fbpx
Wikipedia

Fideism

Fideism (/ˈfd.ɪzəm, ˈfd-/ FEE-day-iz-əm, FAY-dee-) is a term used to name a standpoint or an epistemological theory which maintains that faith is independent of reason, or that reason and faith are hostile to each other and faith is superior at arriving at particular truths (see natural theology). The word fideism comes from fides, the Latin word for faith, and literally means "faith-ism".[1] Philosophers have identified a number of different forms of fideism.[2] Strict fideists hold that reason has no place in discovering theological truths, while moderate fideists hold that though some truth can be known by reason, faith stands above reason.[3]

Theologians and philosophers have responded in various ways to the place of faith and reason in determining the truth of metaphysical ideas, morality, and religious beliefs. Historically, fideism is most commonly ascribed to four philosophers: Søren Kierkegaard, Blaise Pascal, William James, and Ludwig Wittgenstein; with fideism being a label applied in a negative sense by their opponents, but which is not always supported by their own ideas and works or followers.[4] A qualified form of fideism is sometimes attributed to Immanuel Kant's famous suggestion that we must "deny knowledge in order to make room for faith".[5]

Overview edit

Alvin Plantinga defines "fideism" as "the exclusive or basic reliance upon faith alone, accompanied by a consequent disparagement of reason and is used especially in the pursuit of philosophical or religious truth". The fideist therefore "urges reliance on faith rather than reason, in matters philosophical and religious", and therefore may go on to disparage the claims of reason.[7] The fideist seeks truth, above all, and affirms that reason cannot achieve certain kinds of truth, which must instead be accepted only by faith.[6]

History edit

Theories of truth edit

The doctrine of fideism is consistent with some, and radically contrary to other theories of truth:

Tertullian edit

Tertullian taught fideistic concepts such as the later philosophers William of Ockham and Søren Kierkegaard.[3] Tertullian's De Carne Christi (On the Flesh of Christ])[8] says "the Son of God died; it is by all means to be believed, because it is absurd."[9]

On the other hand, some deny Tertullian's fideistic character, the statement "Credo quia absurdum" ("I believe because it is absurd") is sometimes cited as an example of views of the Church Fathers. However, this has been argued to have been a misquotation of Tertullian,[10] saying that Tertullian was critiquing intellectual arrogance and the misuse of philosophy, but that he remained committed to reason and its usefulness in defending the faith.[1][11]

William of Ockham edit

Ockham was a fideist, holding that belief in God is only a matter of faith and not from knowledge, this led him to deny all the alleged proofs of God.[12][3]

Luther edit

Martin Luther taught that faith informs the Christian's use of reason. Regarding the mysteries of Christian faith, he wrote, "All the articles of our Christian faith, which God has revealed to us in His Word, are in presence of reason sheerly impossible, absurd, and false." And "Reason is the greatest enemy that faith has." However, Luther conceded that, grounded upon faith in Christ, reason can be used in its proper realm, as he wrote, "Before faith and the knowledge of God reason is darkness in divine matters, but through faith it is turned into a light in the believer and serves piety as an excellent instrument. For just as all natural endowments serve to further impiety in the godless, so they serve to further salvation in the godly. An eloquent tongue promotes faith; reason makes speech clear, and everything helps faith forward. Reason receives life from faith; it is killed by it and brought back to life."[13]

Blaise Pascal and fideism edit

 
Blaise Pascal

Another form of fideism is assumed by Pascal's Wager, which is a rational argument for a pragmatic view of God's existence.[14] Blaise Pascal invites the atheist considering faith to see faith in God as a cost-free choice that carries a potential reward.[15] He does not attempt to argue that God indeed exists, only that it might be valuable to assume that it is true. Of course, the problem with Pascal's Wager is that it does not restrict itself to a specific god, although Pascal did have in mind the Christian version (referred to both by Jews and Christians as God), as is mentioned in the following quote. In his Pensées, Pascal writes:

Who then will blame Christians for not being able to give reasons for their beliefs, since they profess belief in a religion which they cannot explain? They declare, when they expound it to the world, that it is foolishness, stultitiam; and then you complain because they do not prove it! If they proved it, they would not keep their word; it is through their lack of proofs that they show they are not lacking in sense.

