fbpx
Wikipedia

Level of measurement

Level of measurement or scale of measure is a classification that describes the nature of information within the values assigned to variables.[1] Psychologist Stanley Smith Stevens developed the best-known classification with four levels, or scales, of measurement: nominal, ordinal, interval, and ratio.[1][2] This framework of distinguishing levels of measurement originated in psychology and is widely criticized by scholars in other disciplines.[3] Other classifications include those by Mosteller and Tukey,[4] and by Chrisman.[5]

Stevens's typology

Overview

Stevens proposed his typology in a 1946 Science article titled "On the theory of scales of measurement".[2] In that article, Stevens claimed that all measurement in science was conducted using four different types of scales that he called "nominal", "ordinal", "interval", and "ratio", unifying both "qualitative" (which are described by his "nominal" type) and "quantitative" (to a different degree, all the rest of his scales). The concept of scale types later received the mathematical rigour that it lacked at its inception with the work of mathematical psychologists Theodore Alper (1985, 1987), Louis Narens (1981a, b), and R. Duncan Luce (1986, 1987, 2001). As Luce (1997, p. 395) wrote:

S. S. Stevens (1946, 1951, 1975) claimed that what counted was having an interval or ratio scale. Subsequent research has given meaning to this assertion, but given his attempts to invoke scale type ideas it is doubtful if he understood it himself ... no measurement theorist I know accepts Stevens's broad definition of measurement ... in our view, the only sensible meaning for 'rule' is empirically testable laws about the attribute.

Comparison

Incremental
progress
Measure property Mathematical
operators
Advanced
operations
Central
tendency
Variability
Nominal Classification, membership =, ≠ Grouping Mode Qualitative variation
Ordinal Comparison, level >, < Sorting Median Range,
interquartile range
Interval Difference, affinity +, − Comparison to a standard Arithmetic mean Deviation
Ratio Magnitude, amount ×, / Ratio Geometric mean,
harmonic mean
Coefficient of variation,
studentized range

Nominal level

The nominal type differentiates between items or subjects based only on their names or (meta-)categories and other qualitative classifications they belong to; thus dichotomous data involves the construction of classifications as well as the classification of items. Discovery of an exception to a classification can be viewed as progress. Numbers may be used to represent the variables but the numbers do not have numerical value or relationship: for example, a globally unique identifier.

Examples of these classifications include gender, nationality, ethnicity, language, genre, style, biological species, and form.[6][7] In a university one could also use hall of affiliation as an example. Other concrete examples are

Nominal scales were often called qualitative scales, and measurements made on qualitative scales were called qualitative data. However, the rise of qualitative research has made this usage confusing. If numbers are assigned as labels in nominal measurement, they have no specific numerical value or meaning. No form of arithmetic computation (+, −, ×, etc.) may be performed on nominal measures. The nominal level is the lowest measurement level used from a statistical point of view.

Mathematical operations

Equality and other operations that can be defined in terms of equality, such as inequality and set membership, are the only non-trivial operations that generically apply to objects of the nominal type.

Central tendency

The mode, i.e. the most common item, is allowed as the measure of central tendency for the nominal type. On the other hand, the median, i.e. the middle-ranked item, makes no sense for the nominal type of data since ranking is meaningless for the nominal type.[8]

Ordinal scale

The ordinal type allows for rank order (1st, 2nd, 3rd, etc.) by which data can be sorted but still does not allow for a relative degree of difference between them. Examples include, on one hand, dichotomous data with dichotomous (or dichotomized) values such as 'sick' vs. 'healthy' when measuring health, 'guilty' vs. 'not-guilty' when making judgments in courts, 'wrong/false' vs. 'right/true' when measuring truth value, and, on the other hand, non-dichotomous data consisting of a spectrum of values, such as 'completely agree', 'mostly agree', 'mostly disagree', 'completely disagree' when measuring opinion.

The ordinal scale places events in order, but there is no attempt to make the intervals of the scale equal in terms of some rule. Rank orders represent ordinal scales and are frequently used in research relating to qualitative phenomena. A student's rank in his graduation class involves the use of an ordinal scale. One has to be very careful in making a statement about scores based on ordinal scales. For instance, if Devi's position in his class is 10 and Ganga's position is 40, it cannot be said that Devi's position is four times as good as that of Ganga. The statement would make no sense at all. Ordinal scales only permit the ranking of items from highest to lowest. Ordinal measures have no absolute values, and the real differences between adjacent ranks may not be equal. All that can be said is that one person is higher or lower on the scale than another, but more precise comparisons cannot be made. Thus, the use of an ordinal scale implies a statement of 'greater than' or 'less than' (an equality statement is also acceptable) without our being able to state how much greater or less. The real difference between ranks 1 and 2, for instance, may be more or less than the difference between ranks 5 and 6. Since the numbers of this scale have only a rank meaning, the appropriate measure of central tendency is the median. A percentile or quartile measure is used for measuring dispersion. Correlations are restricted to various rank order methods. Measures of statistical significance are restricted to the non-parametric methods (R. M. Kothari, 2004).

Central tendency

The median, i.e. middle-ranked, item is allowed as the measure of central tendency; however, the mean (or average) as the measure of central tendency is not allowed. The mode is allowed.

In 1946, Stevens observed that psychological measurement, such as measurement of opinions, usually operates on ordinal scales; thus means and standard deviations have no validity, but they can be used to get ideas for how to improve operationalization of variables used in questionnaires. Most psychological data collected by psychometric instruments and tests, measuring cognitive and other abilities, are ordinal, although some theoreticians have argued they can be treated as interval or ratio scales. However, there is little prima facie evidence to suggest that such attributes are anything more than ordinal (Cliff, 1996; Cliff & Keats, 2003; Michell, 2008).[9] In particular,[10] IQ scores reflect an ordinal scale, in which all scores are meaningful for comparison only.[11][12][13] There is no absolute zero, and a 10-point difference may carry different meanings at different points of the scale.[14][15]

Interval scale

The interval type allows for the degree of difference between items, but not the ratio between them. Examples include temperature scales with the Celsius scale, which has two defined points (the freezing and boiling point of water at specific conditions) and then separated into 100 intervals, date when measured from an arbitrary epoch (such as AD), location in Cartesian coordinates, and direction measured in degrees from true or magnetic north. Ratios are not meaningful since 20 °C cannot be said to be "twice as hot" as 10 °C (unlike temperature in Kelvins), nor can multiplication/division be carried out between any two dates directly. However, ratios of differences can be expressed; for example, one difference can be twice another. Interval type variables are sometimes also called "scaled variables", but the formal mathematical term is an affine space (in this case an affine line).

