fbpx
Wikipedia

Entitlement (fair division)

Entitlement in fair division describes that proportion of the resources or goods to be divided that a player can expect to receive. In many fair division settings, all agents have equal entitlements, which means that each agent is entitled to 1/n of the resource. But there are practical settings in which agents have different entitlements. Some examples are:

  • In partnership resolution settings, each partner is entitled to a fraction of the common assets in proportion to his/her investment in the partnership.
  • In inheritance settings, the law in some jurisdictions prescribes a different share to each heir according to his/her proximity to the deceased person. For example, according to the Bible, the firstborn son must receive twice as much as every other son. In contrast, according to the Italian law, when there are three heirs - parent, brother and spouse - they are entitled to 1/4, 1/12 and 2/3 respectively.[1]
  • In parliamentary democracies, each party is entitled to a number of seats in the parliament that is, in general, proportional to the number of votes it received.

The idea is based on the normal idea of entitlement. Entitlements can be determined by agreeing on a cooperative game and using its value as the entitlement.

When agents have equal entitlements, it is reasonable to require that the solution satisfies the axiom of anonymity (also called: symmetry), that is, agents are treated only by their valuations and not by their names. In contrast, when agents have different entitlements, anonymity is no longer valid, and the solutions must be asymmetric.

Various problems of fair division with different entitlements have been studied.

Dividing money edit

Even when only money is to be divided and some fixed amount has been specified for each recipient, the problem can be complex. The amounts specified may be more or less than the amount of money, and the profit or loss will then need to be shared out. The proportional rule is normally used in law nowadays, and is the default assumption in the theory of bankruptcy. Other rules however are often used, for example:

  • The Shapley value is one common method of deciding bargaining power as can be seen in the airport problem. In economics an allocation which cannot be improved upon by any coalition is said to have the core property.
  • Welfare economics on the other hand tries to determine allocations depending on fairness criteria.
  • The people can also agree on their relative entitlements by a consensus process. For instance they could say what they think everyone else is entitled to and if the assessments agree then they have an agreed impartial consensus division.[2]
  • Priority rules are another kind of mechanism for allocation with different entitlements.[3]

In the Talmud edit

The Talmud has a number of examples where entitlements are not decided on a proportional basis.

  • The disputed garment problem. If one person claims the whole of a cloth and another half then it is divided 3/4 and 1/4.[4]
  • The estate division problem. Three wives have claims to 100, 200 and 300 zuz. Three cases are considered, if the estate is 100 zuz then they get 33 and a third each, if 200 then 50, 75, 75, and if 300 then 50, 100 and 150.[5]
  • Profits from a joint fund. If two people put 200 and 100 into a fund and buy an ox for ploughing and use it for that purpose they divide the profit evenly between them. But if they instead then slaughter the ox they divide the profit in proportion. This is discussed in the Babylonian Talmud just after the estate division problem.
  • Ibn Ezra's problem. This is a later problem of estate division that was solved in a different way. A man with an estate of 120 dies bequeathing 120, 60, 40 and 30 to his four sons. The recommendation was to award (120-60)/1+(60-40)/2+(40-30)/3+(30-0)/4 to the first and sums with leading terms removed for the rest ending with 30/4 for the last. This allocation is different from the previous estate division

These solutions can all be modeled by cooperative games. The estate division problem has a large literature and was first given a theoretical basis in game theory by Robert J. Aumann and Michael Maschler in 1985.[6] See Contested garment rule.

Dividing continuous resources edit

Fair cake-cutting is the problem of dividing a heterogeneous continuous resource. There always exists a proportional cake-cutting respecting the different entitlements. The two main research questions are (a) how many cuts are required for a fair division? (b) how many queries are needed for computing a division? See:

Cloud computing environments require to divide multiple homogeneous divisible resources (e.g. memory or CPU) between users, where each user needs a different combination of resources.[7] The setting in which agents may have different entitlements has been studied by [8] and.[9]

Fair item allocation edit

Identical indivisible items - dividing seats in parliaments edit

In parliamentary democracies with proportional representation, each party is entitled to seats in proportion to its number of votes. In multi-constituency systems, each constituency is entitled to seats in proportion to its population. This is a problem of dividing identical indivisible items (the seats) among agents with different entitlements. It is called the apportionment problem.

