advance to general election in race for St Louis Mayor KSDK St Louis MO Retrieved 2024 05 22 Nelson Alisa 2023 05 04 Should Missouri ban ranked choice and approval voting Missourinet Retrieved 2024 01 23 es admin 2024 04 19 CES Urges Missouri Legislature to Oppose HJR 104 Which Aims to Suppress Voter Voices by Prohibiting Approval Voting and RCV The Center for Election Science Retrieved 2024 04 21 Bill tracking in Missouri HJR 104 2024 legislative session FastDemocracy fastdemocracy com Retrieved 2024 04 21 Carvel Tasha 2023 04 19 Fargo approval voting survives after Senate fails to override Burgum veto of ban The Mighty 790 KFGO Fargo ND Retrieved 2024 05 22 Latvia How to vote European elections 2024 all you need to know Retrieved 2024 03 28 Brams Steven J Fishburn Peter C 2007 Approval Voting Springer Verlag p xv ISBN 978 0 387 49895 9 Brams Steven Fishburn Peter 1978 Approval Voting American Political Science Review 72 3 831 847 doi 10 2307 1955105 JSTOR 1955105 S2CID 251092061 Colomer Josep M McLean Iain 1998 Electing Popes Approval Balloting and Qualified Majority Rule The Journal of Interdisciplinary History 29 1 1 22 doi 10 1162 002219598551616 JSTOR 205972 S2CID 145296691 Lines Marji 1986 Approval Voting and Strategy Analysis A Venetian Example Theory and Decision 20 2 155 172 doi 10 1007 BF00135090 S2CID 121512308 Mowbray Miranda Gollmann Dieter July 2007 Electing the Doge of Venice analysis of a 13th Century protocol PDF IEEE Computer Security Foundations Symposium Venice Italy Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Brams Steven J April 1 2006 The Normative Turn in Public Choice PDF Speech Presidential Address to Public Choice Society New Orleans Louisiana Archived from the original PDF on May 31 2010 Retrieved May 8 2010 The Wisnumurti Guidelines for Selecting a Candidate for Secretary General PDF Archived from the original PDF on February 27 2008 Retrieved November 30 2007 Tharoor Shashi October 21 2016 The inside Story of How I Lost the Race for the UN Secretary General s Job in 2006 OPEN Magazine Archived from the original on July 21 2019 Retrieved March 6 2019 Mavrogordatos George Th 1983 Stillborn Republic Social Coalitions and Party Strategies in Greece 1922 1936 University of California Press pp 351 352 Peralta Sal June 17 2016 Following tense primary Independent Party plans presidential preference vote OPINION The Oregonian Retrieved June 26 2018 Radnovich Connor April 21 2018 Independent Party s internal conflict highlighted in Oregon governor race Statesman Journal Retrieved June 26 2018 Richie Rob December 14 2016 New Lessons from Problems with Approval Voting in Practice FairVote STAR VOTING ANNOUNCEMENT Independent Party of Oregon Salem 2020 04 07 Retrieved 2020 04 11 Independent Party of Oregon to utilize STAR system for primary Herald and News Apr 8 2020 Retrieved 2020 04 10 Covich Skylar Vice Chair s Remarks American Solidarity Party Archived from the original on June 22 2018 Retrieved June 21 2018 Platform Green Party of Texas Retrieved January 31 2017 We support switching to a preferential voting method such as approval voting By Laws Green Party of Texas Archived from the original on January 29 2017 Retrieved January 31 2017 The Co Chair Treasurer and Secretary positions shall be filled by using approval voting Ohio Green Party Presidential Nominating Convention Columbus Ohio Green Party Archived from the original on February 26 2021 Retrieved January 31 2017 We have agreed to use approval voting as opposed to instant runoff voting to make the Ohio Green Party choice for president MEETING MINUTES LIBERTARIAN NATIONAL COMMITTEE PDF October 4 2020 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 VOTING METHOD Approval Voting per OpaVote Vote for as many candidates as desired State Platform Libertarian Party of Texas Archived from the original on January 30 2017 Retrieved January 31 2017 We also believe that all races should be decided by Approval Voting Document Colorado State Party Bylaws 2021 LPedia Retrieved 2022 09 24 For any partisan offices Convention Delegates shall vote by approval voting Colorado Convention 2018 LPedia Retrieved 2022 09 24 All candidates were selected by approval voting via standing vote Bylaws Arizona Libertarian Party Retrieved 2022 09 24 The remaining Delegates shall be elected by approval voting should there be more Delegate Candidates than allotted seats Rules of the Libertarian Party PDF Libertarian Party of New York November 7 2021 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 All elections shall be held with