— Pensées, no. 233

Pascal, moreover, contests the various proposed proofs of the existence of God as irrelevant. Even if the proofs were valid, the beings they propose to demonstrate are not congruent with the deity worshiped by historical faiths, and can easily lead to deism instead of revealed religion: "The God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob—not the god of the philosophers!"[16]

Hamann and fideism edit

Considered to be the father of modern antirationalism, Johann Georg Hamann promoted a view that elevated faith alone as the only guide to human conduct. Using the work of David Hume he argued that everything people do is ultimately based on faith.[17] Without faith (for it can never be proven) in the existence of an external world, human affairs could not continue; therefore, he argued, all reasoning comes from this faith: it is fundamental to the human condition. Thus all attempts to base belief in God using reason are in vain. He attacks systems like Spinozism that try to confine what he feels is the infinite majesty of God into a finite human creation.[18]

Kant's qualified fideism edit

Hamann was a personal friend of Immanuel Kant, one of the most influential philosophers of the modern era. While Kant and Hamann disagreed about both the use of reason and the scientific method, there were also a number of points of agreement between them.[19] For instance, one of the views defended in Kant's Critique of Pure Reason is that reason is incapable of attaining knowledge of the existence of God or the immortality of the soul, a point with which Hamann would agree. The most important difference on this point is that Kant did not think that this gave way to antirationalism, whereas Hamann did.[19] As a result, a qualified form of fideism is sometimes attributed to Kant. This modified form of fideism is also evident in his famous suggestion that we must "deny knowledge in order to make room for faith".[5]

Kierkegaard edit

Natural theologians may argue that Kierkegaard was a fideist of this general sort: the argument that God's existence cannot be certainly known, and that the decision to accept faith is neither founded on, nor needs, rational justification, may be found in the writings of Søren Kierkegaard and his followers in Christian existentialism. Many of Kierkegaard's works, including Fear and Trembling, are under pseudonyms; they may represent the work of fictional authors whose views correspond to hypothetical positions, not necessarily those held by Kierkegaard himself.

In Fear and Trembling, Kierkegaard focused on Abraham's willingness to sacrifice Isaac. The New Testament apostles repeatedly argued that Abraham's act was an admirable display of faith. To the eyes of a non-believer, however, it must necessarily have appeared to be an unjustifiable attempted murder, perhaps the fruit of an insane delusion. Kierkegaard used this example to focus attention on the problem of faith in general.[20] He ultimately affirmed that to believe in the incarnation of Christ, in God made flesh, was to believe in the "absolute paradox", since it implies that an eternal, perfect being would become a simple human. Reason cannot possibly comprehend such a phenomenon; therefore, one can only believe in it by taking a "leap of faith".

James and "will to believe" edit

American pragmatic philosopher and psychologist William James introduced his concept of the "will to believe" in 1896. Following upon his earlier theories of truth, James argued that some religious questions can only be answered by believing in the first place: one cannot know if religious doctrines are true without seeing if they work, but they cannot be said to work unless one believes them in the first place.

William James published many works on the subject of religious experience. His four key characteristics of religious experience are: 'passivity', 'ineffability', 'a noetic quality', and 'transiency'. Due to the fact that religious experience is fundamentally ineffable, it is impossible to hold a coherent discussion of it using public language. This means that religious belief cannot be discussed effectively, and so reason does not affect faith. Instead, faith is found through experience of the spiritual, and so understanding of belief is only gained through the practice of it.