Central tendency and statistical dispersion

The mode, median, and arithmetic mean are allowed to measure central tendency of interval variables, while measures of statistical dispersion include range and standard deviation. Since one can only divide by differences, one cannot define measures that require some ratios, such as the coefficient of variation. More subtly, while one can define moments about the origin, only central moments are meaningful, since the choice of origin is arbitrary. One can define standardized moments, since ratios of differences are meaningful, but one cannot define the coefficient of variation, since the mean is a moment about the origin, unlike the standard deviation, which is (the square root of) a central moment.

Ratio scale

See also: Positive real numbers § Ratio scale

The ratio type takes its name from the fact that measurement is the estimation of the ratio between a magnitude of a continuous quantity and a unit of measurement of the same kind (Michell, 1997, 1999). Most measurement in the physical sciences and engineering is done on ratio scales. Examples include mass, length, duration, plane angle, energy and electric charge. In contrast to interval scales, ratios can be compared using division. Very informally, many ratio scales can be described as specifying "how much" of something (i.e. an amount or magnitude). Ratio scale is often used to express an order of magnitude such as for temperature in Orders of magnitude (temperature).

Central tendency and statistical dispersion

The geometric mean and the harmonic mean are allowed to measure the central tendency, in addition to the mode, median, and arithmetic mean. The studentized range and the coefficient of variation are allowed to measure statistical dispersion. All statistical measures are allowed because all necessary mathematical operations are defined for the ratio scale.

Debate on Stevens's typology

While Stevens's typology is widely adopted, it is still being challenged by other theoreticians, particularly in the cases of the nominal and ordinal types (Michell, 1986).[16] Some however have argued that the degree of discord can be overstated. Hand says, "Basic psychology texts often begin with Stevens's framework and the ideas are ubiquitous. Indeed, the essential soundness of his hierarchy has been established for representational measurement by mathematicians, determining the invariance properties of mappings from empirical systems to real number continua. Certainly the ideas have been revised, extended, and elaborated, but the remarkable thing is his insight given the relatively limited formal apparatus available to him and how many decades have passed since he coined them."[17]

Duncan (1986) objected to the use of the word measurement in relation to the nominal type, but Stevens (1975) said of his own definition of measurement that "the assignment can be any consistent rule. The only rule not allowed would be random assignment, for randomness amounts in effect to a nonrule".

The use of the mean as a measure of the central tendency for the ordinal type is still debatable among those who accept Stevens's typology. Many behavioural scientists use the mean for ordinal data, anyway. This is often justified on the basis that the ordinal type in behavioural science is in fact somewhere between the true ordinal and interval types; although the interval difference between two ordinal ranks is not constant, it is often of the same order of magnitude.

For example, applications of measurement models in educational contexts often indicate that total scores have a fairly linear relationship with measurements across the range of an assessment. Thus, some argue that so long as the unknown interval difference between ordinal scale ranks is not too variable, interval scale statistics such as means can meaningfully be used on ordinal scale variables. Statistical analysis software such as SPSS requires the user to select the appropriate measurement class for each variable. This ensures that subsequent user errors cannot inadvertently perform meaningless analyses (for example correlation analysis with a variable on a nominal level).

L. L. Thurstone made progress toward developing a justification for obtaining the interval type, based on the law of comparative judgment. A common application of the law is the analytic hierarchy process. Further progress was made by Georg Rasch (1960), who developed the probabilistic Rasch model that provides a theoretical basis and justification for obtaining interval-level measurements from counts of observations such as total scores on assessments.

Other proposed typologies

Typologies aside from Stevens's typology have been proposed. For instance, Mosteller and Tukey (1977), Nelder (1990)[18] described continuous counts, continuous ratios, count ratios, and categorical modes of data. See also Chrisman (1998), van den Berg (1991).[19]

Mosteller and Tukey's typology (1977)

Mosteller and Tukey[4] noted that the four levels are not exhaustive and proposed:

  1. Names
  2. Grades (ordered labels like beginner, intermediate, advanced)
  3. Ranks (orders with 1 being the smallest or largest, 2 the next smallest or largest, and so on)
  4. Counted fractions (bound by 0 and 1)
  5. Counts (non-negative integers)
  6. Amounts (non-negative real numbers)
  7. Balances (any real number)

For example, percentages (a variation on fractions in the Mosteller–Tukey framework) do not fit well into Stevens's framework: No transformation is fully admissible.[16]

Chrisman's typology (1998)

Nicholas R. Chrisman[5] introduced an expanded list of levels of measurement to account for various measurements that do not necessarily fit with the traditional notions of levels of measurement. Measurements bound to a range and repeating (like degrees in a circle, clock time, etc.), graded membership categories, and other types of measurement do not fit to Stevens's original work, leading to the introduction of six new levels of measurement, for a total of ten:

  1. Nominal
  2. Gradation of membership
  3. Ordinal
  4. Interval
  5. Log-interval
  6. Extensive ratio
  7. Cyclical ratio
  8. Derived ratio
  9. Counts
  10. Absolute

While some claim that the extended levels of measurement are rarely used outside of academic geography,[20] graded membership is central to fuzzy set theory, while absolute measurements include probabilities and the plausibility and ignorance in Dempster–Shafer theory. Cyclical ratio measurements include angles and times. Counts appear to be ratio measurements, but the scale is not arbitrary and fractional counts are commonly meaningless. Log-interval measurements are commonly displayed in stock market graphics. All these types of measurements are commonly used outside academic geography, and do not fit well to Stevens' original work.

Scale types and Stevens's "operational theory of measurement"

The theory of scale types is the intellectual handmaiden to Stevens's "operational theory of measurement", which was to become definitive within psychology and the behavioral sciences,[citation needed] despite Michell's characterization as its being quite at odds with measurement in the natural sciences (Michell, 1999). Essentially, the operational theory of measurement was a reaction to the conclusions of a committee established in 1932 by the British Association for the Advancement of Science to investigate the possibility of genuine scientific measurement in the psychological and behavioral sciences. This committee, which became known as the Ferguson committee, published a Final Report (Ferguson, et al., 1940, p. 245) in which Stevens's sone scale (Stevens & Davis, 1938) was an object of criticism:

…any law purporting to express a quantitative relation between sensation intensity and stimulus intensity is not merely false but is in fact meaningless unless and until a meaning can be given to the concept of addition as applied to sensation.

