fbpx
Wikipedia

Sheffer stroke

In Boolean functions and propositional calculus, the Sheffer stroke denotes a logical operation that is equivalent to the negation of the conjunction operation, expressed in ordinary language as "not both". It is also called non-conjunction, or alternative denial[1] (since it says in effect that at least one of its operands is false), or NAND ("not and").[1] In digital electronics, it corresponds to the NAND gate. It is named after Henry Maurice Sheffer and written as or as or as or as in Polish notation by Łukasiewicz (but not as ||, often used to represent disjunction).

Sheffer stroke
NAND
Definition
Truth table
Logic gate
Normal forms
Disjunctive
Conjunctive
Zhegalkin polynomial
Post's lattices
0-preservingno
1-preservingno
Monotoneno
Affineno

Its dual is the NOR operator (also known as the Peirce arrow, Quine dagger or Webb operator). Like its dual, NAND can be used by itself, without any other logical operator, to constitute a logical formal system (making NAND functionally complete). This property makes the NAND gate crucial to modern digital electronics, including its use in computer processor design.

Definition edit

The non-conjunction is a logical operation on two logical values. It produces a value of true, if — and only if — at least one of the propositions is false.

Truth table edit

The truth table of   is as follows.

   
FFT
FTT
TFT
TTF

Logical equivalences edit

The Sheffer stroke of   and   is the negation of their conjunction

         
           

By De Morgan's laws, this is also equivalent to the disjunction of the negations of   and  

             
             

Alternative notations and names edit

Peirce was the first to show the functional completeness of non-conjunction (representing this as  ) but didn't publish his result.[2][3] Peirce's editor added  ) for non-disjunction[citation needed].[3]

In 1911, Stamm was the first to publish a proof of the completeness of non-conjunction, representing this with   (the Stamm hook)[4] and non-disjunction in print at the first time and showed their functional completeness.[5]

In 1913, Sheffer described non-disjunction using   and showed its functional completeness. Sheffer also used   for non-disjunction.[citation needed] Many people, beginning with Nicod in 1917, and followed by Whitehead, Russell and many others, mistakenly thought Sheffer has described non-conjunction using  , naming this the Sheffer Stroke.

In 1928, Hilbert and Ackermann described non-conjunction with the operator  .[6][7]

In 1929, Łukasiewicz used   in   for non-conjunction in his Polish notation.[8]

An alternative notation for non-conjunction is  . It is not clear who first introduced this notation, although the corresponding   for non-disjunction was used by Quine in 1940,.[9]

History edit

The stroke is named after Henry Maurice Sheffer, who in 1913 published a paper in the Transactions of the American Mathematical Society[10] providing an axiomatization of Boolean algebras using the stroke, and proved its equivalence to a standard formulation thereof by Huntington employing the familiar operators of propositional logic (AND, OR, NOT). Because of self-duality of Boolean algebras, Sheffer's axioms are equally valid for either of the NAND or NOR operations in place of the stroke. Sheffer interpreted the stroke as a sign for nondisjunction (NOR) in his paper, mentioning non-conjunction only in a footnote and without a special sign for it. It was Jean Nicod who first used the stroke as a sign for non-conjunction (NAND) in a paper of 1917 and which has since become current practice.[11][12] Russell and Whitehead used the Sheffer stroke in the 1927 second edition of Principia Mathematica and suggested it as a replacement for the "OR" and "NOT" operations of the first edition.

Charles Sanders Peirce (1880) had discovered the functional completeness of NAND or NOR more than 30 years earlier, using the term ampheck (for 'cutting both ways'), but he never published his finding. Two years before Sheffer, Edward Stamm [pl] also described the NAND and NOR operators and showed that the other Boolean operations could be expressed by it.[5]

Properties edit

NAND does not possess any of the following five properties, each of which is required to be absent from, and the absence of all of which is sufficient for, at least one member of a set of functionally complete operators: truth-preservation, falsity-preservation, linearity, monotonicity, self-duality. (An operator is truth- (or falsity-)preserving if its value is truth (falsity) whenever all of its arguments are truth (falsity).) Therefore {NAND} is a functionally complete set.

This can also be realized as follows: All three elements of the functionally complete set {AND, OR, NOT} can be constructed using only NAND. Thus the set {NAND} must be functionally complete as well.