Wittgenstein and fideism edit

The philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein did not write systematically about religion, though he did lecture on the topic (e.g., student notes published as "Lectures on Religious Belief"), and various remarks about religions appear in sources such as the "Remarks on Frazer's Golden Bough", his private diaries, and in Culture and Value. In his 1967 article, entitled "Wittgensteinian Fideism", Kai Nielsen argues that certain aspects of Wittgenstein's thought have been interpreted by Wittgensteinians in a "fideistic" manner. According to this position, religion is a self-contained—and primarily expressive—enterprise, governed by its own internal logic or "grammar". This view—commonly called Wittgensteinian fideism—states: that religion is logically cut off from other aspects of life; that religious concepts and discourse are essentially self-referential; and that religion cannot be criticized from an external (i.e., non-religious) point of view.[4]

Wittgenstein stated that "Christianity is not based on historical truth; rather, it offers us a historical narrative and says: now believe! But not, believe this narrative with the belief appropriate to a historical narrative, rather: believe, through thick and thin". For Wittgenstein you should "not take the same attitude to it as you take to other historical narratives...there is nothing paradoxical about that!" and that "The historical accounts in the Gospel, might historically speaking, be demonstrably false yet belief would lose nothing by this".[21]

Shestov edit

Lev Shestov is associated with radical fideism, holding that religious truth can only be gained by rejecting reason.[22]

Fideism and presuppositional apologetics edit

Presuppositional apologetics is a Christian system of apologetics associated mainly with Calvinist Protestantism; it attempts to distinguish itself from fideism.[23] It holds that all human thought must begin with the proposition that the revelation contained in the Bible is axiomatic, rather than transcendentally necessary, else one would not be able to make sense of any human experience (see also epistemic foundationalism). To non-believers who reject the notion that the truth about God, the world, and themselves can be found within the Bible, the presuppositional apologist attempts to demonstrate the incoherence of the epistemic foundations of the logical alternative by the use of what has come to be known as the "transcendental argument for God's existence" (TAG). On the other hand, some presuppositional apologists, such as Cornelius Van Til, believe that such a condition of true unbelief is impossible, claiming that all people actually believe in God (even if only on a subconscious level), whether they admit or deny it.

Presuppositional apologetics could be seen as being more closely allied with foundationalism than fideism, though it has sometimes been critical of both.

Criticism edit

Fideism rejected by the Catholic Church edit

Catholic doctrine rejects fideism, with its earliest condemnations dating back to 1348.[24] The Catechism of the Catholic Church, affirms that it is a Catholic doctrine that God's existence can indeed be demonstrated by reason.

The Anti-Modernist oath promulgated by Pope Pius X required Catholics to affirm that:

God, the origin and end of all things, can be known with certainty by the natural light of reason from the created world (cf. Rom. 1:20), that is, from the visible works of creation, as a cause from its effects, and that, therefore, his existence can also be demonstrated

Similarly, the Catechism of the Catholic Church teaches that:

Though human reason is, strictly speaking, truly capable by its own natural power and light of attaining to a true and certain knowledge of the one personal God, who watches over and controls the world by his providence, and of the natural law written in our hearts by the Creator; yet there are many obstacles which prevent reason from the effective and fruitful use of this inborn faculty. For the truths that concern the relations between God and man wholly transcend the visible order of things, and, if they are translated into human action and influence it, they call for self-surrender and abnegation. The human mind, in its turn, is hampered in the attaining of such truths, not only by the impact of the senses and the imagination, but also by disordered appetites which are the consequences of original sin. So it happens that men in such matters easily persuade themselves that what they would not like to be true is false or at least doubtful.

— Catechism of the Catholic Church, ss. 37

Pope John Paul II's encyclical Fides et Ratio also affirms that God's existence is in fact demonstrable by reason, and that attempts to reason otherwise are the results of sin. In the encyclical, John Paul II warned against "a resurgence of fideism, which fails to recognize the importance of rational knowledge and philosophical discourse for the understanding of faith, indeed for the very possibility of belief in God".

Fideist currents in Catholic thought edit

Another course of fideist thinking within the Catholic Church is the concept of "signs of contradiction".[25] According to this belief, the holiness of certain people and institutions is confirmed by the fact that other people contest their claims: this opposition is held to be worthy of comparison to the opposition met by Jesus Christ himself. This opposition and contradiction does not inherently prove something is true in Catholic thought, but acts an additional possible indication of its truth. The idea of the sign of contradiction is related to the conviction that, while human reason is still operative, the distortion of fallen human nature causes some instances of reasoning to go astray.