That is, if Stevens's sone scale genuinely measured the intensity of auditory sensations, then evidence for such sensations as being quantitative attributes needed to be produced. The evidence needed was the presence of additive structure – a concept comprehensively treated by the German mathematician Otto Hölder (Hölder, 1901). Given that the physicist and measurement theorist Norman Robert Campbell dominated the Ferguson committee's deliberations, the committee concluded that measurement in the social sciences was impossible due to the lack of concatenation operations. This conclusion was later rendered false by the discovery of the theory of conjoint measurement by Debreu (1960) and independently by Luce & Tukey (1964). However, Stevens's reaction was not to conduct experiments to test for the presence of additive structure in sensations, but instead to render the conclusions of the Ferguson committee null and void by proposing a new theory of measurement:

Paraphrasing N. R. Campbell (Final Report, p.340), we may say that measurement, in the broadest sense, is defined as the assignment of numerals to objects and events according to rules (Stevens, 1946, p.677).

Stevens was greatly influenced by the ideas of another Harvard academic, the Nobel laureate physicist Percy Bridgman (1927), whose doctrine of operationism Stevens used to define measurement. In Stevens's definition, for example, it is the use of a tape measure that defines length (the object of measurement) as being measurable (and so by implication quantitative). Critics of operationism object that it confuses the relations between two objects or events for properties of one of those of objects or events (Hardcastle, 1995; Michell, 1999; Moyer, 1981a,b; Rogers, 1989).

The Canadian measurement theorist William Rozeboom (1966) was an early and trenchant critic of Stevens's theory of scale types.

Same variable may be different scale type depending on context

Another issue is that the same variable may be a different scale type depending on how it is measured and on the goals of the analysis. For example, hair color is usually thought of as a nominal variable, since it has no apparent ordering.[21] However, it is possible to order colors (including hair colors) in various ways, including by hue; this is known as colorimetry. Hue is an interval level variable.

See also

References

  1. ^ a b Kirch, Wilhelm, ed. (2008). "Level of Measurement". Encyclopedia of Public Health. Vol. 2. Springer. pp. 851–852. doi:10.1007/978-1-4020-5614-7_1971. ISBN 978-1-4020-5613-0.
  2. ^ a b Stevens, S. S. (7 June 1946). "On the Theory of Scales of Measurement". Science. 103 (2684): 677–680. Bibcode:1946Sci...103..677S. doi:10.1126/science.103.2684.677. PMID 17750512. S2CID 4667599.
  3. ^ Michell, J. (1986). "Measurement scales and statistics: a clash of paradigms". Psychological Bulletin. 100 (3): 398–407. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.100.3.398.
  4. ^ a b Mosteller, Frederick (1977). Data analysis and regression : a second course in statistics. Reading, Mass: Addison-Wesley Pub. Co. ISBN 978-0201048544.
  5. ^ a b Chrisman, Nicholas R. (1998). "Rethinking Levels of Measurement for Cartography". Cartography and Geographic Information Science. 25 (4): 231–242. doi:10.1559/152304098782383043. ISSN 1523-0406. – via Taylor & Francis (subscription required)
  6. ^ Nominal measures are based on sets and depend on categories, a la Aristotle: Chrisman, Nicholas (March 1995). "Beyond Stevens: A revised approach to measurement for geographic information". Retrieved 2014-08-25.
  7. ^ "Invariably one came up against fundamental physical limits to the accuracy of measurement. ... The art of physical measurement seemed to be a matter of compromise, of choosing between reciprocally related uncertainties. ... Multiplying together the conjugate pairs of uncertainty limits mentioned, however, I found that they formed invariant products of not one but two distinct kinds. ... The first group of limits were calculable a priori from a specification of the instrument. The second group could be calculated only a posteriori from a specification of what was done with the instrument. ... In the first case each unit [of information] would add one additional dimension (conceptual category), whereas in the second each unit would add one additional atomic fact.", – pp. 1–4: MacKay, Donald M. (1969), Information, Mechanism, and Meaning, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, ISBN 0-262-63-032-X
  8. ^ Manikandan, S. (2011). "Measures of central tendency: Median and mode". Journal of Pharmacology and Pharmacotherapeutics. 2 (3): 214–5. doi:10.4103/0976-500X.83300. PMC 3157145. PMID 21897729.
  9. ^ *Lord, Frederic M.; Novick, Melvin R.; Birnbaum, Allan (1968). Statistical Theories of Mental Test Scores. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. p. 21. LCCN 68011394. Although, formally speaking, interval measurement can always be obtained by specification, such specification is theoretically meaningful only if it is implied by the theory and model relevant to the measurement procedure.
    • William W. Rozeboom (January 1969). "Reviewed Work: Statistical Theories of Mental Test Scores". American Educational Research Journal. 6 (1): 112–116. doi:10.2307/1162101. JSTOR 1162101.
  10. ^ Sheskin, David J. (2007). Handbook of Parametric and Nonparametric Statistical Procedures (Fourth ed.). Boca Raton: Chapman & Hall/CRC. p. 3. ISBN 978-1-58488-814-7. Although in practice IQ and most other human characteristics measured by psychological tests (such as anxiety, introversion, self esteem, etc.) are treated as interval scales, many researchers would argue that they are more appropriately categorized as ordinal scales. Such arguments would be based on the fact that such measures do not really meet the requirements of an interval scale, because it cannot be demonstrated that equal numerical differences at different points on the scale are comparable.
  11. ^ Mussen, Paul Henry (1973). Psychology: An Introduction. Lexington (MA): Heath. p. 363. ISBN 978-0-669-61382-7. The I.Q. is essentially a rank; there are no true "units" of intellectual ability.
  12. ^ Truch, Steve (1993). The WISC-III Companion: A Guide to Interpretation and Educational Intervention. Austin (TX): Pro-Ed. p. 35. ISBN 978-0-89079-585-9. An IQ score is not an equal-interval score, as is evident in Table A.4 in the WISC-III manual.
  13. ^ Bartholomew, David J. (2004). Measuring Intelligence: Facts and Fallacies. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 50. ISBN 978-0-521-54478-8. When we come to quantities like IQ or g, as we are presently able to measure them, we shall see later that we have an even lower level of measurement—an ordinal level. This means that the numbers we assign to individuals can only be used to rank them—the number tells us where the individual comes in the rank order and nothing else.
  14. ^ Eysenck, Hans (1998). Intelligence: A New Look. New Brunswick (NJ): Transaction Publishers. pp. 24–25. ISBN 978-1-56000-360-1. Ideally, a scale of measurement should have a true zero-point and identical intervals. . . . Scales of hardness lack these advantages, and so does IQ. There is no absolute zero, and a 10-point difference may carry different meanings at different points of the scale.
  15. ^ Mackintosh, N. J. (1998). IQ and Human Intelligence. Oxford: Oxford University Press. pp. 30–31. ISBN 978-0-19-852367-3. In the jargon of psychological measurement theory, IQ is an ordinal scale, where we are simply rank-ordering people. . . . It is not even appropriate to claim that the 10-point difference between IQ scores of 110 and 100 is the same as the 10-point difference between IQs of 160 and 150
  16. ^ a b Velleman, Paul F.; Wilkinson, Leland (1993). "Nominal, ordinal, interval, and ratio typologies are misleading". The American Statistician. 47 (1): 65–72. doi:10.2307/2684788. JSTOR 2684788.
  17. ^ Hand, David J. (2017). "Measurement: A Very Short Introduction—Rejoinder to discussion". Measurement: Interdisciplinary Research and Perspectives. 15 (1): 37–50. doi:10.1080/15366367.2017.1360022. hdl:10044/1/50223. S2CID 148934577.
  18. ^ Nelder, J. A. (1990). The knowledge needed to computerise the analysis and interpretation of statistical information. In Expert systems and artificial intelligence: the need for information about data. Library Association Report, London, March, 23–27.
  19. ^ van den Berg, G. (1991). Choosing an analysis method. Leiden: DSWO Press
  20. ^ Wolman, Abel G (2006). "Measurement and meaningfulness in conservation science". Conservation Biology. 20 (6): 1626–1634. doi:10.1111/j.1523-1739.2006.00531.x. PMID 17181798. S2CID 21372776.
  21. ^ . Institute for Digital Research and Education. University of California, Los Angeles. Archived from the original on 2016-01-25. Retrieved 7 February 2016.

