fbpx
Wikipedia

St. Petersburg paradox

The St. Petersburg paradox or St. Petersburg lottery[1] is a paradox involving the game of flipping a coin where the expected payoff of the theoretical lottery game approaches infinity but nevertheless seems to be worth only a very small amount to the participants. The St. Petersburg paradox is a situation where a naïve decision criterion that takes only the expected value into account predicts a course of action that presumably no actual person would be willing to take. Several resolutions to the paradox have been proposed, including the impossible amount of money a casino would need to continue the game indefinitely.

Portrait of Nicolas Bernoulli (1723)

The problem was invented by Nicolas Bernoulli,[2] who stated it in a letter to Pierre Raymond de Montmort on September 9, 1713.[3][4] However, the paradox takes its name from its analysis by Nicolas' cousin Daniel Bernoulli, one-time resident of Saint Petersburg, who in 1738 published his thoughts about the problem in the Commentaries of the Imperial Academy of Science of Saint Petersburg.[5]

The St. Petersburg game edit

A casino offers a game of chance for a single player in which a fair coin is tossed at each stage. The initial stake begins at 2 dollars and is doubled every time tails appears. The first time heads appears, the game ends and the player wins whatever is the current stake. Thus the player wins 2 dollars if heads appears on the first toss, 4 dollars if tails appears on the first toss and heads on the second, 8 dollars if tails appears on the first two tosses and heads on the third, and so on. Mathematically, the player wins   dollars, where   is the number of consecutive tails tosses.[5] What would be a fair price to pay the casino for entering the game?

To answer this, one needs to consider what would be the expected payout at each stage: with probability 1/2, the player wins 2 dollars; with probability 1/4 the player wins 4 dollars; with probability 1/8 the player wins 8 dollars, and so on. Assuming the game can continue as long as the coin toss results in tails and, in particular, that the casino has unlimited resources, the expected value is thus

 

This sum grows without bound so the expected win is an infinite amount of money.

The paradox edit

Considering nothing but the expected value of the net change in one's monetary wealth, one should therefore play the game at any price if offered the opportunity. Yet, Daniel Bernoulli, after describing the game with an initial stake of one ducat, stated, "Although the standard calculation shows that the value of [the player's] expectation is infinitely great, it has ... to be admitted that any fairly reasonable man would sell his chance, with great pleasure, for twenty ducats."[5] Robert Martin quotes Ian Hacking as saying, "Few of us would pay even $25 to enter such a game", and he says most commentators would agree.[6] The apparent paradox is the discrepancy between what people seem willing to pay to enter the game and the infinite expected value.[5]

Solutions edit

Several approaches have been proposed for solving the paradox.

Expected utility theory edit

The classical resolution of the paradox involved the explicit introduction of a utility function, an expected utility hypothesis, and the presumption of diminishing marginal utility of money.

Daniel Bernoulli;

The determination of the value of an item must not be based on the price, but rather on the utility it yields ... There is no doubt that a gain of one thousand ducats is more significant to the pauper than to a rich man though both gain the same amount.

A common utility model, suggested by Daniel Bernoulli, is the logarithmic function U(w) = ln(w) (known as log utility). It is a function of the gambler's total wealth w, and the concept of diminishing marginal utility of money is built into it. The expected utility hypothesis posits that a utility function exists that provides a good criterion for real people's behavior; i.e. a function that returns a positive or negative value indicating if the wager is a good gamble. For each possible event, the change in utility ln(wealth after the event) − ln(wealth before the event) will be weighted by the probability of that event occurring. Let c be the cost charged to enter the game. The expected incremental utility of the lottery now converges to a finite value:

 

This formula gives an implicit relationship between the gambler's wealth and how much he should be willing to pay (specifically, any c that gives a positive change in expected utility). For example, with natural log utility, a millionaire ($1,000,000) should be willing to pay up to $20.88, a person with $1,000 should pay up to $10.95, a person with $2 should borrow $1.35 and pay up to $3.35.

Before Daniel Bernoulli published, in 1728, a mathematician from Geneva, Gabriel Cramer, had already found parts of this idea (also motivated by the St. Petersburg paradox) in stating that

the mathematicians estimate money in proportion to its quantity, and men of good sense in proportion to the usage that they may make of it.

He demonstrated in a letter to Nicolas Bernoulli[7] that a square root function describing the diminishing marginal benefit of gains can resolve the problem. However, unlike Daniel Bernoulli, he did not consider the total wealth of a person, but only the gain by the lottery.

This solution by Cramer and Bernoulli, however, is not completely satisfying, as the lottery can easily be changed in a way such that the paradox reappears. To this aim, we just need to change the game so that it gives even more rapidly increasing payoffs. For any unbounded utility function, one can find a lottery that allows for a variant of the St. Petersburg paradox, as was first pointed out by Menger.[8]

Recently, expected utility theory has been extended to arrive at more behavioral decision models. In some of these new theories, as in cumulative prospect theory, the St. Petersburg paradox again appears in certain cases, even when the utility function is concave, but not if it is bounded.[9]

Probability weighting edit

Nicolas Bernoulli himself proposed an alternative idea for solving the paradox. He conjectured that people will neglect unlikely events.[4] Since in the St. Petersburg lottery only unlikely events yield the high prizes that lead to an infinite expected value, this could resolve the paradox. The idea of probability weighting resurfaced much later in the work on prospect theory by Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky. Paul Weirich similarly wrote that risk aversion could solve the paradox. Weirich went on to write that increasing the prize actually decreases the chance of someone paying to play the game, stating "there is some number of birds in hand worth more than any number of birds in the bush".[10][11] However, this has been rejected by some theorists because, as they point out, some people enjoy the risk of gambling and because it is illogical to assume that increasing the prize will lead to more risks.