Other Boolean operations in terms of the Sheffer stroke edit

Expressed in terms of NAND  , the usual operators of propositional logic are:

                 
                 
   
                                 
                                 
   
                 
                 
 
                 
                 
   
                 
                 

Functional completeness edit

The Sheffer stroke, taken by itself, is a functionally complete set of connectives.[13][14] This can be proved by first showing, with a truth table, that   is truth-functionally equivalent to  .[15] Then, since   is truth-functionally equivalent to  ,[15] and   is equivalent to  ,[15] the Sheffer stroke suffices to define the set of connectives  ,[15] which is shown to be truth-functionally complete by the Disjunctive Normal Form Theorem.[15]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b Howson, Colin (1997). Logic with trees: an introduction to symbolic logic. London; New York: Routledge. p. 43. ISBN 978-0-415-13342-5.
  2. ^ Peirce, C. S. (1933) [1880]. "A Boolian Algebra with One Constant". In Hartshorne, C.; Weiss, P. (eds.). Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume IV The Simplest Mathematics. Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. pp. 13–18.
  3. ^ a b Peirce, C. S. (1933) [1902]. "The Simplest Mathematics". In Hartshorne, C.; Weiss, P. (eds.). Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce, Volume IV The Simplest Mathematics. Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. pp. 189–262.
  4. ^ Zach, R. (2023-02-18). "Sheffer stroke before Sheffer: Edward Stamm". Retrieved 2023-07-02.
  5. ^ a b Stamm, Edward Bronisław [in Polish] (1911). "Beitrag zur Algebra der Logik". Monatshefte für Mathematik und Physik (in German). 22 (1): 137–149. doi:10.1007/BF01742795. S2CID 119816758.
  6. ^ Hilbert, D.; Ackermann, W. (1928). Grundzügen der theoretischen Logik (in German) (1 ed.). Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer. p. 9.
  7. ^ Hilbert, D.; Ackermann, W. (1950). Luce, R. E. (ed.). Principles of Mathematical Logic. Translated by Hammond, L. M.; Leckie, G. G.; Steinhardt, F. New York: Chelsea Publishing Company. p. 11.
  8. ^ Łukasiewicz, J. (1958) [1929]. Elementy logiki matematycznej (in Polish) (2 ed.). Warszawa: Państwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe.
  9. ^ Quine, W. V (1981) [1940]. Mathematical Logic (Revised ed.). Cambridge, London, New York, New Rochelle, Melbourne and Sydney: Harvard University Press. p. 45.
  10. ^ Sheffer, Henry Maurice (1913). "A set of five independent postulates for Boolean algebras, with application to logical constants". Transactions of the American Mathematical Society. 14 (4): 481–488. doi:10.2307/1988701. JSTOR 1988701.
  11. ^ Nicod, Jean George Pierre (1917). "A Reduction in the Number of Primitive Propositions of Logic". Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society. 19: 32–41.
  12. ^ Church, Alonzo (1956). Introduction to mathematical logic. Vol. 1. Princeton University Press. p. 134.
  13. ^ Weisstein, Eric W. "Propositional Calculus". mathworld.wolfram.com. Retrieved 2024-03-22.
  14. ^ Franks, Curtis (2023), "Propositional Logic", in Zalta, Edward N.; Nodelman, Uri (eds.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2023 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2024-03-22
  15. ^ a b c d e Howson, Colin (1997). Logic with trees: an introduction to symbolic logic. London; New York: Routledge. pp. 41–43. ISBN 978-0-415-13342-5.