Further reading

  • Alper, T. M. (1985). "A note on real measurement structures of scale type (m, m + 1)". Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 29: 73–81. doi:10.1016/0022-2496(85)90019-7.
  • Alper, T. M. (1987). "A classification of all order-preserving homeomorphism groups of the reals that satisfy finite uniqueness". Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 31 (2): 135–154. doi:10.1016/0022-2496(87)90012-5.
  • Briand, L. & El Emam, K. & Morasca, S. (1995). On the Application of Measurement Theory in Software Engineering. Empirical Software Engineering, 1, 61–88. [On line]
  • Cliff, N. (1996). Ordinal Methods for Behavioral Data Analysis. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum. ISBN 0-8058-1333-0
  • Cliff, N. & Keats, J. A. (2003). Ordinal Measurement in the Behavioral Sciences. Mahwah, NJ: Erlbaum. ISBN 0-8058-2093-0
  • Lord, Frederic M (December 1953). (PDF). American Psychologist. 8 (12): 750–751. doi:10.1037/h0063675. Archived from the original (PDF) on 20 July 2011. Retrieved 16 September 2010.
See also reprints in:
  • Readings in Statistics, Ch. 3, (Haber, A., Runyon, R. P., and Badia, P.) Reading, Mass: Addison–Wesley, 1970
  • Maranell, Gary Michael, ed. (2007). "Chapter 31". Scaling: A Sourcebook for Behavioral Scientists. New Brunswick, New Jersey & London, UK: Aldine Transaction. pp. 402–405. ISBN 978-0-202-36175-8. Retrieved 16 September 2010.
  • Hardcastle, G. L. (1995). "S. S. Stevens and the origins of operationism". Philosophy of Science. 62 (3): 404–424. doi:10.1086/289875. S2CID 170941474.
  • Lord, F. M., & Novick, M. R. (1968). Statistical theories of mental test scores. Reading, MA: Addison–Wesley.
  • Luce, R. D. (1986). "Uniqueness and homogeneity of ordered relational structures". Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 30 (4): 391–415. doi:10.1016/0022-2496(86)90017-9. S2CID 13567893.
  • Luce, R. D. (1987). "Measurement structures with Archimedean ordered translation groups". Order. 4 (2): 165–189. doi:10.1007/bf00337695. S2CID 16080432.
  • Luce, R. D. (1997). "Quantification and symmetry: commentary on Michell 'Quantitative science and the definition of measurement in psychology'". British Journal of Psychology. 88 (3): 395–398. doi:10.1111/j.2044-8295.1997.tb02645.x.
  • Luce, R. D. (2000). Utility of uncertain gains and losses: measurement theoretic and experimental approaches. Mahwah, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum.
  • Luce, R. D. (2001). "Conditions equivalent to unit representations of ordered relational structures". Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 45 (1): 81–98. doi:10.1006/jmps.1999.1293. PMID 11178923. S2CID 12231599.
  • Luce, R. D.; Tukey, J. W. (1964). "Simultaneous conjoint measurement: a new scale type of fundamental measurement". Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 1: 1–27. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.334.5018. doi:10.1016/0022-2496(64)90015-x.
  • Michell, J. (1986). "Measurement scales and statistics: a clash of paradigms". Psychological Bulletin. 100 (3): 398–407. doi:10.1037/0033-2909.100.3.398.
  • Michell, J. (1997). "Quantitative science and the definition of measurement in psychology". British Journal of Psychology. 88 (3): 355–383. doi:10.1111/j.2044-8295.1997.tb02641.x. S2CID 143169737.
  • Michell, J. (1999). Measurement in Psychology – A critical history of a methodological concept. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Michell, J. (2008). "Is psychometrics pathological science?". Measurement – Interdisciplinary Research & Perspectives. 6 (1–2): 7–24. doi:10.1080/15366360802035489. S2CID 146702066.
  • Narens, L. (1981a). "A general theory of ratio scalability with remarks about the measurement-theoretic concept of meaningfulness". Theory and Decision. 13: 1–70. doi:10.1007/bf02342603. S2CID 119401596.
  • Narens, L. (1981b). "On the scales of measurement". Journal of Mathematical Psychology. 24 (3): 249–275. doi:10.1016/0022-2496(81)90045-6.
  • Rasch, G. (1960). Probabilistic models for some intelligence and attainment tests. Copenhagen: Danish Institute for Educational Research.
  • Rozeboom, W. W. (1966). "Scaling theory and the nature of measurement". Synthese. 16 (2): 170–233. doi:10.1007/bf00485356. S2CID 46970420.
  • Stevens, S. S. (June 7, 1946). (PDF). Science. 103 (2684): 677–680. Bibcode:1946Sci...103..677S. doi:10.1126/science.103.2684.677. PMID 17750512. Archived from the original (PDF) on 25 November 2011. Retrieved 16 September 2010.
  • Stevens, S. S. (1951). Mathematics, measurement and psychophysics. In S. S. Stevens (Ed.), Handbook of experimental psychology (pp. 1–49). New York: Wiley.
  • Stevens, S. S. (1975). Psychophysics. New York: Wiley.
  • von Eye, A. (2005). "Review of Cliff and Keats, Ordinal measurement in the behavioral sciences". Applied Psychological Measurement. 29 (5): 401–403. doi:10.1177/0146621605276938. S2CID 220583753.