The allocation of seats by size of population can leave small constituencies with no voice at all. The easiest solution is to have constituencies of equal size. Sometimes, however, this can prove impossible – for instance, in the European Union or United States. Ensuring the 'voting power' is proportional to the size of constituencies is a problem of entitlement.

There are a number of methods which compute a voting power for different sized or weighted constituencies. The main ones are the Shapley–Shubik power index, the Banzhaf power index. These power indexes assume the constituencies can join up in any random way and approximate to the square root of the weighting as given by the Penrose method. This assumption does not correspond to actual practice and it is arguable that larger constituencies are unfairly treated by them.

Heterogeneous indivisible items edit

In the more complex setting of fair item allocation, there are multiple different items with possibly different values to different people.

Aziz, Gaspers, Mackenzie and Walsh[10]: sec.7.2  define proportionality and envy-freeness for agents with different entitlements, when the agents reveal only an ordinal ranking on the items, rather than their complete utility functions. They present a polynomial-time algorithm for checking whether there exists an allocation that is possibly proportional (proportional according to at least one utility profile consistent with the agent rankings), or necessarily proportional (proportional according to all utility profiles consistent with the rankings).

Farhadi, Ghodsi, Hajiaghayi, Lahaie, Pennock, Seddighin, Seddighin and Yami[11] defined the Weighted Maximin Share (WMMS) as a generalization of the maximin share to agents with different entitlements. They showed that the best attainable multiplicative guarantee for the WMMS is 1/n in general, and 1/2 in the special case in which the value of each good to every agent is at most the agent's WMMS. Aziz, Chan and Li[12] adapted the notion of WMMS to chores (items with negative utilities). They showed that, even for two agents, it is impossible to guarantee more than 4/3 of the WMMS (Note that with chores, the approximation ratios are larger than 1, and smaller is better). They present a 3/2-WMMS approximation algorithm for two agents, and an WMMS algorithm for n agents with binary valuations. They also define the OWMMS, which is the optimal approximation of WMMS that is attainable in the given instance. They present a polynomial-time algorithm that attains a 4-factor approximation of the OWMMS.

The WMMS is a cardinal notion in that, if the cardinal utilities of an agent changes, then the set of bundles that satisfy the WMMS for the agent may change. Babaioff, Nisan and Talgam-Cohen[13] introduced another adaptation of the MMS to agents with different entitlements, which is based only on the agent's ordinal ranking of the bundles. They show that this fairness notion is attained by a competitive equilibrium with different budgets, where the budgets are proportional to the entitlements. This fairness notion is called Ordinal Maximin Share (OMMS) by Chakraborty, Segal-Halevi and Suksompong.[14] The relation between various ordinal MMS approximations is further studied by Segal-Halevi.[15][16]

Babaioff, Ezra and Feige[17] present another ordinal notion, stronger than OMMS, which they call the AnyPrice Share (APS). They show a polynomial-time algorithm that attains a 3/5-fraction of the APS.

Aziz, Moulin and Sandomirskiy[18] present a strongly polynomial time algorithm that always finds a Pareto-optimal and WPROP(0,1) allocation for agents with different entitlements and arbitrary (positive or negative) valuations.

Relaxations of WEF have been studied, so far, only for goods. Chakraborty, Igarashi and Suksompong[19] introduced the weighted round-robin algorithm for WEF(1,0). In a follow-up work, Chakraborty, Schmidt-Kraepelin and Suksompong generalized the weighted round-robin algorithm to general picking-sequences, and studied various monotonicity properties of these sequences.

