fbpx
Wikipedia

Monopoly on violence

In political philosophy, a monopoly on violence or monopoly on the legal use of force is the property of a polity that is the only entity in its jurisdiction to legitimately use force, and thus the supreme authority of that area.

While the monopoly on violence as the defining conception of the state was first described in sociology by Max Weber in his essay Politics as a Vocation (1919),[1] the monopoly of the legitimate use of physical force is a core concept of modern public law, which goes back to French jurist and political philosopher Jean Bodin's 1576 work Les Six livres de la République and English philosopher Thomas Hobbes' 1651 book Leviathan. Weber claims that the state is the "only human Gemeinschaft which lays claim to the monopoly on the legitimate use of physical force. As such, states can resort to coercive means such as incarceration, expropriation, humiliation, and death threats to obtain the population's compliance with its rule and thus maintain order. However, this monopoly is limited to a certain geographical area, and in fact this limitation to a particular area is one of the things that defines a state."[2] In other words, Weber describes the state as any organization that succeeds in holding the exclusive right to use, threaten, or authorize physical force against residents of its territory. Such a monopoly, according to Weber, must occur via a process of legitimation.

Max Weber's theory

Max Weber wrote in Politics as a Vocation that a fundamental characteristic of statehood is the claim of such a monopoly. An expanded definition appears in Economy and Society:

A compulsory political organization with continuous operations will be called a 'state' [if and] insofar as its administrative staff successfully upholds a claim to the monopoly of the legitimate use of physical force (das Monopol legitimen physischen Zwanges) in the enforcement of its order.[3][4]

Weber applied several caveats to this definition:

  • He intended the statement as a contemporary observation, noting that the connection between the state and the use of physical force has not always been so close. He uses the examples of feudalism, where private warfare was permitted under certain conditions, and of religious courts, which had sole jurisdiction over some types of offenses, especially heresy and sex crimes (thus the nickname "bawdy courts"). Regardless, the state exists wherever a single authority can legitimately authorize violence.
  • For the same reasons, "monopoly" does not mean that only the government may use physical force, but that the state is that human community that successfully claims for itself to be the only source of legitimacy for all physical coercion or adjudication of coercion. For example, the law might permit individuals to use force in defense of one's self or property, but this right derives from the state's authority. This conflicts directly with enlightenment principles of individual sovereignty that delegates power to the state by consent, and concepts of natural law that hold that individual rights deriving from sapient self-ownership preexist the state and are only recognised and guaranteed by the state which may be restricted from limiting them by constitutional law.[5]

Criticisms of Weber

Robert Hinrichs Bates argues that the state itself has no violent power; rather, the people hold all the power of coercion to ensure that order and other equilibriums hold up.[6] The implication of this is that there is a frontier of well-being in stateless societies, that can only be surpassed if some level of coercion or violence is used to elevate the complexity of the state. In other words, without investing in troops, police, or some sort of enforcement mechanism, early states cannot enjoy the law and order (or prosperity) of more developed states.

Relation to state capacity

 
Anarchist placard, 12 December 2020

The capacity of a state is often measured in terms of its fiscal and legal capacity. Fiscal capacity meaning the state's ability to recover taxation, and legal capacity meaning the state's supremacy as sole arbiter of conflict resolution and contract enforcement. Without some sort of coercion, the state would not otherwise be able to enforce its legitimacy in its desired sphere of influence. In early and developing states, this role was often played by the "stationary bandit" who defended villagers from roving bandits, in the hope that the protection would incentivize villagers to invest in economic production, and the stationary bandit could eventually use its coercive power to expropriate some of that wealth.[7]

In regions where state presence is minimally felt, non-state actors can use their monopoly of violence to establish legitimacy, or maintain power.[8] For example, the Sicilian Mafia originated as a protection racket providing buyers and sellers in the black market with protection. Without this type of enforcement, market participants would not be confident enough to trust their counter-parties to honour contracts and the market would collapse.