level, measurement, confused, with, units, measurement, level, sensor, level, logarithmic, quantity, nominal, variable, redirects, here, economics, usage, real, versus, nominal, value, economics, scale, measure, classification, that, describes, nature, informa. Not to be confused with Units of measurement Level sensor or Level logarithmic quantity Nominal variable redirects here For the economics usage see Real versus nominal value economics Level of measurement or scale of measure is a classification that describes the nature of information within the values assigned to variables 1 Psychologist Stanley Smith Stevens developed the best known classification with four levels or scales of measurement nominal ordinal interval and ratio 1 2 This framework of distinguishing levels of measurement originated in psychology and is widely criticized by scholars in other disciplines 3 Other classifications include those by Mosteller and Tukey 4 and by Chrisman 5 Contents 1 Stevens s typology 1 1 Overview 1 1 1 Comparison 1 2 Nominal level 1 2 1 Mathematical operations 1 2 2 Central tendency 1 3 Ordinal scale 1 3 1 Central tendency 1 4 Interval scale 1 4 1 Central tendency and statistical dispersion 1 5 Ratio scale 1 5 1 Central tendency and statistical dispersion 2 Debate on Stevens s typology 2 1 Other proposed typologies 2 1 1 Mosteller and Tukey s typology 1977 2 1 2 Chrisman s typology 1998 2 2 Scale types and Stevens s operational theory of measurement 2 2 1 Same variable may be different scale type depending on context 3 See also 4 References 5 Further readingStevens s typology EditOverview Edit Stevens proposed his typology in a 1946 Science article titled On the theory of scales of measurement 2 In that article Stevens claimed that all measurement in science was conducted using four different types of scales that he called nominal ordinal interval and ratio unifying both qualitative which are described by his nominal type and quantitative to a different degree all the rest of his scales The concept of scale types later received the mathematical rigour that it lacked at its inception with the work of mathematical psychologists Theodore Alper 1985 1987 Louis Narens 1981a b and R Duncan Luce 1986 1987 2001 As Luce 1997 p 395 wrote S S Stevens 1946 1951 1975 claimed that what counted was having an interval or ratio scale Subsequent research has given meaning to this assertion but given his attempts to invoke scale type ideas it is doubtful if he understood it himself no measurement theorist I know accepts Stevens s broad definition of measurement in our view the only sensible meaning for rule is empirically testable laws about the attribute Comparison Edit Incremental progress Measure property Mathematical operators Advanced operations Central tendency VariabilityNominal Classification membership Grouping Mode Qualitative variationOrdinal Comparison level gt lt Sorting Median Range interquartile rangeInterval Difference affinity Comparison to a standard Arithmetic mean DeviationRatio Magnitude amount Ratio Geometric mean harmonic mean Coefficient of variation studentized rangeNominal level Edit The nominal type differentiates between items or subjects based only on their names or meta categories and other qualitative classifications they belong to thus dichotomous data involves the construction of classifications as well as the classification of items Discovery of an exception to a classification can be viewed as progress Numbers may be used to represent the variables but the numbers do not have numerical value or relationship for example a globally unique identifier Examples of these classifications include gender nationality ethnicity language genre style biological species and form 6 7 In a university one could also use hall of affiliation as an example Other concrete examples are in grammar the parts of speech noun verb preposition article pronoun etc in politics power projection hard power soft power etc in biology the taxonomic ranks below domains Archaea Bacteria and Eukarya in software engineering type of faults specification faults design faults and code faultsNominal scales were often called qualitative scales and measurements made on qualitative scales were called qualitative data However the rise of qualitative research has made this usage confusing If numbers are assigned as labels in nominal measurement they have no specific numerical value or meaning No form of arithmetic computation etc may be performed on nominal measures The nominal level is the lowest measurement level used from a statistical point of view Mathematical operations Edit Equality and other operations that can be defined in terms of equality such as inequality and set membership are the only non trivial operations that generically apply to objects of the nominal type Central tendency Edit The mode i e the most common item is allowed as the measure of central tendency for the nominal type On the other hand the median i e the middle ranked item makes no sense for the nominal type of data since ranking is meaningless for the nominal type 8 Ordinal scale Edit Further information Ordinal data The ordinal type allows for rank order 1st 2nd 3rd etc by which data can be sorted but still does not allow for a relative degree of difference between them Examples include on one hand dichotomous data with dichotomous or dichotomized values such as sick vs healthy when measuring health guilty vs not guilty when making judgments in courts wrong false vs right true when measuring truth value and on the other hand non dichotomous data consisting of a spectrum of values such as completely agree mostly agree mostly disagree completely disagree when measuring opinion The ordinal scale places events in order but there is no attempt to make the intervals of the scale equal in terms of some rule Rank orders represent ordinal scales and are frequently used in research relating to qualitative phenomena A student s rank in his graduation class involves the use of an ordinal scale One has to be very careful in making a statement about scores based on ordinal scales For instance if Devi s position in his class is 10 and Ganga s position is 40 it cannot be said that Devi s position is four times as good as that of Ganga The statement would make no sense at all Ordinal scales only permit the ranking of items from highest to lowest Ordinal measures have no absolute values and the real differences between adjacent ranks may not be equal All that can be said is that one person is higher or lower on the scale than another but more precise comparisons cannot be made Thus the use of an ordinal scale implies a statement of greater than or less than an equality statement is also acceptable without our being able to state how much greater or less The real difference between ranks 1 and 2 for instance may be more or less than the difference between ranks 5 and 6 Since the numbers of this scale have only a rank meaning the appropriate measure of central tendency is the median A percentile or quartile measure is used for measuring dispersion Correlations are restricted to various rank order methods Measures of statistical significance are restricted to the non parametric methods R M Kothari 2004 Central tendency Edit The median i e middle ranked item is allowed as the measure of central tendency however the mean or average as the measure of central tendency is not allowed The mode is allowed In 1946 Stevens observed that psychological measurement such as measurement of opinions usually operates on ordinal scales thus means and standard deviations have no validity but they can be used