approval voting Grune Munchen Satzung Statutes of the city association Alliance 90 The Greens Munich City District Association in German 2017 01 18 Archived from the original on 2017 01 18 Retrieved 2023 03 05 Delegierte fur Bundes Landes und Bezirksversammlungen werden per Zustimmungsblockwahl gewahlt Jede r Stimmberechtigte hat so viele Stimmen wie Bewerber innen zur Wahl stehen und kann jeder m Bewerber in eine oder keine Stimme geben Jednaci rad celostatniho fora Pirati CZ in Czech Retrieved 2021 11 16 Bundesparteitag 2010 1 Geschaftsordnung in German German Pirate Party Retrieved June 24 2018 Election Data from the German Pirate Party Piratenpartei The Center for Election Science Archived from the original on 2019 02 19 Retrieved 2022 09 24 Hu Xingwei Shapley Lloyd S 2003 On Authority Distributions in Organizations Games and Economic Behavior 45 1 132 170 doi 10 1016 S0899 8256 03 00130 1 Statutes of the Society for Social Choice and Welfare PDF Society for Social Choice and Welfare Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Retrieved January 28 2020 MAA Bylaws Mathematical Association of America August 7 2010 Retrieved November 6 2014 2015 American Mathematical Society Elections PDF American Mathematical Society Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Retrieved August 19 2015 Constitution of the Institute for Operations Research and the Management Sciences PDF Institute for Operations Research and the Management Sciences August 2017 p 7 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Bylaws of the American Statistical Association PDF American Statistical Association September 19 2018 Retrieved January 28 2020 Brams Steven J Fishburn Peter C 2010 Going from Theory to Practice The Mixed Success of Approval Voting In Laslier Jean Francois Sanver M Remzi eds Handbook on Approval Voting Studies in Choice and Welfare Springer Berlin Heidelberg pp 19 37 doi 10 1007 978 3 642 02839 7 3 ISBN 9783642028380 a b Brams amp Fishburn 1983 p 29 a b c Niemi R G 1984 The Problem of Strategic Behavior under Approval Voting American Political Science Review 78 4 952 958 doi 10 2307 1955800 JSTOR 1955800 S2CID 146976380 Yilmaz M R 1999 Can we improve upon approval voting European Journal of Political Economy 15 1 89 100 doi 10 1016 S0176 2680 98 00043 3 Saari Donald G Van Newenhizen Jill 2004 The problem of indeterminancy in approval multiple and truncated voting systems Public Choice 59 2 101 120 doi 10 1007 BF00054447 JSTOR 30024954 S2CID 154705078 Saari Donald G Van Newenhizen Jill 2004 Is approval voting an unmitigated evil A response to Brams Fishburn and Merrill Public Choice 59 2 133 147 doi 10 1007 BF00054449 JSTOR 30024956 S2CID 154007278 Brams amp Fishburn 1983 p 31 Brams amp Fishburn 1983 p 38 Brams amp Fishburn 1983 p 16 17 Brams S J Remzi Sanver M 2005 Critical strategies under approval voting Who gets ruled in and ruled out Electoral Studies 25 2 287 305 doi 10 1016 j electstud 2005 05 007 Myerson R Weber R J 1993 A theory of Voting Equilibria PDF American Political Science Review 87 1 102 114 doi 10 2307 2938959 hdl 10419 221141 JSTOR 2938959 S2CID 143828854 Archived PDF from the original on 2022 10 09 Dutta B De Sinopoli F Laslier J F 2006 Approval voting three examples International Journal of Game Theory 35 27 38 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 365 8090 doi 10 1007 s00182 006 0053 2 S2CID 801286 Brams amp Fishburn 1983 p 85 Laslier J F 2009 The Leader rule a model of strategic approval voting in a large electorate Journal of Theoretical Politics 21 1 113 136 doi 10 1177 0951629808097286 S2CID 153790214 Brams amp Fishburn 1983 p 74 81 Laslier J F 2006 Strategic approval voting in a large electorate IDEP Working Papers No 405 Marseille France Institut D Economie Publique Sources edit Brams Steven J Fishburn Peter C 1983 Approval Voting Boston Birkhauser ISBN 3764331240 External links edit nbsp Look up approval in Wiktionary the free dictionary Approval Voting Article by The Center for Election Science Could Approval Voting Prevent Electoral Disaster Video by Big Think Approval Voting on Dichotomous Preferences Article by Marc Vorsatz Scoring Rules on Dichotomous Preferences Article by Marc Vorsatz The Arithmetic of Voting article by Guy Ottewell Critical Strategies Under Approval Voting Who Gets Ruled In And Ruled Out Article by Steven J Brams and M Remzi Sanver Quick and Easy Voting for Normal People YouTube video Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Approval voting amp oldid 1225359970, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.