In unorganized and underground markets, violence is used to enforce contracts in the absence of accessible legal conflict resolution.[9] Charles Tilly continues this comparison to say that warmaking and statemaking are actually the best representations of what organized crime can grow into.[10] The relationship between the state, markets and violence has been noted as having a direct relationship, using violence as a form of coercion.[11][12] Anarchists view a direct relationship between capitalism, authority, and the state; the notion of a monopoly of violence is largely connected to anarchist philosophy of rejection of all unjustified hierarchy.[13][14]

Other

According to Raymond Aron, international relations are characterized by the absence of widely acknowledged legitimacy in the use of force between states.[15]

Martha Lizabeth Phelps takes Weber's ideas on the legitimacy of private security a step further, claiming that the use of private actors by the state remains legitimate if and only if military contractors are perceived as being controlled by the state.[16]

In Encyclopedia of Violence, Peace, & Conflict, Jon D. Wiseman points out that states’ monopoly on violence is conferred by the people of the said state in exchange for protection of their person as well as property, which in turn grant states the ability to coerce and exploit people through, for example, taxation.[17]

See also

References

  1. ^ Max Weber, Weber's Rationalism and Modern Society, translated and edited by Tony Waters and Dagmar Waters. New York: Palgrave Books, 2015, pp. 129-198.
  2. ^ Max Weber in Weber's Rationalism and Modern Society, translated and edited by Tony Waters and Dagmar Waters. Palgrave Books 2015, p. 136
  3. ^ Weber, Max (1978). Roth, Guenther; Wittich, Claus (eds.). Economy and Society. Berkeley: U. California P. p. 54.
  4. ^ Weber, Max (1980) [1921]. Winckelmann, Johannes (ed.). Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft (5 ed.). Tübingen: J. C. B. Mohr (Paul Siebeck. p. 29.
  5. ^ Munro, André (2013-03-06). "State Monopoly on Violence". Britannica. Retrieved 2023-02-01.
  6. ^ Bates, R.; Greif, A.; Singh, S. (2002). "Organizing Violence". Journal of Conflict Resolution. 46 (5): 599–628. doi:10.1177/002200202236166. S2CID 14970734.
  7. ^ Olson, Mancur (1993). "Dictatorship, Democracy, and Development". American Political Science Review. September 1993 (3): 567–576. doi:10.2307/2938736. JSTOR 2938736. S2CID 145312307.
  8. ^ Gambetta, Diego (1996). The Sicilian Mafia: the business of private protection. Harvard University Press. p. 1.
  9. ^ Owens, Emily Greene (2011). "Are Underground Markets Really More Violent? Evidence from Early 20th Century America". American Law and Economics Review. v13, N1: 1–44. doi:10.1093/aler/ahq017.
  10. ^ Tilly, Charles (1985). “War making and state making as organized crime” in Bringing the State Back In, eds P.B. Evans, D. Rueschemeyer, and T. Skocpol. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985. • Introduction and Chapt
  11. ^ Thorelli, Hans B. (1986). "Networks: Between markets and hierarchies". Strategic Management Journal. 7: 37–51. doi:10.1002/smj.4250070105.
  12. ^ Williamson, Oliver E. (1973). "Markets and Hierarchies: Some Elementary Considerations" (PDF). The American Economic Review. 63 (2): 316–325. JSTOR 1817092.
  13. ^ Newell, Michael E. (2019). "How the normative resistance of anarchism shaped the state monopoly on violence". European Journal of International Relations. 25 (4): 1236–1260. doi:10.1177/1354066119848037. S2CID 182194314.
  14. ^ https://onlinelibrary.wiley.com/doi/pdf/10.1111/j.1467-8330.2012.01034[dead link]
  15. ^ Raymond Aron. Paix et guerre entre les nations, Paris 1962; English: Peace and War, 1966. New edition 2003.
  16. ^ Phelps, Martha Lizabeth (December 2014). "Doppelgangers of the State: Private Security and Transferable Legitimacy". Politics & Policy. 42 (6): 824–849. doi:10.1111/polp.12100.
  17. ^ Kurtz, Lester R., and Jennifer E. Turpin. Encyclopedia of Violence, Peace, & Conflict. San Diego ;: Academic Press, 1999.