to get ideas for how to improve operationalization of variables used in questionnaires Most psychological data collected by psychometric instruments and tests measuring cognitive and other abilities are ordinal although some theoreticians have argued they can be treated as interval or ratio scales However there is little prima facie evidence to suggest that such attributes are anything more than ordinal Cliff 1996 Cliff amp Keats 2003 Michell 2008 9 In particular 10 IQ scores reflect an ordinal scale in which all scores are meaningful for comparison only 11 12 13 There is no absolute zero and a 10 point difference may carry different meanings at different points of the scale 14 15 Interval scale Edit The interval type allows for the degree of difference between items but not the ratio between them Examples include temperature scales with the Celsius scale which has two defined points the freezing and boiling point of water at specific conditions and then separated into 100 intervals date when measured from an arbitrary epoch such as AD location in Cartesian coordinates and direction measured in degrees from true or magnetic north Ratios are not meaningful since 20 C cannot be said to be twice as hot as 10 C unlike temperature in Kelvins nor can multiplication division be carried out between any two dates directly However ratios of differences can be expressed for example one difference can be twice another Interval type variables are sometimes also called scaled variables but the formal mathematical term is an affine space in this case an affine line Central tendency and statistical dispersion Edit The mode median and arithmetic mean are allowed to measure central tendency of interval variables while measures of statistical dispersion include range and standard deviation Since one can only divide by differences one cannot define measures that require some ratios such as the coefficient of variation More subtly while one can define moments about the origin only central moments are meaningful since the choice of origin is arbitrary One can define standardized moments since ratios of differences are meaningful but one cannot define the coefficient of variation since the mean is a moment about the origin unlike the standard deviation which is the square root of a central moment Ratio scale Edit See also Positive real numbers Ratio scaleThe ratio type takes its name from the fact that measurement is the estimation of the ratio between a magnitude of a continuous quantity and a unit of measurement of the same kind Michell 1997 1999 Most measurement in the physical sciences and engineering is done on ratio scales Examples include mass length duration plane angle energy and electric charge In contrast to interval scales ratios can be compared using division Very informally many ratio scales can be described as specifying how much of something i e an amount or magnitude Ratio scale is often used to express an order of magnitude such as for temperature in Orders of magnitude temperature Central tendency and statistical dispersion Edit The geometric mean and the harmonic mean are allowed to measure the central tendency in addition to the mode median and arithmetic mean The studentized range and the coefficient of variation are allowed to measure statistical dispersion All statistical measures are allowed because all necessary mathematical operations are defined for the ratio scale Debate on Stevens s typology EditWhile Stevens s typology is widely adopted it is still being challenged by other theoreticians particularly in the cases of the nominal and ordinal types Michell 1986 16 Some however have argued that the degree of discord can be overstated Hand says Basic psychology texts often begin with Stevens s framework and the ideas are ubiquitous Indeed the essential soundness of his hierarchy has been established for representational measurement by mathematicians determining the invariance properties of mappings from empirical systems to real number continua Certainly the ideas have been revised extended and elaborated but the remarkable thing is his insight given the relatively limited formal apparatus available to him and how many decades have passed since he coined them 17 Duncan 1986 objected to the use of the word measurement in relation to the nominal type but Stevens 1975 said of his own definition of measurement that the assignment can be any consistent rule The only rule not allowed would be random assignment for randomness amounts in effect to a nonrule The use of the mean as a measure of the central tendency for the ordinal type is still debatable among those who accept Stevens s typology Many behavioural scientists use the mean for ordinal data anyway This is often justified on the basis that the ordinal type in behavioural science is in fact somewhere between the true ordinal and interval types although the interval difference between two ordinal ranks is not constant it is often of the same order of magnitude For example applications of measurement models in educational contexts often indicate that total scores have a fairly linear relationship with measurements across the range of an assessment Thus some argue that so long as the unknown interval difference between ordinal scale ranks is not too variable interval scale statistics such as means can meaningfully be used on ordinal scale variables Statistical analysis software such as SPSS requires the user to select the appropriate measurement class for each variable This ensures that subsequent user errors cannot inadvertently perform meaningless analyses for example correlation analysis with a variable on a nominal level L L Thurstone made progress toward developing a justification for obtaining the interval type based on the law of comparative judgment A common application of the law is the analytic hierarchy process Further progress was made by Georg Rasch 1960 who developed the probabilistic Rasch model that provides a theoretical basis and justification for obtaining interval level measurements from counts of observations such as total scores on assessments Other proposed typologies Edit Typologies aside from Stevens s typology have been proposed For instance Mosteller and Tukey 1977 Nelder 1990 18 described continuous counts continuous ratios count ratios and categorical modes of data See also Chrisman 1998 van den Berg 1991 19 Mosteller and Tukey s typology 1977 Edit Mosteller and Tukey 4 noted that the four levels are not exhaustive and proposed Names Grades ordered labels like beginner intermediate advanced Ranks orders with 1 being the smallest or largest 2 the next smallest or largest and so on Counted fractions bound by 0 and 1 Counts non negative integers Amounts non negative real numbers Balances any real number For example percentages a variation on fractions in the Mosteller Tukey framework do not fit well into Stevens s framework No transformation is fully admissible 16 Chrisman s typology 1998 Edit Nicholas R Chrisman 5 introduced an expanded list of levels of measurement to account for various measurements that do not necessarily fit with the traditional notions of levels of measurement Measurements bound to a range and repeating like degrees in a circle clock time etc graded membership categories and other types of measurement do not fit to Stevens s original work leading to the introduction of six new levels of measurement for a total of ten Nominal Gradation of membership Ordinal Interval Log interval Extensive ratio Cyclical ratio Derived ratio Counts AbsoluteWhile some claim that the extended levels of measurement are rarely used outside