As sin edit

Fideism has received criticism from theologians who argue that fideism is not a proper way to worship God. According to this position, if one does not attempt to understand what one believes, one is not really believing. "Blind faith" is not true faith. Notable articulations of this position include:

As relativism edit

Some critics argue that fideism can lead to relativism.[26]

A case for reason edit

Some critics note the successful use of reason in the daily lives of people to solve problems. That reason has led to an increase of knowledge, including in the sphere of science.

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b Amesbury 2005.
  2. ^ Taliaferro, Charles (2000), Quinn, Philip L (ed.), A companion to philosophy of religion, Malden, MA: Blackwell, p. 376, ISBN 0-631-21328-7
  3. ^ a b c "fideism | philosophy | Britannica". www.britannica.com. Retrieved 2022-09-08.
  4. ^ a b Amesbury 2005, section 2.2.
  5. ^ a b "Immanuel Kant: Philosophy of Religion". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 13 June 2020.
  6. ^ a b Amesbury 2005, section 1.
  7. ^ Plantinga, Alvin (1983). "Reason and Belief in God" in Alvin Plantinga and Nicholas Wolterstorff (eds.), Faith and Rationality: Reason and Belief in God, page 87. (Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press).[6]
  8. ^ Vainio, Olli-Pekka (2010). Beyond Fideism: Negotiable Religious Identities. Transcending boundaries in philosophy and theology. Ashgate. p. 25. ISBN 978-1-40940679-2.
  9. ^ Tertullian, On the Flesh of Christ, Fathers, New Advent.
  10. ^ Sider, R. D. (1980). "Tertullian: Credo Quia Absurdum?, Classical World 73". pp. 417–419.
  11. ^ Osborn, Eric (2003). Tertullian, First Theologian of the West. Cambridge University Press. p. 28.
  12. ^ "Ockham (Occam), William of | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2022-09-08.
  13. ^ Luther, Martin (1883–2009), "Die Sammlung von Konrad Cordatus (Schluß)", Tischreden [Table talks], Werke: kritische Gesammtausgabe (in German), vol. 3. aus den dreißiger Jahren, Weimar: Hermann Böhlau, ISBN 0-85964-464-2.
  14. ^ Olli-Pekka Vainio (15 April 2016). Beyond Fideism: Negotiable Religious Identities. Routledge. pp. 32–. ISBN 978-1-317-17479-0.
  15. ^ Geisler 1976, p. 49.
  16. ^ Pascal, Blaise (1854), Pensées [Thoughts] (in French), Paris: Charles Louandre, p. 40.
  17. ^ Redmond, M. (1987). "The Hamann-Hume Connection". Religious Studies. 23 (1). Cambridge University Press: 97. doi:10.1017/s0034412500018564. JSTOR 20006314. S2CID 170457310.
  18. ^ Berlin, Isaiah (2000). Three Critics of the Enlightenment: Vico, Hamann, Herder. Princeton University Press. p. 297. ISBN 0691057273.
  19. ^ a b "Johann Georg Hamann (1730–1788)". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 13 June 2020.
  20. ^ Geisler 1976, pp. 50–51.
  21. ^ Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1980). Culture and Value. University of Chicago Press. p. 32.
  22. ^ Plantinga, Alvin (1998). The Analytic Theist: An Alvin Plantinga Reader. Wm. B. Eerdmans Publishing. ISBN 978-0-8028-4229-9.
  23. ^ Payne, Michael W (2002). (PDF). Westminster Theological Journal (63). Westminster Theological Seminary: 117. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2017-02-23. Retrieved 2013-02-02.
  24. ^ "CATHOLIC ENCYCLOPEDIA: Fideism". www.newadvent.org. Retrieved 2023-07-05.
  25. ^ Wojtyla, Carol (1979), Sign of contradiction, St. Paul Publications, p. 8.
  26. ^ Craig, Edward, ed. (1998). "Rationality and cultural relativism". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Taylor & Francis. p. 85. ISBN 9780415169172.