Cumulative prospect theory is one popular generalization of expected utility theory that can predict many behavioral regularities.[12] However, the overweighting of small probability events introduced in cumulative prospect theory may restore the St. Petersburg paradox. Cumulative prospect theory avoids the St. Petersburg paradox only when the power coefficient of the utility function is lower than the power coefficient of the probability weighting function.[13] Intuitively, the utility function must not simply be concave, but it must be concave relative to the probability weighting function to avoid the St. Petersburg paradox. One can argue that the formulas for the prospect theory are obtained in the region of less than $400.[12] This is not applicable for infinitely increasing sums in the St. Petersburg paradox.

Finite St. Petersburg lotteries edit

The classical St. Petersburg game assumes that the casino or banker has infinite resources. This assumption has long been challenged as unrealistic.[14][15] Alexis Fontaine des Bertins pointed out in 1754 that the resources of any potential backer of the game are finite.[16] More importantly, the expected value of the game only grows logarithmically with the resources of the casino. As a result, the expected value of the game, even when played against a casino with the largest bankroll realistically conceivable, is quite modest. In 1777, Georges-Louis Leclerc, Comte de Buffon calculated that after 29 rounds of play there would not be enough money in the Kingdom of France to cover the bet.[17]

If the casino has finite resources, the game must end once those resources are exhausted.[15] Suppose the total resources (or maximum jackpot) of the casino are W dollars (more generally, W is measured in units of half the game's initial stake). Then the maximum number of times the casino can play before it no longer can fully cover the next bet is L = log2(W).[18][nb 1] Assuming the game ends when the casino can no longer cover the bet, the expected value E of the lottery then becomes:[18]

 

The following table shows the expected value E of the game with various potential bankers and their bankroll W:

Banker Bankroll Expected value
of one game
Millionaire $1,050,000 $20
Billionaire $1,075,000,000 $30
Elon Musk (Apr 2022)[19] $265,000,000,000 $38
U.S. GDP (2020)[20] $20.8 trillion $44
World GDP (2020)[20] $83.8 trillion $46
Billion-billionaire[21] $1018 $59
Atoms in the universe[22] ~$1080 $266
Googolionaire $10100 $332

Note: Under game rules which specify that if the player wins more than the casino's bankroll they will be paid all the casino has, the additional expected value is less than it would be if the casino had enough funds to cover one more round, i.e. less than $1. For the player to win W he must be allowed to play round L+1. So the additional expected value is W/2L+1.

The premise of infinite resources produces a variety of apparent paradoxes in economics. In the martingale betting system, a gambler betting on a tossed coin doubles his bet after every loss so that an eventual win would cover all losses; this system fails with any finite bankroll. The gambler's ruin concept shows that a persistent gambler who raises his bet to a fixed fraction of his bankroll when he wins, but does not reduce his bet when he loses, will eventually and inevitably go broke—even if the game has a positive expected value.

Ignore events with small probability edit

Buffon[17] argued that a theory of rational behavior must correspond to what a rational decision-maker would do in real life, and since reasonable people regularly ignore events that are unlikely enough, a rational decision-maker should also ignore such rare events.

As an estimate of the threshold of ignorability, he argued that, since a 56-year-old man ignores the possibility of dying in the next 24 hours, which has a probability of 1/10189 according to the mortality tables, events with less than 1/10,000 probability could be ignored. Assuming that, the St Petersburg game has an expected payoff of only  .

Rejection of mathematical expectation edit

Various authors, including Jean le Rond d'Alembert and John Maynard Keynes, have rejected maximization of expectation (even of utility) as a proper rule of conduct.[23][24] Keynes, in particular, insisted that the relative risk[clarification needed] of an alternative could be sufficiently high to reject it even if its expectation were enormous.[24] Recently, some researchers have suggested to replace the expected value by the median as the fair value.[25][26]

Ergodicity edit

An early resolution containing the essential mathematical arguments assuming multiplicative dynamics was put forward in 1870 by William Allen Whitworth.[27] An explicit link to the ergodicity problem was made by Peters in 2011.[28] These solutions are mathematically similar to using the Kelly criterion or logarithmic utility. General dynamics beyond the purely multiplicative case can correspond to non-logarithmic utility functions, as was pointed out by Carr and Cherubini in 2020.[29]

Recent discussions edit

Although this paradox is three centuries old, new arguments have still been introduced in recent years.

Feller edit

A solution involving sampling was offered by William Feller.[30] Intuitively Feller's answer is "to perform this game with a large number of people and calculate the expected value from the sample extraction". In this method, when the games of infinite number of times are possible, the expected value will be infinity, and in the case of finite, the expected value will be a much smaller value.