Items and money edit

In the problem of fair allocation of items and money, monetary transfers can be used to attain exact fairness of indivisible goods.

Corradi and Corradi[20] define an allocation as equitable if the utility of each agent i (defined as the value of items plus the money given to i) is r ti ui (AllItems), where r is the same for all agents.

They present an algorithm that finds an equitable allocation with r >= 1, which means that the allocation is also proportional.

Bargaining edit

Cooperative bargaining is the abstract problem of selecting a feasible vector of utilities, as a function of the set of feasible utility vectors (fair division is a special case of bargaining).

Three classic bargaining solutions have variants for agents with different entitlements. In particular:

References edit

  1. ^ Corradi, Marco Claudio; Corradi, Valentina (2001-04-21). "The Adjusted Knaster Procedure Under Unequal Entitlements". SSRN 2427304.
  2. ^ Geoffroy de Clippel; HerveMoulin; Nicolaus Tideman (March 2008), "Impartial division of a dollar", Journal of Economic Theory, 139 (1): 176–191, CiteSeerX 10.1.1.397.1420, doi:10.1016/j.jet.2007.06.005
  3. ^ Moulin, Herve (May 2000). "Priority Rules and Other Asymmetric Rationing Methods". Econometrica. 68 (3): 643–684. doi:10.1111/1468-0262.00126. ISSN 0012-9682.
  4. ^ Bava Metzia 2a. The disputed garment
  5. ^ Ketubot 93a. The estate division problem
  6. ^ Robert J. Aumann and Michael Maschler. Journal of Economic Theory 36, 195-213 (1985)
  7. ^ "Dominant Resource Fairness: Fair Allocation of Multiple Resource Types". 2011.
  8. ^ Dolev, Danny; Feitelson, Dror G.; Halpern, Joseph Y.; Kupferman, Raz; Linial, Nathan (2012-01-08). "No justified complaints". Proceedings of the 3rd Innovations in Theoretical Computer Science Conference. ITCS '12. New York, NY, USA: Association for Computing Machinery. pp. 68–75. doi:10.1145/2090236.2090243. ISBN 978-1-4503-1115-1. S2CID 9105218.
  9. ^ Gutman, Avital; Nisan, Noam (2012-04-19). "Fair Allocation Without Trade". arXiv:1204.4286 [cs.GT].
  10. ^ Aziz, Haris; Gaspers, Serge; Mackenzie, Simon; Walsh, Toby (2015-10-01). "Fair assignment of indivisible objects under ordinal preferences". Artificial Intelligence. 227: 71–92. arXiv:1312.6546. doi:10.1016/j.artint.2015.06.002. ISSN 0004-3702. S2CID 1408197.
  11. ^ Farhadi, Alireza; Ghodsi, Mohammad; Hajiaghayi, Mohammad Taghi; Lahaie, Sébastien; Pennock, David; Seddighin, Masoud; Seddighin, Saeed; Yami, Hadi (2019-01-07). "Fair Allocation of Indivisible Goods to Asymmetric Agents". Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research. 64: 1–20. arXiv:1703.01649. doi:10.1613/jair.1.11291. ISSN 1076-9757. S2CID 15326855.