Sources edit

Further reading edit

  • Benjamin Brown, "The Comeback of "Simple Faith": The Ultra-Orthodox Concept of Faith and Its Development in the Nineteenth Century", Studies in Judaism, Humanities and the Social Sciences, 2017.
  • "Fideism", The Catholic Encyclopedia, New advent.

fideism, this, article, about, epistemological, theory, religious, movement, faithism, cuban, socialist, ideology, also, known, fidelism, politics, fidel, castro, term, used, name, standpoint, epistemological, theory, which, maintains, that, faith, independent. This article is about the epistemological theory For the new religious movement see Faithism For the Cuban socialist ideology also known as Fidelism see Politics of Fidel Castro Fideism ˈ f iː d eɪ ɪ z em ˈ f aɪ d iː FEE day iz em FAY dee is a term used to name a standpoint or an epistemological theory which maintains that faith is independent of reason or that reason and faith are hostile to each other and faith is superior at arriving at particular truths see natural theology The word fideism comes from fides the Latin word for faith and literally means faith ism 1 Philosophers have identified a number of different forms of fideism 2 Strict fideists hold that reason has no place in discovering theological truths while moderate fideists hold that though some truth can be known by reason faith stands above reason 3 Theologians and philosophers have responded in various ways to the place of faith and reason in determining the truth of metaphysical ideas morality and religious beliefs Historically fideism is most commonly ascribed to four philosophers Soren Kierkegaard Blaise Pascal William James and Ludwig Wittgenstein with fideism being a label applied in a negative sense by their opponents but which is not always supported by their own ideas and works or followers 4 A qualified form of fideism is sometimes attributed to Immanuel Kant s famous suggestion that we must deny knowledge in order to make room for faith 5 Contents 1 Overview 1 1 History 1 2 Theories of truth 1 3 Tertullian 1 4 William of Ockham 1 5 Luther 1 6 Blaise Pascal and fideism 1 7 Hamann and fideism 1 8 Kant s qualified fideism 1 9 Kierkegaard 1 10 James and will to believe 1 11 Wittgenstein and fideism 1 12 Shestov 1 13 Fideism and presuppositional apologetics 2 Criticism 2 1 Fideism rejected by the Catholic Church 2 1 1 Fideist currents in Catholic thought 2 2 As sin 2 3 As relativism 2 4 A case for reason 3 See also 4 References 4 1 Sources 5 Further readingOverview editAlvin Plantinga defines fideism as the exclusive or basic reliance upon faith alone accompanied by a consequent disparagement of reason and is used especially in the pursuit of philosophical or religious truth The fideist therefore urges reliance on faith rather than reason in matters philosophical and religious and therefore may go on to disparage the claims of reason 7 The fideist seeks truth above all and affirms that reason cannot achieve certain kinds of truth which must instead be accepted only by faith 6 History edit Main article Relationship between religion and science Theories of truth edit Main article Truth Major theories The doctrine of fideism is consistent with some and radically contrary to other theories of truth Correspondence theory of truth Pragmatic theory of truth Constructivist epistemology Consensus theory of truth Coherence theory of truth SubjectivismTertullian edit Tertullian taught fideistic concepts such as the later philosophers William of Ockham and Soren Kierkegaard 3 Tertullian s De Carne Christi On the Flesh of Christ 8 says the Son of God died it is by all means to be believed because it is absurd 9 On the other hand some deny Tertullian s fideistic character the statement Credo quia absurdum I believe because it is absurd is sometimes cited as an example of views of the Church Fathers However this has been argued to have been a misquotation of Tertullian 10 saying that Tertullian was critiquing intellectual arrogance and the misuse of philosophy but that he remained committed to reason and its usefulness in defending the faith 1 11 William of Ockham edit Ockham was a fideist holding that belief in God is only a matter of faith and not from knowledge this led him to deny all the alleged proofs of God 12 3 Luther edit Martin Luther taught that faith informs the Christian s use of reason Regarding the mysteries of Christian faith he wrote All the articles of our Christian faith which God has revealed to us in His Word are in presence of reason sheerly impossible absurd and false And Reason is the greatest enemy that faith has However Luther conceded that grounded upon faith in Christ reason can be used in its proper realm as he wrote Before faith and the knowledge of God reason is darkness in divine matters but through faith it is turned into a light in the believer and serves piety as an excellent instrument For just as all natural endowments serve to further impiety in the godless so they serve to further salvation in the godly An eloquent tongue promotes faith reason