Samuelson edit

Paul Samuelson resolves the paradox[31] by arguing that, even if an entity had infinite resources, the game would never be offered. If the lottery represents an infinite expected gain to the player, then it also represents an infinite expected loss to the host. No one could be observed paying to play the game because it would never be offered. As Samuelson summarized the argument: "Paul will never be willing to give as much as Peter will demand for such a contract; and hence the indicated activity will take place at the equilibrium level of zero intensity."

Variants edit

Many variants of the St Petersburg game are proposed to counter proposed solutions to the game.[11]

For example, the "Pasadena game":[32] let   be the number of coin-flips; if   is odd, the player gains units of  ; else the player loses   units of utility. The expected utility from the game is then  . However, since the sum is not absolutely convergent, it may be rearranged to sum to any number, including positive or negative infinity. This suggests that the expected utility of the Pasadena game depends on the summation order, but standard decision theory does not provide a principled way to choose a summation order.

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Weiss, Michael D. (1987). Conceptual foundations of risk theory. U.S. Dept. of Agriculture, Economic Research Service. p. 36.
  2. ^ Plous, Scott (January 1, 1993). "Chapter 7". The psychology of decision-making. McGraw-Hill Education. ISBN 978-0070504776.
  3. ^ Eves, Howard (1990). An Introduction To The History of Mathematics (6th ed.). Brooks/Cole – Thomson Learning. p. 427.
  4. ^ a b de Montmort, Pierre Remond (1713). Essay d'analyse sur les jeux de hazard [Essays on the analysis of games of chance] (Reprinted in 2006) (in French) (Second ed.). Providence, Rhode Island: American Mathematical Society. ISBN 978-0-8218-3781-8. Translated by Pulskamp, Richard J (January 1, 2013). (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on April 14, 2021. Retrieved July 22, 2010.
  5. ^ a b c d Bernoulli, Daniel; originally published in 1738 ("Specimen Theorize Naval de Mensura Sortis", "Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae"); translated by Dr. Louise Sommer (January 1954). "Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk". Econometrica. 22 (1): 22–36. doi:10.2307/1909829. JSTOR 1909829. Retrieved May 30, 2006.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link)
  6. ^ Martin, Robert (Fall 2004). "The St. Petersburg Paradox". In Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Stanford, California: Stanford University. ISSN 1095-5054. Retrieved May 30, 2006.
  7. ^ Xavier University Computer Science. correspondence_petersburg_game.pdf Nicolas Bernoulli May 1, 2015, at the Wayback Machine
  8. ^ Menger, Karl (August 1934). "Das Unsicherheitsmoment in der Wertlehre Betrachtungen im Anschluß an das sogenannte Petersburger Spiel" [The element of uncertainty in value theory: Reflections on the so-called St Petersburg game]. Zeitschrift für Nationalökonomie (in German). 5 (4): 459–485. doi:10.1007/BF01311578. ISSN 0931-8658. S2CID 151290589.
  9. ^ Rieger, Marc Oliver; Wang, Mei (August 2006). "Cumulative prospect theory and the St. Petersburg paradox" (PDF). Economic Theory. 28 (3): 665–679. doi:10.1007/s00199-005-0641-6. hdl:20.500.11850/32060. ISSN 0938-2259. S2CID 790082. (Publicly accessible, older version. June 4, 2006, at the Wayback Machine)
  10. ^ Martin, R. M. "The St. Petersburg Paradox". Stanford Library. Stanford University.
  11. ^ a b Peterson, Martin (July 30, 2019) [July 30, 2019]. "The St. Petersburg Paradox". In Edward N. Zalta (ed.). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2020 ed.). Retrieved March 24, 2021.
  12. ^ a b Tversky, Amos; Kahneman (1992). "Advances in prospect theory: Cumulative representation of uncertainty". Journal of Risk and Uncertainty. 5 (4): 297–323. doi:10.1007/bf00122574. S2CID 8456150.
  13. ^ Blavatskyy, Pavlo (April 2005). "Back to the St. Petersburg Paradox?" (PDF). Management Science. 51 (4): 677–678. doi:10.1287/mnsc.1040.0352.
  14. ^ Peterson, Martin (2011). "A New Twist to the St. Petersburg Paradox". Journal of Philosophy 108 (12):697–699.
  15. ^ a b Jeffrey, Richard C. (1990). The Logic of Decision (2 ed.). University of Chicago Press. pp. 154. ISBN 9780226395821. [O]ur rebuttal of the St. Petersburg paradox consists in the remark that anyone who offers to let the agent play the St. Petersburg game is a liar for he is pretending to have an indefinitely large bank.
  16. ^ Fontaine, Alexix (1764). "Solution d'un problème sur les jeux de hasard" [Solution to a problem about gambling games]. Mémoires donnés à l'Académie Royale des Sciences: 429–431. cited in Dutka, 1988
  17. ^ a b Buffon, G. L. L. (1777). "Essai d'Arithmétique Motale". Supplements a l'Histoire Naturelle. IV: 46–14. Reprinted in Oeuvres Philosophiques de Buffon, Paris, 1906, cited in Dutka, 1988
  18. ^ a b Dutka, Jacques (1988). "On the St. Petersburg Paradox". Archive for History of Exact Sciences. 39 (1): 13–39. doi:10.1007/BF00329984. JSTOR 41133842. S2CID 121413446. Retrieved March 23, 2021.
  19. ^ Klebnikov, Sergei (January 11, 2021). "Elon Musk Falls To Second Richest Person In The World After His Fortune Drops Nearly $14 Billion In One Day". Forbes. Retrieved March 25, 2021.
  20. ^ a b The GDP data are as estimated for 2020 by the International Monetary Fund.
  21. ^ Jeffery 1983, p.155, noting that no banker could cover such a sum because "there is not that much money in the world".
  22. ^ "Notable Properties of Specific Numbers (page 19) at MROB".
  23. ^ d'Alembert, Jean le Rond; Opuscules mathématiques (1768), vol. iv, p. 284-5.
  24. ^ a b Keynes, John Maynard; A Treatise on Probability (1921), Pt IV Ch XXVI §9.
  25. ^ Hayden, B.; Platt, M. (2009). "The mean, the median, and the St. Petersburg paradox". Judgment and Decision Making. 4 (4): 256–272. doi:10.1017/S1930297500003831. PMC 3811154. PMID 24179560.
  26. ^ Okabe, T.; Nii, M.; Yoshimura, J. (2019). "The median-based resolution of the St. Petersburg paradox". Physics Letters A. 383 (26): 125838. Bibcode:2019PhLA..38325838O. doi:10.1016/j.physleta.2019.125838. S2CID 199124414.
  27. ^ Whitworth, William Allen (1870). Choice and Chance (2 ed.). London: Deighton Bell.
  28. ^ Peters, Ole (2011a). "The time resolution of the St Petersburg paradox". Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society. 369 (1956): 4913–4931. arXiv:1011.4404. Bibcode:2011RSPTA.369.4913P. doi:10.1098/rsta.2011.0065. PMC 3270388. PMID 22042904.
  29. ^ Carr, Peter; Cherubini, Umberto (2020). "Generalized Compounding and Growth Optimal Portfolios: Reconciling Kelly and Samuelson". SSRN. doi:10.2139/ssrn.3529729. S2CID 219384143.
  30. ^ Feller, William (1968). An Introduction to Probability Theory and its Applications Volume I, II. Wiley. ISBN 978-0471257080.
  31. ^ Samuelson, Paul (January 1960). "The St. Petersburg Paradox as a Divergent Double Limit". International Economic Review. 1 (1): 31–37. doi:10.2307/2525406. JSTOR 2525406.
  32. ^ Nover, H. (April 1, 2004). "Vexing Expectations". Mind. 113 (450): 237–249. doi:10.1093/mind/113.450.237. ISSN 0026-4423.