monopoly, violence, this, article, needs, additional, citations, verification, please, help, improve, this, article, adding, citations, reliable, sources, unsourced, material, challenged, removed, find, sources, news, newspapers, books, scholar, jstor, septemb. This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Monopoly on violence news newspapers books scholar JSTOR September 2014 Learn how and when to remove this template message In political philosophy a monopoly on violence or monopoly on the legal use of force is the property of a polity that is the only entity in its jurisdiction to legitimately use force and thus the supreme authority of that area While the monopoly on violence as the defining conception of the state was first described in sociology by Max Weber in his essay Politics as a Vocation 1919 1 the monopoly of the legitimate use of physical force is a core concept of modern public law which goes back to French jurist and political philosopher Jean Bodin s 1576 work Les Six livres de la Republique and English philosopher Thomas Hobbes 1651 book Leviathan Weber claims that the state is the only human Gemeinschaft which lays claim to the monopoly on the legitimate use of physical force As such states can resort to coercive means such as incarceration expropriation humiliation and death threats to obtain the population s compliance with its rule and thus maintain order However this monopoly is limited to a certain geographical area and in fact this limitation to a particular area is one of the things that defines a state 2 In other words Weber describes the state as any organization that succeeds in holding the exclusive right to use threaten or authorize physical force against residents of its territory Such a monopoly according to Weber must occur via a process of legitimation Contents 1 Max Weber s theory 1 1 Criticisms of Weber 2 Relation to state capacity 3 Other 4 See also 5 ReferencesMax Weber s theory EditMax Weber wrote in Politics as a Vocation that a fundamental characteristic of statehood is the claim of such a monopoly An expanded definition appears in Economy and Society A compulsory political organization with continuous operations will be called a state if and insofar as its administrative staff successfully upholds a claim to the monopoly of the legitimate use of physical force das Monopol legitimen physischen Zwanges in the enforcement of its order 3 4 Weber applied several caveats to this definition He intended the statement as a contemporary observation noting that the connection between the state and the use of physical force has not always been so close He uses the examples of feudalism where private warfare was permitted under certain conditions and of religious courts which had sole jurisdiction over some types of offenses especially heresy and sex crimes thus the nickname bawdy courts Regardless the state exists wherever a single authority can legitimately authorize violence For the same reasons monopoly does not mean that only the government may use physical force but that the state is that human community that successfully claims for itself to be the only source of legitimacy for all physical coercion or adjudication of coercion For example the law might permit individuals to use force in defense of one s self or property but this right derives from the state s authority This conflicts directly with enlightenment principles of individual sovereignty that delegates power to the state by consent and concepts of natural law that hold that individual rights deriving from sapient self ownership preexist the state and are only recognised and guaranteed by the state which may be restricted from limiting them by constitutional law 5 Criticisms of Weber Edit Robert Hinrichs Bates argues that the state itself has no violent power rather the people hold all the power of coercion to ensure that order and other equilibriums hold up 6 The implication of this is that there is a frontier of well being in stateless societies that can only be surpassed if some level of coercion or violence is used to elevate the complexity of the state In other words without investing in troops police or some sort of enforcement mechanism early states cannot enjoy the law and order or prosperity of more developed states Relation to state capacity Edit Anarchist placard 12 December 2020 The capacity of a state is often measured in terms of its fiscal and legal capacity Fiscal capacity meaning the state s ability to recover taxation and legal capacity meaning the state s supremacy as sole arbiter of conflict resolution and contract enforcement Without some sort of coercion the state would not otherwise be able to enforce its legitimacy in its desired sphere of influence In early and developing states this role was often played by the stationary bandit who defended villagers from roving