makes speech clear and everything helps faith forward Reason receives life from faith it is killed by it and brought back to life 13 Blaise Pascal and fideism edit nbsp Blaise PascalAnother form of fideism is assumed by Pascal s Wager which is a rational argument for a pragmatic view of God s existence 14 Blaise Pascal invites the atheist considering faith to see faith in God as a cost free choice that carries a potential reward 15 He does not attempt to argue that God indeed exists only that it might be valuable to assume that it is true Of course the problem with Pascal s Wager is that it does not restrict itself to a specific god although Pascal did have in mind the Christian version referred to both by Jews and Christians as God as is mentioned in the following quote In his Pensees Pascal writes Who then will blame Christians for not being able to give reasons for their beliefs since they profess belief in a religion which they cannot explain They declare when they expound it to the world that it is foolishness stultitiam and then you complain because they do not prove it If they proved it they would not keep their word it is through their lack of proofs that they show they are not lacking in sense Pensees no 233 Pascal moreover contests the various proposed proofs of the existence of God as irrelevant Even if the proofs were valid the beings they propose to demonstrate are not congruent with the deity worshiped by historical faiths and can easily lead to deism instead of revealed religion The God of Abraham Isaac and Jacob not the god of the philosophers 16 Hamann and fideism edit Considered to be the father of modern antirationalism Johann Georg Hamann promoted a view that elevated faith alone as the only guide to human conduct Using the work of David Hume he argued that everything people do is ultimately based on faith 17 Without faith for it can never be proven in the existence of an external world human affairs could not continue therefore he argued all reasoning comes from this faith it is fundamental to the human condition Thus all attempts to base belief in God using reason are in vain He attacks systems like Spinozism that try to confine what he feels is the infinite majesty of God into a finite human creation 18 Kant s qualified fideism edit Hamann was a personal friend of Immanuel Kant one of the most influential philosophers of the modern era While Kant and Hamann disagreed about both the use of reason and the scientific method there were also a number of points of agreement between them 19 For instance one of the views defended in Kant s Critique of Pure Reason is that reason is incapable of attaining knowledge of the existence of God or the immortality of the soul a point with which Hamann would agree The most important difference on this point is that Kant did not think that this gave way to antirationalism whereas Hamann did 19 As a result a qualified form of fideism is sometimes attributed to Kant This modified form of fideism is also evident in his famous suggestion that we must deny knowledge in order to make room for faith 5 Kierkegaard edit Natural theologians may argue that Kierkegaard was a fideist of this general sort the argument that God s existence cannot be certainly known and that the decision to accept faith is neither founded on nor needs rational justification may be found in the writings of Soren Kierkegaard and his followers in Christian existentialism Many of Kierkegaard s works including Fear and Trembling are under pseudonyms they may represent the work of fictional authors whose views correspond to hypothetical positions not necessarily those held by Kierkegaard himself In Fear and Trembling Kierkegaard focused on Abraham s willingness to sacrifice Isaac The New Testament apostles repeatedly argued that Abraham s act was an admirable display of faith To the eyes of a non believer however it must necessarily have appeared to be an unjustifiable attempted murder perhaps the fruit of an insane delusion Kierkegaard used this example to focus attention on the problem of faith in general 20 He ultimately affirmed that to believe in the incarnation of Christ in God made flesh was to believe in the absolute paradox since it implies that an eternal perfect being would become a simple human Reason cannot possibly comprehend such a phenomenon therefore one can only believe in it by taking a leap of faith James and will to believe edit American pragmatic philosopher and psychologist William James introduced his concept of the will to believe in 1896 Following upon his earlier theories of truth James argued that some religious questions can only be answered by believing in the first place one cannot know if religious doctrines are true without seeing if they work but they cannot be said to work unless one believes them in the first place William James published many works on the subject of religious experience His four key characteristics of religious experience are passivity ineffability a noetic quality and transiency Due to the fact that religious