Notes edit

  1. ^ The notation X indicates the floor function, the largest integer less than or equal to X.

Further reading edit

  • Arrow, Kenneth J. (February 1974). "The use of unbounded utility functions in expected-utility maximization: Response" (PDF). Quarterly Journal of Economics. 88 (1): 136–138. doi:10.2307/1881800. JSTOR 1881800.
  • Aumann, Robert J. (April 1977). "The St. Petersburg paradox: A discussion of some recent comments". Journal of Economic Theory. 14 (2): 443–445. doi:10.1016/0022-0531(77)90143-0.
  • Cappiello, Antonio (2016). "Decision Making And Saint Petersburg Paradox: Focusing On Heuristic Parameters, Considering The Non-Ergodic Context And The Gambling Risks". Rivista italiana di economia demografia e statistica. 70 (4): 147–158. ISSN 0035-6832. RePEc:ite:iteeco:160406.
  • Durand, David (September 1957). "Growth Stocks and the Petersburg Paradox". The Journal of Finance. 12 (3): 348–363. doi:10.2307/2976852. JSTOR 2976852.
  • Haigh, John (1999). Taking Chances. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press. pp. 330. ISBN 978-0198526636.(Chapter 4)
  • Jeffrey, Richard C. (1983). The Logic of Decision (2 ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
  • Laplace, Pierre Simon (1814). Théorie analytique des probabilités [Analytical theory of probabilities] (in French) (Second ed.). Paris: Ve. Courcier.
  • Peters, Ole (October 2011b). "Menger 1934 revisited". arXiv:1110.1578 [q-fin.RM].
  • Peters, Ole; Gell-Mann, Murray (2016). "Evaluating gambles using dynamics". Chaos. 26 (2): 023103. arXiv:1405.0585. Bibcode:2016Chaos..26b3103P. doi:10.1063/1.4940236. PMID 26931584. S2CID 9726238.
  • Samuelson, Paul (March 1977). "St. Petersburg Paradoxes: Defanged, Dissected, and Historically Described". Journal of Economic Literature. 15 (1): 24–55. JSTOR 2722712.
  • Sen, P.K.; Singer, J.M. (1993). Large Sample Methods in Statistics. An Introduction with Applications. New York: Springer. ISBN 978-0412042218.
  • Todhunter, Isaac (1865). A history of the mathematical theory of probabilities. Macmillan & Co.
  • . The History of Economic Thought. The New School for Social Research, New York. Archived from the original on June 18, 2006. Retrieved May 30, 2006.