  12. ^ Aziz, Haris; Chan, Hau; Li, Bo (2019-06-18). "Weighted Maxmin Fair Share Allocation of Indivisible Chores". arXiv:1906.07602 [cs.GT].
  13. ^ Babaioff, Moshe; Nisan, Noam; Talgam-Cohen, Inbal (2021-02-01). "Competitive Equilibrium with Indivisible Goods and Generic Budgets". Mathematics of Operations Research. 46 (1): 382–403. arXiv:1703.08150. doi:10.1287/moor.2020.1062. ISSN 0364-765X. S2CID 8514018.
  14. ^ Chakraborty, Mithun; Segal-Halevi, Erel; Suksompong, Warut (2021-12-08). "Weighted Fairness Notions for Indivisible Items Revisited". Proceedings of AAAI 2022. arXiv:2112.04166.
  15. ^ Segal-Halevi, Erel (2020-02-20). "Competitive equilibrium for almost all incomes: existence and fairness". Autonomous Agents and Multi-Agent Systems. 34 (1): 26. arXiv:1705.04212. doi:10.1007/s10458-020-09444-z. ISSN 1573-7454. S2CID 210911501.
  16. ^ Segal-Halevi, Erel (2019-12-18). "The Maximin Share Dominance Relation". arXiv:1912.08763 [math.CO].
  17. ^ Babaioff, Moshe; Ezra, Tomer; Feige, Uriel (2021-11-15). "Fair-Share Allocations for Agents with Arbitrary Entitlements". arXiv:2103.04304 [cs.GT].
  18. ^ Aziz, Haris; Moulin, Hervé; Sandomirskiy, Fedor (2020-09-01). "A polynomial-time algorithm for computing a Pareto optimal and almost proportional allocation". Operations Research Letters. 48 (5): 573–578. arXiv:1909.00740. doi:10.1016/j.orl.2020.07.005. ISSN 0167-6377. S2CID 202541717.
  19. ^ Chakraborty, Mithun; Igarashi, Ayumi; Suksompong, Warut; Zick, Yair (2021-08-16). "Weighted Envy-freeness in Indivisible Item Allocation". ACM Transactions on Economics and Computation. 9 (3): 18:1–39. arXiv:1909.10502. doi:10.1145/3457166. ISSN 2167-8375. S2CID 202719373.
  20. ^ Corradi, Marco Claudio; Corradi, Valentina (2001-04-21). "The Adjusted Knaster Procedure Under Unequal Entitlements". SSRN 2427304.
  21. ^ Kalai, E. (1977-09-01). "Nonsymmetric Nash solutions and replications of 2-person bargaining". International Journal of Game Theory. 6 (3): 129–133. doi:10.1007/BF01774658. ISSN 1432-1270. S2CID 122236229.
  22. ^ Thomson, William (1994), "Cooperative models of bargaining", Handbook of Game Theory with Economic Applications, 2, Elsevier: 1237–1284, doi:10.1016/S1574-0005(05)80067-0, retrieved 2022-03-29
  23. ^ Driesen, Bram W. (2012). The Asymmetric Leximin Solution (Report). doi:10.11588/heidok.00013124.