bandits in the hope that the protection would incentivize villagers to invest in economic production and the stationary bandit could eventually use its coercive power to expropriate some of that wealth 7 In regions where state presence is minimally felt non state actors can use their monopoly of violence to establish legitimacy or maintain power 8 For example the Sicilian Mafia originated as a protection racket providing buyers and sellers in the black market with protection Without this type of enforcement market participants would not be confident enough to trust their counter parties to honour contracts and the market would collapse In unorganized and underground markets violence is used to enforce contracts in the absence of accessible legal conflict resolution 9 Charles Tilly continues this comparison to say that warmaking and statemaking are actually the best representations of what organized crime can grow into 10 The relationship between the state markets and violence has been noted as having a direct relationship using violence as a form of coercion 11 12 Anarchists view a direct relationship between capitalism authority and the state the notion of a monopoly of violence is largely connected to anarchist philosophy of rejection of all unjustified hierarchy 13 14 Other EditAccording to Raymond Aron international relations are characterized by the absence of widely acknowledged legitimacy in the use of force between states 15 Martha Lizabeth Phelps takes Weber s ideas on the legitimacy of private security a step further claiming that the use of private actors by the state remains legitimate if and only if military contractors are perceived as being controlled by the state 16 In Encyclopedia of Violence Peace amp Conflict Jon D Wiseman points out that states monopoly on violence is conferred by the people of the said state in exchange for protection of their person as well as property which in turn grant states the ability to coerce and exploit people through for example taxation 17 See also EditCoercion Counter insurgency Conflict resolution Civilian control of the military Definitions of terrorism Failed state Fiscal capacity Insurgency Legitimacy political Non state actor Peelian principles Police brutality Police legitimacy Police power United States constitutional law Political power grows out of the barrel of a gun Power social and political Private army State building StatelessnessReferences Edit Max Weber Weber s Rationalism and Modern Society translated and edited by Tony Waters and Dagmar Waters New York Palgrave Books 2015 pp 129 198 Max Weber in Weber s Rationalism and Modern Society translated and edited by Tony Waters and Dagmar Waters Palgrave Books 2015 p 136 Weber Max 1978 Roth Guenther Wittich Claus eds Economy and Society Berkeley U California P p 54 Weber Max 1980 1921 Winckelmann Johannes ed Wirtschaft und Gesellschaft 5 ed Tubingen J C B Mohr Paul Siebeck p 29 Munro Andre 2013 03 06 State Monopoly on Violence Britannica Retrieved 2023 02 01 Bates R Greif A Singh S 2002 Organizing Violence Journal of Conflict Resolution 46 5 599 628 doi 10 1177 002200202236166 S2CID 14970734 Olson Mancur 1993 Dictatorship Democracy and Development American Political Science Review September 1993 3 567 576 doi 10 2307 2938736 JSTOR 2938736 S2CID 145312307 Gambetta Diego 1996 The Sicilian Mafia the business of private protection Harvard University Press p 1 Owens Emily Greene 2011 Are Underground Markets Really More Violent Evidence from Early 20th Century America American Law and Economics Review v13 N1 1 44 doi 10 1093 aler ahq017 Tilly Charles 1985 War making and state making as organized crime in Bringing the State Back In eds P B Evans D Rueschemeyer and T Skocpol Cambridge Cambridge University Press 1985 Introduction and Chapt Thorelli Hans B 1986 Networks Between markets and hierarchies Strategic Management Journal 7 37 51 doi 10 1002 smj 4250070105 Williamson Oliver E 1973 Markets and Hierarchies Some Elementary Considerations PDF The American Economic Review 63 2 316 325 JSTOR 1817092 Newell Michael E 2019 How the normative resistance of anarchism shaped the state monopoly on violence European Journal of International Relations 25 4 1236 1260 doi 10 1177 1354066119848037 S2CID 182194314 https onlinelibrary wiley com doi pdf 10 1111 j 1467 8330 2012 01034 dead link Raymond Aron Paix et guerre entre les nations Paris 1962 English Peace and War 1966 New edition 2003 Phelps Martha Lizabeth December 2014 Doppelgangers of the State Private Security and Transferable Legitimacy Politics amp Policy 42 6 824 849 doi 10 1111 polp 12100 Kurtz Lester R and Jennifer E Turpin Encyclopedia of Violence Peace amp Conflict San Diego Academic Press 1999 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Monopoly on violence amp oldid 1137530539, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.