External links edit

  • Online simulation of the St. Petersburg lottery

petersburg, paradox, petersburg, lottery, paradox, involving, game, flipping, coin, where, expected, payoff, theoretical, lottery, game, approaches, infinity, nevertheless, seems, worth, only, very, small, amount, participants, situation, where, naïve, decisio. The St Petersburg paradox or St Petersburg lottery 1 is a paradox involving the game of flipping a coin where the expected payoff of the theoretical lottery game approaches infinity but nevertheless seems to be worth only a very small amount to the participants The St Petersburg paradox is a situation where a naive decision criterion that takes only the expected value into account predicts a course of action that presumably no actual person would be willing to take Several resolutions to the paradox have been proposed including the impossible amount of money a casino would need to continue the game indefinitely Portrait of Nicolas Bernoulli 1723 The problem was invented by Nicolas Bernoulli 2 who stated it in a letter to Pierre Raymond de Montmort on September 9 1713 3 4 However the paradox takes its name from its analysis by Nicolas cousin Daniel Bernoulli one time resident of Saint Petersburg who in 1738 published his thoughts about the problem in the Commentaries of the Imperial Academy of Science of Saint Petersburg 5 Contents 1 The St Petersburg game 2 The paradox 3 Solutions 3 1 Expected utility theory 3 2 Probability weighting 3 3 Finite St Petersburg lotteries 3 4 Ignore events with small probability 3 5 Rejection of mathematical expectation 3 6 Ergodicity 4 Recent discussions 4 1 Feller 4 2 Samuelson 4 3 Variants 5 See also 6 References 7 Notes 8 Further reading 9 External linksThe St Petersburg game editA casino offers a game of chance for a single player in which a fair coin is tossed at each stage The initial stake begins at 2 dollars and is doubled every time tails appears The first time heads appears the game ends and the player wins whatever is the current stake Thus the player wins 2 dollars if heads appears on the first toss 4 dollars if tails appears on the first toss and heads on the second 8 dollars if tails appears on the first two tosses and heads on the third and so on Mathematically the player wins 2 k 1 displaystyle 2 k 1 nbsp dollars where k displaystyle k nbsp is the number of consecutive tails tosses 5 What would be a fair price to pay the casino for entering the game To answer this one needs to consider what would be the expected payout at each stage with probability 1 2 the player wins 2 dollars with probability 1 4 the player wins 4 dollars with probability 1 8 the player wins 8 dollars and so on Assuming the game can continue as long as the coin toss results in tails and in particular that the casino has unlimited resources the expected value is thus E 1 2 2 1 4 4 1 8 8 1 16 16 1 1 1 1 displaystyle begin aligned E amp frac 1 2 cdot 2 frac 1 4 cdot 4 frac 1 8 cdot 8 frac 1 16 cdot 16 cdots amp 1 1 1 1 cdots amp infty end aligned nbsp This sum grows without bound so the expected win is an infinite amount of money The paradox editConsidering nothing but the expected value of the net change in one s monetary wealth one should therefore play the game at any price if offered the opportunity Yet Daniel Bernoulli after describing the game with an initial stake of one ducat stated Although the standard calculation shows that the value of the player s expectation is infinitely great it has to be admitted that any fairly reasonable man would sell his chance with great pleasure for twenty ducats 5 Robert Martin quotes Ian Hacking as saying Few of us would pay even 25 to enter such a game and he says most commentators would agree 6 The apparent paradox is the discrepancy between what people seem willing to pay to enter the game and the infinite expected value 5 Solutions editSeveral approaches have been proposed for solving the paradox Expected utility theory edit The classical resolution of the paradox involved the explicit introduction of a utility function an expected utility hypothesis and the presumption of diminishing marginal utility of money Daniel Bernoulli The determination of the value of an item must not be based on the price but rather on the utility it yields There is no doubt that a gain of one thousand ducats is more significant to the pauper than to a rich man though both gain the same amount A common utility model suggested by Daniel Bernoulli is the logarithmic function U w ln w known as log utility It is a function of the gambler s total wealth w and the concept of diminishing marginal utility of money is built into it The expected utility hypothesis posits that a utility function exists that provides a good criterion for real people s behavior i e a function that returns a positive or negative value indicating if the wager is a good gamble For each possible event the change in utility ln wealth after the event ln wealth before the event will be weighted by the probability of that event occurring Let c be the cost charged to enter the game The expected incremental utility of the lottery now converges to a finite value D E U k 1 1 2 k ln w 2 k c ln w lt displaystyle Delta E U sum k 1 infty frac 1 2 k left ln left w 2 k c right ln w right lt infty nbsp This formula gives an implicit relationship between the gambler s wealth and how much he should be willing to pay specifically any c that gives a positive change in expected utility For example with natural log utility a millionaire 1 000 000 should be willing to pay up to 20 88 a person with 1 000 should pay up to 10 95 a person with 2 should borrow 