experience is fundamentally ineffable it is impossible to hold a coherent discussion of it using public language This means that religious belief cannot be discussed effectively and so reason does not affect faith Instead faith is found through experience of the spiritual and so understanding of belief is only gained through the practice of it Wittgenstein and fideism edit The philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein did not write systematically about religion though he did lecture on the topic e g student notes published as Lectures on Religious Belief and various remarks about religions appear in sources such as the Remarks on Frazer s Golden Bough his private diaries and in Culture and Value In his 1967 article entitled Wittgensteinian Fideism Kai Nielsen argues that certain aspects of Wittgenstein s thought have been interpreted by Wittgensteinians in a fideistic manner According to this position religion is a self contained and primarily expressive enterprise governed by its own internal logic or grammar This view commonly called Wittgensteinian fideism states that religion is logically cut off from other aspects of life that religious concepts and discourse are essentially self referential and that religion cannot be criticized from an external i e non religious point of view 4 Wittgenstein stated that Christianity is not based on historical truth rather it offers us a historical narrative and says now believe But not believe this narrative with the belief appropriate to a historical narrative rather believe through thick and thin For Wittgenstein you should not take the same attitude to it as you take to other historical narratives there is nothing paradoxical about that and that The historical accounts in the Gospel might historically speaking be demonstrably false yet belief would lose nothing by this 21 Shestov edit Lev Shestov is associated with radical fideism holding that religious truth can only be gained by rejecting reason 22 Fideism and presuppositional apologetics edit Presuppositional apologetics is a Christian system of apologetics associated mainly with Calvinist Protestantism it attempts to distinguish itself from fideism 23 It holds that all human thought must begin with the proposition that the revelation contained in the Bible is axiomatic rather than transcendentally necessary else one would not be able to make sense of any human experience see also epistemic foundationalism To non believers who reject the notion that the truth about God the world and themselves can be found within the Bible the presuppositional apologist attempts to demonstrate the incoherence of the epistemic foundations of the logical alternative by the use of what has come to be known as the transcendental argument for God s existence TAG On the other hand some presuppositional apologists such as Cornelius Van Til believe that such a condition of true unbelief is impossible claiming that all people actually believe in God even if only on a subconscious level whether they admit or deny it Presuppositional apologetics could be seen as being more closely allied with foundationalism than fideism though it has sometimes been critical of both Criticism editFideism rejected by the Catholic Church edit Catholic doctrine rejects fideism with its earliest condemnations dating back to 1348 24 The Catechism of the Catholic Church affirms that it is a Catholic doctrine that God s existence can indeed be demonstrated by reason The Anti Modernist oath promulgated by Pope Pius X required Catholics to affirm that God the origin and end of all things can be known with certainty by the natural light of reason from the created world cf Rom 1 20 that is from the visible works of creation as a cause from its effects and that therefore his existence can also be demonstrated Similarly the Catechism of the Catholic Church teaches that Though human reason is strictly speaking truly capable by its own natural power and light of attaining to a true and certain knowledge of the one personal God who watches over and controls the world by his providence and of the natural law written in our hearts by the Creator yet there are many obstacles which prevent reason from the effective and fruitful use of this inborn faculty For the truths that concern the relations between God and man wholly transcend the visible order of things and if they are translated into human action and influence it they call for self surrender and abnegation The human mind in its turn is hampered in the attaining of such truths not only by the impact of the senses and the imagination but also by disordered appetites which are the consequences of original sin So it happens that men in such matters easily persuade themselves that what they would not like to be true is false or at least doubtful Catechism of the Catholic Church ss 37 Pope John Paul II s encyclical Fides et Ratio also affirms that God s existence is in fact demonstrable by reason and that attempts to reason otherwise are the results of sin In the encyclical John Paul II