of academic geography 20 graded membership is central to fuzzy set theory while absolute measurements include probabilities and the plausibility and ignorance in Dempster Shafer theory Cyclical ratio measurements include angles and times Counts appear to be ratio measurements but the scale is not arbitrary and fractional counts are commonly meaningless Log interval measurements are commonly displayed in stock market graphics All these types of measurements are commonly used outside academic geography and do not fit well to Stevens original work Scale types and Stevens s operational theory of measurement Edit The theory of scale types is the intellectual handmaiden to Stevens s operational theory of measurement which was to become definitive within psychology and the behavioral sciences citation needed despite Michell s characterization as its being quite at odds with measurement in the natural sciences Michell 1999 Essentially the operational theory of measurement was a reaction to the conclusions of a committee established in 1932 by the British Association for the Advancement of Science to investigate the possibility of genuine scientific measurement in the psychological and behavioral sciences This committee which became known as the Ferguson committee published a Final Report Ferguson et al 1940 p 245 in which Stevens s sone scale Stevens amp Davis 1938 was an object of criticism any law purporting to express a quantitative relation between sensation intensity and stimulus intensity is not merely false but is in fact meaningless unless and until a meaning can be given to the concept of addition as applied to sensation That is if Stevens s sone scale genuinely measured the intensity of auditory sensations then evidence for such sensations as being quantitative attributes needed to be produced The evidence needed was the presence of additive structure a concept comprehensively treated by the German mathematician Otto Holder Holder 1901 Given that the physicist and measurement theorist Norman Robert Campbell dominated the Ferguson committee s deliberations the committee concluded that measurement in the social sciences was impossible due to the lack of concatenation operations This conclusion was later rendered false by the discovery of the theory of conjoint measurement by Debreu 1960 and independently by Luce amp Tukey 1964 However Stevens s reaction was not to conduct experiments to test for the presence of additive structure in sensations but instead to render the conclusions of the Ferguson committee null and void by proposing a new theory of measurement Paraphrasing N R Campbell Final Report p 340 we may say that measurement in the broadest sense is defined as the assignment of numerals to objects and events according to rules Stevens 1946 p 677 Stevens was greatly influenced by the ideas of another Harvard academic the Nobel laureate physicist Percy Bridgman 1927 whose doctrine of operationism Stevens used to define measurement In Stevens s definition for example it is the use of a tape measure that defines length the object of measurement as being measurable and so by implication quantitative Critics of operationism object that it confuses the relations between two objects or events for properties of one of those of objects or events Hardcastle 1995 Michell 1999 Moyer 1981a b Rogers 1989 The Canadian measurement theorist William Rozeboom 1966 was an early and trenchant critic of Stevens s theory of scale types Same variable may be different scale type depending on context Edit Another issue is that the same variable may be a different scale type depending on how it is measured and on the goals of the analysis For example hair color is usually thought of as a nominal variable since it has no apparent ordering 21 However it is possible to order colors including hair colors in various ways including by hue this is known as colorimetry Hue is an interval level variable See also EditCohen s kappa Coherence units of measurement Hume s principle Inter rater reliability Logarithmic scale Ramsey Lewis method Set theory Statistical data type Transition linguistics References Edit a b Kirch Wilhelm ed 2008 Level of Measurement Encyclopedia of Public Health Vol 2 Springer pp 851 852 doi 10 1007 978 1 4020 5614 7 1971 ISBN 978 1 4020 5613 0 a b Stevens S S 7 June 1946 On the Theory of Scales of Measurement Science 103 2684 677 680 Bibcode 1946Sci 103 677S doi 10 1126 science 103 2684 677 PMID 17750512 S2CID 4667599 Michell J 1986 Measurement scales and statistics a clash of paradigms Psychological Bulletin 100 3 398 407 doi 10 1037 0033 2909 100 3 398 a b Mosteller Frederick 1977 Data analysis and regression a second course in statistics Reading Mass Addison Wesley Pub Co ISBN 978 0201048544 a b Chrisman Nicholas R 1998 Rethinking Levels of Measurement for Cartography Cartography and Geographic Information Science 25 4 231 242 doi 10 1559 152304098782383043 ISSN 1523 0406 via Taylor amp Francis subscription required Nominal measures are based on sets and depend on categories a la Aristotle Chrisman Nicholas March 1995 Beyond Stevens A revised approach to measurement for geographic information Retrieved 2014 08 25 Invariably one came up against fundamental physical limits to the accuracy of measurement The art of physical measurement seemed to be a matter of compromise of choosing between reciprocally related uncertainties Multiplying together the conjugate pairs of uncertainty limits mentioned however I found that they formed invariant products of not one but two distinct kinds The first group of limits were calculable a priori from a specification of the instrument The second group could be calculated only a posteriori from a specification of what was done with the instrument In the first case each unit of information would add one additional dimension conceptual category whereas in the second each unit would add one additional atomic fact pp 1 4 MacKay Donald M 1969 Information Mechanism and Meaning Cambridge MA MIT Press ISBN 0 262 63 032 X Manikandan S 2011 Measures of central tendency Median and mode Journal of Pharmacology and Pharmacotherapeutics 2 3 214 5 doi 10 4103 0976 500X 83300 PMC 3157145 PMID 21897729 Lord Frederic M Novick Melvin R Birnbaum Allan 1968 Statistical Theories of Mental Test Scores Reading MA Addison Wesley p 21 LCCN 68011394 Although formally speaking interval measurement can always be obtained by specification such specification is theoretically meaningful only if it is implied by the theory and model relevant to the measurement procedure William W Rozeboom January 1969 Reviewed Work Statistical Theories of Mental Test Scores American Educational Research Journal 6 1 112 116 doi 10 2307 1162101 JSTOR 1162101 Sheskin David J 2007 Handbook of Parametric and Nonparametric Statistical Procedures Fourth ed Boca Raton Chapman amp Hall CRC p 3 ISBN 978 1 58488 814 7 Although in practice IQ and most other human characteristics measured by psychological tests such as anxiety introversion self esteem etc are treated as interval scales many researchers would argue that they are more appropriately categorized as ordinal scales Such arguments would be based on the fact that such measures do not really meet the requirements of an interval scale because it cannot be demonstrated that equal numerical differences at different points on the scale are comparable Mussen Paul Henry 1973 Psychology An Introduction Lexington MA Heath p 363 ISBN 978 0 669 61382 7 The I Q is essentially a rank there are no true units of intellectual ability Truch Steve 1993 The WISC III Companion A Guide to Interpretation and