1 35 and pay up to 3 35 Before Daniel Bernoulli published in 1728 a mathematician from Geneva Gabriel Cramer had already found parts of this idea also motivated by the St Petersburg paradox in stating that the mathematicians estimate money in proportion to its quantity and men of good sense in proportion to the usage that they may make of it He demonstrated in a letter to Nicolas Bernoulli 7 that a square root function describing the diminishing marginal benefit of gains can resolve the problem However unlike Daniel Bernoulli he did not consider the total wealth of a person but only the gain by the lottery This solution by Cramer and Bernoulli however is not completely satisfying as the lottery can easily be changed in a way such that the paradox reappears To this aim we just need to change the game so that it gives even more rapidly increasing payoffs For any unbounded utility function one can find a lottery that allows for a variant of the St Petersburg paradox as was first pointed out by Menger 8 Recently expected utility theory has been extended to arrive at more behavioral decision models In some of these new theories as in cumulative prospect theory the St Petersburg paradox again appears in certain cases even when the utility function is concave but not if it is bounded 9 Probability weighting edit Nicolas Bernoulli himself proposed an alternative idea for solving the paradox He conjectured that people will neglect unlikely events 4 Since in the St Petersburg lottery only unlikely events yield the high prizes that lead to an infinite expected value this could resolve the paradox The idea of probability weighting resurfaced much later in the work on prospect theory by Daniel Kahneman and Amos Tversky Paul Weirich similarly wrote that risk aversion could solve the paradox Weirich went on to write that increasing the prize actually decreases the chance of someone paying to play the game stating there is some number of birds in hand worth more than any number of birds in the bush 10 11 However this has been rejected by some theorists because as they point out some people enjoy the risk of gambling and because it is illogical to assume that increasing the prize will lead to more risks Cumulative prospect theory is one popular generalization of expected utility theory that can predict many behavioral regularities 12 However the overweighting of small probability events introduced in cumulative prospect theory may restore the St Petersburg paradox Cumulative prospect theory avoids the St Petersburg paradox only when the power coefficient of the utility function is lower than the power coefficient of the probability weighting function 13 Intuitively the utility function must not simply be concave but it must be concave relative to the probability weighting function to avoid the St Petersburg paradox One can argue that the formulas for the prospect theory are obtained in the region of less than 400 12 This is not applicable for infinitely increasing sums in the St Petersburg paradox Finite St Petersburg lotteries edit The classical St Petersburg game assumes that the casino or banker has infinite resources This assumption has long been challenged as unrealistic 14 15 Alexis Fontaine des Bertins pointed out in 1754 that the resources of any potential backer of the game are finite 16 More importantly the expected value of the game only grows logarithmically with the resources of the casino As a result the expected value of the game even when played against a casino with the largest bankroll realistically conceivable is quite modest In 1777 Georges Louis Leclerc Comte de Buffon calculated that after 29 rounds of play there would not be enough money in the Kingdom of France to cover the bet 17 If the casino has finite resources the game must end once those resources are exhausted 15 Suppose the total resources or maximum jackpot of the casino are W dollars more generally W is measured in units of half the game s initial stake Then the maximum number of times the casino can play before it no longer can fully cover the next bet is L log2 W 18 nb 1 Assuming the game ends when the casino can no longer cover the bet the expected value E of the lottery then becomes 18 E k 1 L 1 2 k 2 k L displaystyle begin aligned E amp sum k 1 L frac 1 2 k cdot 2 k L end aligned nbsp The following table shows the expected value E of the game with various potential bankers and their bankroll W Banker Bankroll Expected value of one gameMillionaire 1 050 000 20Billionaire 1 075 000 000 30Elon Musk Apr 2022 19 265 000 000 000 38U S GDP 2020 20 20 8 trillion 44World GDP 2020 20 83 8 trillion 46Billion billionaire 21 1018 59Atoms in the universe 22 1080 266Googolionaire 10100 332Note Under game rules which specify that if the player wins more than the casino s bankroll they will be paid all the casino has the additional expected value is less than it would be if the casino had enough funds to cover one more round i e less than 1 For the player to win W he must be allowed to play round L 1 So the additional expected value is W 2L 1 The premise of infinite resources produces a variety of apparent paradoxes in economics In the martingale betting system a gambler betting on a tossed coin doubles his bet after every loss so that an eventual win would cover all losses this system fails with any finite bankroll The gambler s ruin concept shows that a persistent gambler who raises his bet to a fixed fraction of his bankroll when he wins but does not reduce his bet when he loses will eventually and inevitably go broke even if the game has a positive expected value Ignore events with small probability edit