entitlement, fair, division, entitlement, fair, division, describes, that, proportion, resources, goods, divided, that, player, expect, receive, many, fair, division, settings, agents, have, equal, entitlements, which, means, that, each, agent, entitled, resou. Entitlement in fair division describes that proportion of the resources or goods to be divided that a player can expect to receive In many fair division settings all agents have equal entitlements which means that each agent is entitled to 1 n of the resource But there are practical settings in which agents have different entitlements Some examples are In partnership resolution settings each partner is entitled to a fraction of the common assets in proportion to his her investment in the partnership In inheritance settings the law in some jurisdictions prescribes a different share to each heir according to his her proximity to the deceased person For example according to the Bible the firstborn son must receive twice as much as every other son In contrast according to the Italian law when there are three heirs parent brother and spouse they are entitled to 1 4 1 12 and 2 3 respectively 1 In parliamentary democracies each party is entitled to a number of seats in the parliament that is in general proportional to the number of votes it received The idea is based on the normal idea of entitlement Entitlements can be determined by agreeing on a cooperative game and using its value as the entitlement When agents have equal entitlements it is reasonable to require that the solution satisfies the axiom of anonymity also called symmetry that is agents are treated only by their valuations and not by their names In contrast when agents have different entitlements anonymity is no longer valid and the solutions must be asymmetric Various problems of fair division with different entitlements have been studied Contents 1 Dividing money 1 1 In the Talmud 2 Dividing continuous resources 3 Fair item allocation 3 1 Identical indivisible items dividing seats in parliaments 3 2 Heterogeneous indivisible items 3 3 Items and money 4 Bargaining 5 ReferencesDividing money editEven when only money is to be divided and some fixed amount has been specified for each recipient the problem can be complex The amounts specified may be more or less than the amount of money and the profit or loss will then need to be shared out The proportional rule is normally used in law nowadays and is the default assumption in the theory of bankruptcy Other rules however are often used for example The Shapley value is one common method of deciding bargaining power as can be seen in the airport problem In economics an allocation which cannot be improved upon by any coalition is said to have the core property Welfare economics on the other hand tries to determine allocations depending on fairness criteria The people can also agree on their relative entitlements by a consensus process For instance they could say what they think everyone else is entitled to and if the assessments agree then they have an agreed impartial consensus division 2 Priority rules are another kind of mechanism for allocation with different entitlements 3 In the Talmud edit The Talmud has a number of examples where entitlements are not decided on a proportional basis The disputed garment problem If one person claims the whole of a cloth and another half then it is divided 3 4 and 1 4 4 The estate division problem Three wives have claims to 100 200 and 300 zuz Three cases are considered if the estate is 100 zuz then they get 33 and a third each if 200 then 50 75 75 and if 300 then 50 100 and 150 5 Profits from a joint fund If two people put 200 and 100 into a fund and buy an ox for ploughing and use it for that purpose they divide the profit evenly between them But if they instead then slaughter the ox they divide the profit in proportion This is discussed in the Babylonian Talmud just after the estate division problem Ibn Ezra s problem This is a later problem of estate division that was solved in a different way A man with an estate of 120 dies bequeathing 120 60 40 and 30 to his four sons The recommendation was to award 120 60 1 60 40 2 40 30 3 30 0 4 to the first and sums with leading terms removed for the rest ending with 30 4 for the last This allocation is different from the previous estate divisionThese solutions can all be modeled by cooperative games The estate division problem has a large literature and was first given a theoretical basis in game theory by Robert J Aumann and Michael Maschler in 1985 6 See Contested garment rule Dividing continuous resources editFair cake cutting is the problem of dividing a heterogeneous continuous resource There always exists a proportional cake cutting respecting the different entitlements The two main research questions are a how many cuts are required for a fair division b how many queries are needed for computing a