Educational Intervention Austin TX Pro Ed p 35 ISBN 978 0 89079 585 9 An IQ score is not an equal interval score as is evident in Table A 4 in the WISC III manual Bartholomew David J 2004 Measuring Intelligence Facts and Fallacies Cambridge Cambridge University Press p 50 ISBN 978 0 521 54478 8 When we come to quantities like IQ or g as we are presently able to measure them we shall see later that we have an even lower level of measurement an ordinal level This means that the numbers we assign to individuals can only be used to rank them the number tells us where the individual comes in the rank order and nothing else Eysenck Hans 1998 Intelligence A New Look New Brunswick NJ Transaction Publishers pp 24 25 ISBN 978 1 56000 360 1 Ideally a scale of measurement should have a true zero point and identical intervals Scales of hardness lack these advantages and so does IQ There is no absolute zero and a 10 point difference may carry different meanings at different points of the scale Mackintosh N J 1998 IQ and Human Intelligence Oxford Oxford University Press pp 30 31 ISBN 978 0 19 852367 3 In the jargon of psychological measurement theory IQ is an ordinal scale where we are simply rank ordering people It is not even appropriate to claim that the 10 point difference between IQ scores of 110 and 100 is the same as the 10 point difference between IQs of 160 and 150 a b Velleman Paul F Wilkinson Leland 1993 Nominal ordinal interval and ratio typologies are misleading The American Statistician 47 1 65 72 doi 10 2307 2684788 JSTOR 2684788 Hand David J 2017 Measurement A Very Short Introduction Rejoinder to discussion Measurement Interdisciplinary Research and Perspectives 15 1 37 50 doi 10 1080 15366367 2017 1360022 hdl 10044 1 50223 S2CID 148934577 Nelder J A 1990 The knowledge needed to computerise the analysis and interpretation of statistical information In Expert systems and artificial intelligence the need for information about data Library Association Report London March 23 27 van den Berg G 1991 Choosing an analysis method Leiden DSWO Press Wolman Abel G 2006 Measurement and meaningfulness in conservation science Conservation Biology 20 6 1626 1634 doi 10 1111 j 1523 1739 2006 00531 x PMID 17181798 S2CID 21372776 What is the difference between categorical ordinal and interval variables Institute for Digital Research and Education University of California Los Angeles Archived from the original on 2016 01 25 Retrieved 7 February 2016 Further reading EditThis further reading section may contain inappropriate or excessive suggestions that may not follow Wikipedia s guidelines Please ensure that only a reasonable number of balanced topical reliable and notable further reading suggestions are given removing less relevant or redundant publications with the same point of view where appropriate Consider utilising appropriate texts as inline sources or creating a separate bibliography article June 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message Alper T M 1985 A note on real measurement structures of scale type m m 1 Journal of Mathematical Psychology 29 73 81 doi 10 1016 0022 2496 85 90019 7 Alper T M 1987 A classification of all order preserving homeomorphism groups of the reals that satisfy finite uniqueness Journal of Mathematical Psychology 31 2 135 154 doi 10 1016 0022 2496 87 90012 5 Briand L amp El Emam K amp Morasca S 1995 On the Application of Measurement Theory in Software Engineering Empirical Software Engineering 1 61 88 On line https web archive org web 20070926232755 http www2 umassd edu swpi ISERN isern 95 04 pdf Cliff N 1996 Ordinal Methods for Behavioral Data Analysis Mahwah NJ Lawrence Erlbaum ISBN 0 8058 1333 0 Cliff N amp Keats J A 2003 Ordinal Measurement in the Behavioral Sciences Mahwah NJ Erlbaum ISBN 0 8058 2093 0 Lord Frederic M December 1953 On the Statistical Treatment of Football Numbers PDF American Psychologist 8 12 750 751 doi 10 1037 h0063675 Archived from the original PDF on 20 July 2011 Retrieved 16 September 2010 See also reprints in Readings in Statistics Ch 3 Haber A Runyon R P and Badia P Reading Mass Addison Wesley 1970 Maranell Gary Michael ed 2007 Chapter 31 Scaling A Sourcebook for Behavioral Scientists New Brunswick New Jersey amp London UK Aldine Transaction pp 402 405 ISBN 978 0 202 36175 8 Retrieved 16 September 2010 Hardcastle G L 1995 S S Stevens and the origins of operationism Philosophy of Science 62 3 404 424 doi 10 1086 289875 S2CID 170941474 Lord F M amp Novick M R 1968 Statistical theories of mental test scores Reading MA Addison Wesley Luce R D 1986 Uniqueness and homogeneity of ordered relational structures Journal of Mathematical Psychology 30 4 391 415 doi 10 1016 0022 2496 86 90017 9 S2CID 13567893 Luce R D 1987 Measurement structures with Archimedean ordered translation groups Order 4 2 165 189 doi 10 1007 bf00337695 S2CID 16080432 Luce R D 1997 Quantification and symmetry commentary on Michell Quantitative science and the definition of measurement in psychology British Journal of Psychology 88 3 395 398 doi 10 1111 j 2044 8295 1997 tb02645 x Luce R D 2000 Utility of uncertain gains and losses measurement theoretic and experimental approaches Mahwah N J Lawrence Erlbaum Luce R D 2001 Conditions equivalent to unit representations of ordered relational structures Journal of Mathematical Psychology 45 1 81 98 doi 10 1006 jmps 1999 1293 PMID 11178923 S2CID 12231599 Luce R D Tukey J W 1964 Simultaneous conjoint measurement a new scale type of fundamental measurement Journal of Mathematical Psychology 1 1 27 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 334 5018 doi 10 1016 0022 2496 64 90015 x Michell J 1986 Measurement scales and statistics a clash of paradigms Psychological Bulletin 100 3 398 407 doi 10 1037 0033 2909 100 3 398 Michell J 1997 Quantitative science and the definition of measurement in psychology British Journal of Psychology 88 3 355 383 doi 10 1111 j 2044 8295 1997 tb02641 x S2CID 143169737 Michell J 1999 Measurement in Psychology A critical history of a methodological concept Cambridge Cambridge University Press Michell J 2008 Is psychometrics pathological science Measurement Interdisciplinary Research amp Perspectives 6 1 2 7 24 doi 10 1080 15366360802035489 S2CID 146702066 Narens L 1981a A general theory of ratio scalability with remarks about the measurement theoretic concept of meaningfulness Theory and Decision 13 1 70 doi 10 1007 bf02342603 S2CID 119401596 Narens L 1981b On the scales of measurement Journal of Mathematical Psychology 24 3 249 275 doi 10 1016 0022 2496 81 90045 6 Rasch G 1960 Probabilistic models for some intelligence and attainment tests Copenhagen Danish Institute for Educational Research Rozeboom W W 1966 Scaling theory and the nature of measurement Synthese 16 2 170 233 doi 10 1007 bf00485356 S2CID 46970420 Stevens S S June 7 1946 On the Theory of Scales of Measurement PDF Science 103 2684 677 680 Bibcode 1946Sci 103 677S doi 10 1126 science 103 2684 677 PMID 17750512 Archived from the original PDF on 25 November 2011 Retrieved 16 September 2010 Stevens S S 1951 Mathematics measurement and psychophysics In S S Stevens Ed Handbook of experimental psychology pp 1 49 New York Wiley Stevens S S 1975 Psychophysics New York Wiley von Eye A 2005 Review of Cliff and Keats Ordinal measurement in the behavioral sciences Applied Psychological Measurement 29 5 401 403 doi 10 1177 0146621605276938 S2CID 220583753 Wikiversity has learning resources about Level of measurement Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Level of measurement amp oldid 1141908572, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.