Buffon 17 argued that a theory of rational behavior must correspond to what a rational decision maker would do in real life and since reasonable people regularly ignore events that are unlikely enough a rational decision maker should also ignore such rare events As an estimate of the threshold of ignorability he argued that since a 56 year old man ignores the possibility of dying in the next 24 hours which has a probability of 1 10189 according to the mortality tables events with less than 1 10 000 probability could be ignored Assuming that the St Petersburg game has an expected payoff of only k 1 13 2 k 1 2 k 13 displaystyle sum k 1 13 2 k frac 1 2 k 13 nbsp Rejection of mathematical expectation edit Various authors including Jean le Rond d Alembert and John Maynard Keynes have rejected maximization of expectation even of utility as a proper rule of conduct 23 24 Keynes in particular insisted that the relative risk clarification needed of an alternative could be sufficiently high to reject it even if its expectation were enormous 24 Recently some researchers have suggested to replace the expected value by the median as the fair value 25 26 Ergodicity edit An early resolution containing the essential mathematical arguments assuming multiplicative dynamics was put forward in 1870 by William Allen Whitworth 27 An explicit link to the ergodicity problem was made by Peters in 2011 28 These solutions are mathematically similar to using the Kelly criterion or logarithmic utility General dynamics beyond the purely multiplicative case can correspond to non logarithmic utility functions as was pointed out by Carr and Cherubini in 2020 29 Recent discussions editAlthough this paradox is three centuries old new arguments have still been introduced in recent years Feller edit A solution involving sampling was offered by William Feller 30 Intuitively Feller s answer is to perform this game with a large number of people and calculate the expected value from the sample extraction In this method when the games of infinite number of times are possible the expected value will be infinity and in the case of finite the expected value will be a much smaller value Samuelson edit Paul Samuelson resolves the paradox 31 by arguing that even if an entity had infinite resources the game would never be offered If the lottery represents an infinite expected gain to the player then it also represents an infinite expected loss to the host No one could be observed paying to play the game because it would never be offered As Samuelson summarized the argument Paul will never be willing to give as much as Peter will demand for such a contract and hence the indicated activity will take place at the equilibrium level of zero intensity Variants edit Many variants of the St Petersburg game are proposed to counter proposed solutions to the game 11 For example the Pasadena game 32 let n displaystyle n nbsp be the number of coin flips if n displaystyle n nbsp is odd the player gains units of 2 n n displaystyle frac 2 n n nbsp else the player loses 2 n n displaystyle frac 2 n n nbsp units of utility The expected utility from the game is then n 1 1 n n ln 2 displaystyle sum n 1 infty frac 1 n n ln 2 nbsp However since the sum is not absolutely convergent it may be rearranged to sum to any number including positive or negative infinity This suggests that the expected utility of the Pasadena game depends on the summation order but standard decision theory does not provide a principled way to choose a summation order See also editEllsberg paradox Exponential growth Gambler s ruin Kelly criterion Martingale betting system Pascal s mugging Two envelopes problem Zeno s paradoxesReferences edit Weiss Michael D 1987 Conceptual foundations of risk theory U S Dept of Agriculture Economic Research Service p 36 Plous Scott January 1 1993 Chapter 7 The psychology of decision making McGraw Hill Education ISBN 978 0070504776 Eves Howard 1990 An Introduction To The History of Mathematics 6th ed Brooks Cole Thomson Learning p 427 a b de Montmort Pierre Remond 1713 Essay d analyse sur les jeux de hazard Essays on the analysis of games of chance Reprinted in 2006 in French Second ed Providence Rhode Island American Mathematical Society ISBN 978 0 8218 3781 8 Translated by Pulskamp Richard J January 1 2013 Correspondence of Nicolas Bernoulli concerning the St Petersburg Game PDF Archived from the original PDF on April 14 2021 Retrieved July 22 2010 a b c d Bernoulli Daniel originally published in 1738 Specimen Theorize Naval de Mensura Sortis Commentarii Academiae Scientiarum Imperialis Petropolitanae translated by Dr Louise Sommer January 1954 Exposition of a New Theory on the Measurement of Risk Econometrica 22 1 22 36 doi 10 2307 1909829 JSTOR 1909829 Retrieved May 30 2006 a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a CS1 maint multiple names authors list link Martin Robert Fall 2004 The St Petersburg Paradox In Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Stanford California Stanford University ISSN 1095 5054 Retrieved May 30 2006 Xavier University Computer Science correspondence petersburg game pdf Nicolas Bernoulli Archived May 1 2015 at the Wayback Machine Menger Karl August 1934 Das Unsicherheitsmoment in der Wertlehre Betrachtungen im Anschluss an das sogenannte Petersburger Spiel The element of uncertainty in value theory Reflections on the so called St Petersburg game Zeitschrift fur Nationalokonomie in German 5 4 459 485 doi 10 1007 BF01311578 ISSN 0931 8658 S2CID 151290589 Rieger Marc Oliver Wang Mei August 2006 Cumulative prospect theory and the St Petersburg paradox PDF Economic Theory 28 3 665 679 