Further reading edit

External links edit

sheffer, stroke, boolean, functions, propositional, calculus, denotes, logical, operation, that, equivalent, negation, conjunction, operation, expressed, ordinary, language, both, also, called, conjunction, alternative, denial, since, says, effect, that, least. In Boolean functions and propositional calculus the Sheffer stroke denotes a logical operation that is equivalent to the negation of the conjunction operation expressed in ordinary language as not both It is also called non conjunction or alternative denial 1 since it says in effect that at least one of its operands is false or NAND not and 1 In digital electronics it corresponds to the NAND gate It is named after Henry Maurice Sheffer and written as displaystyle mid or as displaystyle uparrow or as displaystyle overline wedge or as D p q displaystyle Dpq in Polish notation by Lukasiewicz but not as often used to represent disjunction Sheffer strokeNANDDefinitionx y displaystyle overline x cdot y Truth table 0111 displaystyle 0111 Logic gateNormal formsDisjunctivex y displaystyle overline x overline y Conjunctivex y displaystyle overline x overline y Zhegalkin polynomial1 x y displaystyle 1 oplus xy Post s lattices0 preservingno1 preservingnoMonotonenoAffinenovte Its dual is the NOR operator also known as the Peirce arrow Quine dagger or Webb operator Like its dual NAND can be used by itself without any other logical operator to constitute a logical formal system making NAND functionally complete This property makes the NAND gate crucial to modern digital electronics including its use in computer processor design Contents 1 Definition 1 1 Truth table 1 2 Logical equivalences 2 Alternative notations and names 3 History 4 Properties 5 Other Boolean operations in terms of the Sheffer stroke 6 Functional completeness 7 See also 8 References 9 Further reading 10 External linksDefinition editThe non conjunction is a logical operation on two logical values It produces a value of true if and only if at least one of the propositions is false Truth table edit The truth table of A B displaystyle A uparrow B nbsp is as follows A displaystyle A nbsp B displaystyle B nbsp A B displaystyle A uparrow B nbsp FFTFTTTFTTTF Logical equivalences edit The Sheffer stroke of P displaystyle P nbsp and Q displaystyle Q nbsp is the negation of their conjunction P Q displaystyle P uparrow Q nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp P Q displaystyle neg P land Q nbsp nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp displaystyle neg nbsp nbsp By De Morgan s laws this is also equivalent to the disjunction of the negations of P displaystyle P nbsp and Q displaystyle Q nbsp P Q displaystyle P uparrow Q nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp P displaystyle neg P nbsp displaystyle lor nbsp Q displaystyle neg Q nbsp nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp nbsp displaystyle lor nbsp nbsp Alternative notations and names editPeirce was the first to show the functional completeness of non conjunction representing this as displaystyle overline curlywedge nbsp but didn t publish his result 2 3 Peirce s editor added displaystyle overline curlywedge nbsp for non disjunction citation needed 3 In 1911 Stamm was the first to publish a proof of the completeness of non conjunction representing this with displaystyle sim nbsp the Stamm hook 4 and non disjunction in print at the first time and showed their functional completeness 5 In 1913 Sheffer described non disjunction using displaystyle mid nbsp and showed its functional completeness Sheffer also used displaystyle wedge nbsp for non disjunction citation needed Many people beginning with Nicod in 1917 and followed by Whitehead Russell and many others mistakenly thought Sheffer has described non conjunction using displaystyle mid nbsp naming this the Sheffer Stroke In 1928 Hilbert and Ackermann described non conjunction with the operator displaystyle nbsp 6 7 In 1929 Lukasiewicz used D displaystyle D nbsp in D p q displaystyle Dpq nbsp for non conjunction in his Polish notation 8 An alternative notation for non conjunction is displaystyle uparrow nbsp It is not clear who first introduced this notation although the corresponding displaystyle downarrow nbsp for non disjunction was used by Quine in 1940 9 History editThe stroke is named after Henry Maurice Sheffer who in 1913 published a paper in the Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 10 providing an axiomatization of Boolean algebras using the stroke and proved its equivalence to a standard formulation thereof by Huntington employing the familiar operators of propositional logic AND OR NOT Because of self duality of Boolean algebras Sheffer s axioms are equally valid for either of the NAND or NOR operations in place of the stroke Sheffer interpreted the stroke as a sign for nondisjunction NOR in his paper mentioning non conjunction only in a footnote and without a special sign for it It was Jean Nicod who first used the stroke as a sign for non conjunction NAND in a paper of 1917 and which has since become current practice 11 12 Russell and Whitehead used the Sheffer stroke in the 1927 second edition of Principia Mathematica and suggested it as a replacement for the OR and NOT operations of the first edition Charles Sanders Peirce 1880 had discovered the functional completeness of NAND or NOR more than 30 years earlier using the term ampheck for cutting both ways but he never published his finding Two years before Sheffer Edward Stamm pl also described the NAND and NOR operators and showed that the other Boolean operations could be expressed by it 5 Properties editNAND does not possess any of the following five properties each of which is required to be absent from and the absence of all of which is sufficient for at least one member of a set of functionally complete operators truth preservation falsity preservation linearity monotonicity self duality An operator is truth or falsity preserving