division See Proportional cake cutting with different entitlements Envy free cake cutting with different entitlements Cloud computing environments require to divide multiple homogeneous divisible resources e g memory or CPU between users where each user needs a different combination of resources 7 The setting in which agents may have different entitlements has been studied by 8 and 9 Fair item allocation editIdentical indivisible items dividing seats in parliaments edit In parliamentary democracies with proportional representation each party is entitled to seats in proportion to its number of votes In multi constituency systems each constituency is entitled to seats in proportion to its population This is a problem of dividing identical indivisible items the seats among agents with different entitlements It is called the apportionment problem The allocation of seats by size of population can leave small constituencies with no voice at all The easiest solution is to have constituencies of equal size Sometimes however this can prove impossible for instance in the European Union or United States Ensuring the voting power is proportional to the size of constituencies is a problem of entitlement There are a number of methods which compute a voting power for different sized or weighted constituencies The main ones are the Shapley Shubik power index the Banzhaf power index These power indexes assume the constituencies can join up in any random way and approximate to the square root of the weighting as given by the Penrose method This assumption does not correspond to actual practice and it is arguable that larger constituencies are unfairly treated by them Heterogeneous indivisible items edit In the more complex setting of fair item allocation there are multiple different items with possibly different values to different people Aziz Gaspers Mackenzie and Walsh 10 sec 7 2 define proportionality and envy freeness for agents with different entitlements when the agents reveal only an ordinal ranking on the items rather than their complete utility functions They present a polynomial time algorithm for checking whether there exists an allocation that is possibly proportional proportional according to at least one utility profile consistent with the agent rankings or necessarily proportional proportional according to all utility profiles consistent with the rankings Farhadi Ghodsi Hajiaghayi Lahaie Pennock Seddighin Seddighin and Yami 11 defined the Weighted Maximin Share WMMS as a generalization of the maximin share to agents with different entitlements They showed that the best attainable multiplicative guarantee for the WMMS is 1 n in general and 1 2 in the special case in which the value of each good to every agent is at most the agent s WMMS Aziz Chan and Li 12 adapted the notion of WMMS to chores items with negative utilities They showed that even for two agents it is impossible to guarantee more than 4 3 of the WMMS Note that with chores the approximation ratios are larger than 1 and smaller is better They present a 3 2 WMMS approximation algorithm for two agents and an WMMS algorithm for n agents with binary valuations They also define the OWMMS which is the optimal approximation of WMMS that is attainable in the given instance They present a polynomial time algorithm that attains a 4 factor approximation of the OWMMS The WMMS is a cardinal notion in that if the cardinal utilities of an agent changes then the set of bundles that satisfy the WMMS for the agent may change Babaioff Nisan and Talgam Cohen 13 introduced another adaptation of the MMS to agents with different entitlements which is based only on the agent s ordinal ranking of the bundles They show that this fairness notion is attained by a competitive equilibrium with different budgets where the budgets are proportional to the entitlements This fairness notion is called Ordinal Maximin Share OMMS by Chakraborty Segal Halevi and Suksompong 14 The relation between various ordinal MMS approximations is further studied by Segal Halevi 15 16 Babaioff Ezra and Feige 17 present another ordinal notion stronger than OMMS which they call the AnyPrice Share APS They show a polynomial time algorithm that attains a 3 5 fraction of the APS Aziz Moulin and Sandomirskiy 18 present a strongly polynomial time algorithm that always finds a Pareto optimal and WPROP 0 1 allocation for agents with different entitlements and arbitrary positive or negative valuations Relaxations of WEF have been studied so far only for goods Chakraborty Igarashi and Suksompong 19 introduced the weighted round robin algorithm for WEF 1 0 In a follow up work Chakraborty Schmidt Kraepelin and Suksompong generalized the weighted round robin algorithm to general picking sequences and studied various monotonicity properties of these sequences Items and money edit In the problem of fair allocation of items and money monetary transfers can