doi 10 1007 s00199 005 0641 6 hdl 20 500 11850 32060 ISSN 0938 2259 S2CID 790082 Publicly accessible older version Archived June 4 2006 at the Wayback Machine Martin R M The St Petersburg Paradox Stanford Library Stanford University a b Peterson Martin July 30 2019 July 30 2019 The St Petersburg Paradox In Edward N Zalta ed Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2020 ed Retrieved March 24 2021 a b Tversky Amos Kahneman 1992 Advances in prospect theory Cumulative representation of uncertainty Journal of Risk and Uncertainty 5 4 297 323 doi 10 1007 bf00122574 S2CID 8456150 Blavatskyy Pavlo April 2005 Back to the St Petersburg Paradox PDF Management Science 51 4 677 678 doi 10 1287 mnsc 1040 0352 Peterson Martin 2011 A New Twist to the St Petersburg Paradox Journal of Philosophy 108 12 697 699 a b Jeffrey Richard C 1990 The Logic of Decision 2 ed University of Chicago Press pp 154 ISBN 9780226395821 O ur rebuttal of the St Petersburg paradox consists in the remark that anyone who offers to let the agent play the St Petersburg game is a liar for he is pretending to have an indefinitely large bank Fontaine Alexix 1764 Solution d un probleme sur les jeux de hasard Solution to a problem about gambling games Memoires donnes a l Academie Royale des Sciences 429 431 cited in Dutka 1988 a b Buffon G L L 1777 Essai d Arithmetique Motale Supplements a l Histoire Naturelle IV 46 14 Reprinted in Oeuvres Philosophiques de Buffon Paris 1906 cited in Dutka 1988 a b Dutka Jacques 1988 On the St Petersburg Paradox Archive for History of Exact Sciences 39 1 13 39 doi 10 1007 BF00329984 JSTOR 41133842 S2CID 121413446 Retrieved March 23 2021 Klebnikov Sergei January 11 2021 Elon Musk Falls To Second Richest Person In The World After His Fortune Drops Nearly 14 Billion In One Day Forbes Retrieved March 25 2021 a b The GDP data are as estimated for 2020 by the International Monetary Fund Jeffery 1983 p 155 noting that no banker could cover such a sum because there is not that much money in the world Notable Properties of Specific Numbers page 19 at MROB d Alembert Jean le Rond Opuscules mathematiques 1768 vol iv p 284 5 a b Keynes John Maynard A Treatise on Probability 1921 Pt IV Ch XXVI 9 Hayden B Platt M 2009 The mean the median and the St Petersburg paradox Judgment and Decision Making 4 4 256 272 doi 10 1017 S1930297500003831 PMC 3811154 PMID 24179560 Okabe T Nii M Yoshimura J 2019 The median based resolution of the St Petersburg paradox Physics Letters A 383 26 125838 Bibcode 2019PhLA 38325838O doi 10 1016 j physleta 2019 125838 S2CID 199124414 Whitworth William Allen 1870 Choice and Chance 2 ed London Deighton Bell Peters Ole 2011a The time resolution of the St Petersburg paradox Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society 369 1956 4913 4931 arXiv 1011 4404 Bibcode 2011RSPTA 369 4913P doi 10 1098 rsta 2011 0065 PMC 3270388 PMID 22042904 Carr Peter Cherubini Umberto 2020 Generalized Compounding and Growth Optimal Portfolios Reconciling Kelly and Samuelson SSRN doi 10 2139 ssrn 3529729 S2CID 219384143 Feller William 1968 An Introduction to Probability Theory and its Applications Volume I II Wiley ISBN 978 0471257080 Samuelson Paul January 1960 The St Petersburg Paradox as a Divergent Double Limit International Economic Review 1 1 31 37 doi 10 2307 2525406 JSTOR 2525406 Nover H April 1 2004 Vexing Expectations Mind 113 450 237 249 doi 10 1093 mind 113 450 237 ISSN 0026 4423 Notes edit The notation X indicates the floor function the largest integer less than or equal to X Further reading editArrow Kenneth J February 1974 The use of unbounded utility functions in expected utility maximization Response PDF Quarterly Journal of Economics 88 1 136 138 doi 10 2307 1881800 JSTOR 1881800 Aumann Robert J April 1977 The St Petersburg paradox A discussion of some recent comments Journal of Economic Theory 14 2 443 445 doi 10 1016 0022 0531 77 90143 0 Cappiello Antonio 2016 Decision Making And Saint Petersburg Paradox Focusing On Heuristic Parameters Considering The Non Ergodic Context And The Gambling Risks Rivista italiana di economia demografia e statistica 70 4 147 158 ISSN 0035 6832 RePEc ite iteeco 160406 Durand David September 1957 Growth Stocks and the Petersburg Paradox The Journal of Finance 12 3 348 363 doi 10 2307 2976852 JSTOR 2976852 Haigh John 1999 Taking Chances Oxford UK Oxford University Press pp 330 ISBN 978 0198526636 Chapter 4 Jeffrey Richard C 1983 The Logic of Decision 2 ed Chicago University of Chicago Press Laplace Pierre Simon 1814 Theorie analytique des probabilites Analytical theory of probabilities in French Second ed Paris Ve Courcier Peters Ole October 2011b Menger 1934 revisited arXiv 1110 1578 q fin RM Peters Ole Gell Mann Murray 2016 Evaluating gambles using dynamics Chaos 26 2 023103 arXiv 1405 0585 Bibcode 2016Chaos 26b3103P doi 10 1063 1 4940236 PMID 26931584 S2CID 9726238 Samuelson Paul March 1977 St Petersburg Paradoxes Defanged Dissected and Historically Described Journal of Economic Literature 15 1 24 55 JSTOR 2722712 Sen P K Singer J M 1993 Large Sample Methods in Statistics An Introduction with Applications New York Springer ISBN 978 0412042218 Todhunter Isaac 1865 A history of the mathematical theory of probabilities Macmillan amp Co Bernoulli and the St Petersburg Paradox The History of Economic Thought The New School for Social Research New York Archived from the original on June 18 2006 Retrieved May 30 2006 External links editOnline simulation of the St Petersburg lottery Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title St Petersburg paradox amp oldid 1183165022, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.