if its value is truth falsity whenever all of its arguments are truth falsity Therefore NAND is a functionally complete set This can also be realized as follows All three elements of the functionally complete set AND OR NOT can be constructed using only NAND Thus the set NAND must be functionally complete as well Other Boolean operations in terms of the Sheffer stroke editExpressed in terms of NAND displaystyle uparrow nbsp the usual operators of propositional logic are P displaystyle neg P nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp P displaystyle P nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp P displaystyle P nbsp nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp nbsp P Q displaystyle P rightarrow Q nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp P displaystyle P nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp Q Q displaystyle Q uparrow Q nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp P displaystyle P nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp P Q displaystyle P uparrow Q nbsp nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp nbsp P Q displaystyle P leftrightarrow Q nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp P Q displaystyle P uparrow Q nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp P P Q Q displaystyle P uparrow P uparrow Q uparrow Q nbsp nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp nbsp P Q displaystyle P land Q nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp P Q displaystyle P uparrow Q nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp P Q displaystyle P uparrow Q nbsp nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp nbsp P Q displaystyle P lor Q nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp P P displaystyle P uparrow P nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp Q Q displaystyle Q uparrow Q nbsp nbsp displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp nbsp displaystyle uparrow nbsp nbsp Functional completeness editThe Sheffer stroke taken by itself is a functionally complete set of connectives 13 14 This can be proved by first showing with a truth table that A displaystyle neg A nbsp is truth functionally equivalent to A A displaystyle A uparrow A nbsp 15 Then since A B displaystyle A uparrow B nbsp is truth functionally equivalent to A B displaystyle neg A land B nbsp 15 and A B displaystyle A lor B nbsp is equivalent to A B displaystyle neg neg A land neg B nbsp 15 the Sheffer stroke suffices to define the set of connectives displaystyle land lor neg nbsp 15 which is shown to be truth functionally complete by the Disjunctive Normal Form Theorem 15 See also editBoolean domain CMOS Gate equivalent GE Logical graph Minimal axioms for Boolean algebra NAND flash memory NAND logic Peirce s law Peirce arrow NOR Sole sufficient operatorReferences edit a b Howson Colin 1997 Logic with trees an introduction to symbolic logic London New York Routledge p 43 ISBN 978 0 415 13342 5 Peirce C S 1933 1880 A Boolian Algebra with One Constant In Hartshorne C Weiss P eds Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce Volume IV The Simplest Mathematics Massachusetts Harvard University Press pp 13 18 a b Peirce C S 1933 1902 The Simplest Mathematics In Hartshorne C Weiss P eds Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce Volume IV The Simplest Mathematics Massachusetts Harvard University Press pp 189 262 Zach R 2023 02 18 Sheffer stroke before Sheffer Edward Stamm Retrieved 2023 07 02 a b Stamm Edward Bronislaw in Polish 1911 Beitrag zur Algebra der Logik Monatshefte fur Mathematik und Physik in German 22 1 137 149 doi 10 1007 BF01742795 S2CID 119816758 Hilbert D Ackermann W 1928 Grundzugen der theoretischen Logik in German 1 ed Berlin Verlag von Julius Springer p 9 Hilbert D Ackermann W 1950 Luce R E ed Principles of Mathematical Logic Translated by Hammond L M Leckie G G Steinhardt F New York Chelsea Publishing Company p 11 Lukasiewicz J 1958 1929 Elementy logiki matematycznej in Polish 2 ed Warszawa Panstwowe Wydawnictwo Naukowe Quine W V 1981 1940 Mathematical Logic Revised ed Cambridge London New York New Rochelle Melbourne and Sydney Harvard University Press p 45 Sheffer Henry Maurice 1913 A set of five independent postulates for Boolean algebras with application to logical constants Transactions of the American Mathematical Society 14 4 481 488 doi 10 2307 1988701 JSTOR 1988701 Nicod Jean George Pierre 1917 A Reduction in the Number of Primitive Propositions of Logic Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical Society 19 32 41 Church Alonzo 1956 Introduction to mathematical logic Vol 1 Princeton University Press p 134 Weisstein Eric W Propositional Calculus mathworld wolfram com Retrieved 2024 03 22 Franks Curtis 2023 Propositional Logic in Zalta Edward N Nodelman Uri eds The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Fall 2023 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2024 03 22 a b c d e Howson Colin 1997 Logic with trees an introduction to symbolic logic London New York Routledge pp 41 43 ISBN 978 0 415 13342 5 Further reading editBochenski Jozef Maria Menne Albert Heinrich in German 1960 Precis of Mathematical Logic Translated by Bird Otto revised ed Dordrecht South Holland Netherlands D Reidel NB Edited and translated from the French and German editions Precis de logique mathematique Peirce Charles Sanders 1931 1935 1880 A Boolian Algebra with One Constant In Hartshorne Charles Weiss Paul eds Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce Vol 4 Cambridge Harvard University Press pp 12 20 External links editSheffer Stroke article in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy http hyperphysics phy astr gsu edu hbase electronic nand html Implementations of 2 and 4 input NAND gates Proofs of some axioms by Stroke function by Yasuo Seto Project Euclid Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Sheffer stroke amp oldid 1219818232, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.