warned against a resurgence of fideism which fails to recognize the importance of rational knowledge and philosophical discourse for the understanding of faith indeed for the very possibility of belief in God Fideist currents in Catholic thought edit Another course of fideist thinking within the Catholic Church is the concept of signs of contradiction 25 According to this belief the holiness of certain people and institutions is confirmed by the fact that other people contest their claims this opposition is held to be worthy of comparison to the opposition met by Jesus Christ himself This opposition and contradiction does not inherently prove something is true in Catholic thought but acts an additional possible indication of its truth The idea of the sign of contradiction is related to the conviction that while human reason is still operative the distortion of fallen human nature causes some instances of reasoning to go astray As sin edit Fideism has received criticism from theologians who argue that fideism is not a proper way to worship God According to this position if one does not attempt to understand what one believes one is not really believing Blind faith is not true faith Notable articulations of this position include Peter Abelard Sic et Non Lord Herbert De VeritateAs relativism edit Some critics argue that fideism can lead to relativism 26 A case for reason edit Main article Relationship between religion and science Some critics note the successful use of reason in the daily lives of people to solve problems That reason has led to an increase of knowledge including in the sphere of science See also editAgnostic theism Apophatic theology Christian existential apologetics Christian existentialism Existence of God Liberal Christianity contrast Rational fideism Religious epistemology Scholasticism contrast Sola fide the Protestant belief that Christians are saved by faith in Christ aloneReferences edit a b Amesbury 2005 Taliaferro Charles 2000 Quinn Philip L ed A companion to philosophy of religion Malden MA Blackwell p 376 ISBN 0 631 21328 7 a b c fideism philosophy Britannica www britannica com Retrieved 2022 09 08 a b Amesbury 2005 section 2 2 a b Immanuel Kant Philosophy of Religion Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 13 June 2020 a b Amesbury 2005 section 1 Plantinga Alvin 1983 Reason and Belief in God in Alvin Plantinga and Nicholas Wolterstorff eds Faith and Rationality Reason and Belief in God page 87 Notre Dame University of Notre Dame Press 6 Vainio Olli Pekka 2010 Beyond Fideism Negotiable Religious Identities Transcending boundaries in philosophy and theology Ashgate p 25 ISBN 978 1 40940679 2 Tertullian On the Flesh of Christ Fathers New Advent Sider R D 1980 Tertullian Credo Quia Absurdum Classical World 73 pp 417 419 Osborn Eric 2003 Tertullian First Theologian of the West Cambridge University Press p 28 Ockham Occam William of Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2022 09 08 Luther Martin 1883 2009 Die Sammlung von Konrad Cordatus Schluss Tischreden Table talks Werke kritische Gesammtausgabe in German vol 3 aus den dreissiger Jahren Weimar Hermann Bohlau ISBN 0 85964 464 2 Olli Pekka Vainio 15 April 2016 Beyond Fideism Negotiable Religious Identities Routledge pp 32 ISBN 978 1 317 17479 0 Geisler 1976 p 49 Pascal Blaise 1854 Pensees Thoughts in French Paris Charles Louandre p 40 Redmond M 1987 The Hamann Hume Connection Religious Studies 23 1 Cambridge University Press 97 doi 10 1017 s0034412500018564 JSTOR 20006314 S2CID 170457310 Berlin Isaiah 2000 Three Critics of the Enlightenment Vico Hamann Herder Princeton University Press p 297 ISBN 0691057273 a b Johann Georg Hamann 1730 1788 Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 13 June 2020 Geisler 1976 pp 50 51 Wittgenstein Ludwig 1980 Culture and Value University of Chicago Press p 32 Plantinga Alvin 1998 The Analytic Theist An Alvin Plantinga Reader Wm B Eerdmans Publishing ISBN 978 0 8028 4229 9 Payne Michael W 2002 Epistemological crises dramatic narratives and apologetics the ad hominem once more PDF Westminster Theological Journal 63 Westminster Theological Seminary 117 Archived from the original PDF on 2017 02 23 Retrieved 2013 02 02 CATHOLIC ENCYCLOPEDIA Fideism www newadvent org Retrieved 2023 07 05 Wojtyla Carol 1979 Sign of contradiction St Paul Publications p 8 Craig Edward ed 1998 Rationality and cultural relativism Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Taylor amp Francis p 85 ISBN 9780415169172 Sources edit Amesbury Richard 2005 Fideism Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Geisler Norman 1976 Christian Apologetics Baker Book House ISBN 0 80103704 2 Further reading editBenjamin Brown The Comeback of Simple Faith The Ultra Orthodox Concept of Faith and Its Development in the Nineteenth Century Studies in Judaism Humanities and the Social Sciences 2017 Fideism The Catholic Encyclopedia New advent Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Fideism amp oldid 1218304654, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.