be used to attain exact fairness of indivisible goods Corradi and Corradi 20 define an allocation as equitable if the utility of each agent i defined as the value of items plus the money given to i is r ti ui AllItems where r is the same for all agents They present an algorithm that finds an equitable allocation with r gt 1 which means that the allocation is also proportional Bargaining editCooperative bargaining is the abstract problem of selecting a feasible vector of utilities as a function of the set of feasible utility vectors fair division is a special case of bargaining Three classic bargaining solutions have variants for agents with different entitlements In particular Kalai 21 extended the Nash bargaining solution by introducing the max weighted Nash welfare rule Thomson 22 extended the Kalai Smorodinsky bargaining solution Driesen 23 extended the leximin rule by introducing the asymmetric leximin rule References edit Corradi Marco Claudio Corradi Valentina 2001 04 21 The Adjusted Knaster Procedure Under Unequal Entitlements SSRN 2427304 Geoffroy de Clippel HerveMoulin Nicolaus Tideman March 2008 Impartial division of a dollar Journal of Economic Theory 139 1 176 191 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 397 1420 doi 10 1016 j jet 2007 06 005 Moulin Herve May 2000 Priority Rules and Other Asymmetric Rationing Methods Econometrica 68 3 643 684 doi 10 1111 1468 0262 00126 ISSN 0012 9682 Bava Metzia 2a The disputed garment Ketubot 93a The estate division problem Game Theoretic Analysis of a bankruptcy Problem from the Talmud Robert J Aumann and Michael Maschler Journal of Economic Theory 36 195 213 1985 Dominant Resource Fairness Fair Allocation of Multiple Resource Types 2011 Dolev Danny Feitelson Dror G Halpern Joseph Y Kupferman Raz Linial Nathan 2012 01 08 No justified complaints Proceedings of the 3rd Innovations in Theoretical Computer Science Conference ITCS 12 New York NY USA Association for Computing Machinery pp 68 75 doi 10 1145 2090236 2090243 ISBN 978 1 4503 1115 1 S2CID 9105218 Gutman Avital Nisan Noam 2012 04 19 Fair Allocation Without Trade arXiv 1204 4286 cs GT Aziz Haris Gaspers Serge Mackenzie Simon Walsh Toby 2015 10 01 Fair assignment of indivisible objects under ordinal preferences Artificial Intelligence 227 71 92 arXiv 1312 6546 doi 10 1016 j artint 2015 06 002 ISSN 0004 3702 S2CID 1408197 Farhadi Alireza Ghodsi Mohammad Hajiaghayi Mohammad Taghi Lahaie Sebastien Pennock David Seddighin Masoud Seddighin Saeed Yami Hadi 2019 01 07 Fair Allocation of Indivisible Goods to Asymmetric Agents Journal of Artificial Intelligence Research 64 1 20 arXiv 1703 01649 doi 10 1613 jair 1 11291 ISSN 1076 9757 S2CID 15326855 Aziz Haris Chan Hau Li Bo 2019 06 18 Weighted Maxmin Fair Share Allocation of Indivisible Chores arXiv 1906 07602 cs GT Babaioff Moshe Nisan Noam Talgam Cohen Inbal 2021 02 01 Competitive Equilibrium with Indivisible Goods and Generic Budgets Mathematics of Operations Research 46 1 382 403 arXiv 1703 08150 doi 10 1287 moor 2020 1062 ISSN 0364 765X S2CID 8514018 Chakraborty Mithun Segal Halevi Erel Suksompong Warut 2021 12 08 Weighted Fairness Notions for Indivisible Items Revisited Proceedings of AAAI 2022 arXiv 2112 04166 Segal Halevi Erel 2020 02 20 Competitive equilibrium for almost all incomes existence and fairness Autonomous Agents and Multi Agent Systems 34 1 26 arXiv 1705 04212 doi 10 1007 s10458 020 09444 z ISSN 1573 7454 S2CID 210911501 Segal Halevi Erel 2019 12 18 The Maximin Share Dominance Relation arXiv 1912 08763 math CO Babaioff Moshe Ezra Tomer Feige Uriel 2021 11 15 Fair Share Allocations for Agents with Arbitrary Entitlements arXiv 2103 04304 cs GT Aziz Haris Moulin Herve Sandomirskiy Fedor 2020 09 01 A polynomial time algorithm for computing a Pareto optimal and almost proportional allocation Operations Research Letters 48 5 573 578 arXiv 1909 00740 doi 10 1016 j orl 2020 07 005 ISSN 0167 6377 S2CID 202541717 Chakraborty Mithun Igarashi Ayumi Suksompong Warut Zick Yair 2021 08 16 Weighted Envy freeness in Indivisible Item Allocation ACM Transactions on Economics and Computation 9 3 18 1 39 arXiv 1909 10502 doi 10 1145 3457166 ISSN 2167 8375 S2CID 202719373 Corradi Marco Claudio Corradi Valentina 2001 04 21 The Adjusted Knaster Procedure Under Unequal Entitlements SSRN 2427304 Kalai E 1977 09 01 Nonsymmetric Nash solutions and replications of 2 person bargaining International Journal of Game Theory 6 3 129 133 doi 10 1007 BF01774658 ISSN 1432 1270 S2CID 122236229 Thomson William 1994 Cooperative models of bargaining Handbook of Game Theory with Economic Applications 2 Elsevier 1237 1284 doi 10 1016 S1574 0005 05 80067 0 retrieved 2022 03 29 Driesen Bram W 2012 The Asymmetric Leximin Solution Report doi 10 11588 heidok 00013124 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Entitlement fair division amp oldid 1193743024, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.