fbpx
Wikipedia

Topos

In mathematics, a topos (US: /ˈtɒpɒs/, UK: /ˈtps, ˈtpɒs/; plural topoi /ˈtɒpɔɪ/ or /ˈtpɔɪ/, or toposes) is a category that behaves like the category of sheaves of sets on a topological space (or more generally: on a site). Topoi behave much like the category of sets and possess a notion of localization; they are a direct generalization of point-set topology.[1] The Grothendieck topoi find applications in algebraic geometry; the more general elementary topoi are used in logic.

The mathematical field that studies topoi is called topos theory.

Grothendieck topos (topos in geometry) edit

Since the introduction of sheaves into mathematics in the 1940s, a major theme has been to study a space by studying sheaves on a space. This idea was expounded by Alexander Grothendieck by introducing the notion of a "topos". The main utility of this notion is in the abundance of situations in mathematics where topological heuristics are very effective, but an honest topological space is lacking; it is sometimes possible to find a topos formalizing the heuristic. An important example of this programmatic idea is the étale topos of a scheme. Another illustration of the capability of Grothendieck topoi to incarnate the “essence” of different mathematical situations is given by their use as bridges for connecting theories which, albeit written in possibly very different languages, share a common mathematical content.[2][3]

Equivalent definitions edit

A Grothendieck topos is a category C which satisfies any one of the following three properties. (A theorem of Jean Giraud states that the properties below are all equivalent.)

Here Presh(D) denotes the category of contravariant functors from D to the category of sets; such a contravariant functor is frequently called a presheaf.

Giraud's axioms edit

Giraud's axioms for a category C are:

  • C has a small set of generators, and admits all small colimits. Furthermore, fiber products distribute over coproducts. That is, given a set I, an I-indexed coproduct mapping to A, and a morphism A'A, the pullback is an I-indexed coproduct of the pullbacks:
     
  • Sums in C are disjoint. In other words, the fiber product of X and Y over their sum is the initial object in C.
  • All equivalence relations in C are effective.

The last axiom needs the most explanation. If X is an object of C, an "equivalence relation" R on X is a map RX × X in C such that for any object Y in C, the induced map Hom(Y, R) → Hom(Y, X) × Hom(Y, X) gives an ordinary equivalence relation on the set Hom(Y, X). Since C has colimits we may form the coequalizer of the two maps RX; call this X/R. The equivalence relation is "effective" if the canonical map

 

is an isomorphism.

Examples edit

Giraud's theorem already gives "sheaves on sites" as a complete list of examples. Note, however, that nonequivalent sites often give rise to equivalent topoi. As indicated in the introduction, sheaves on ordinary topological spaces motivate many of the basic definitions and results of topos theory.

Category of sets and G-sets edit

The category of sets is an important special case: it plays the role of a point in topos theory. Indeed, a set may be thought of as a sheaf on a point since functors on the singleton category with a single object and only the identity morphism are just specific sets in the category of sets.

Similarly, there is a topos   for any group   which is equivalent to the category of  -sets. We construct this as the category of presheaves on the category with one object, but now the set of morphisms is given by the group  . Since any functor must give a  -action on the target, this gives the category of  -sets. Similarly, for a groupoid   the category of presheaves on   gives a collection of sets indexed by the set of objects in  , and the automorphisms of an object in   has an action on the target of the functor.

Topoi from ringed spaces edit

More exotic examples, and the raison d'être of topos theory, come from algebraic geometry. The basic example of a topos comes from the Zariski topos of a scheme. For each scheme   there is a site   (of objects given by open subsets and morphisms given by inclusions) whose category of presheaves forms the Zariski topos  . But once distinguished classes of morphisms are considered, there are multiple generalizations of this which leads to non-trivial mathematics. Moreover, topoi give the foundations for studying schemes purely as functors on the category of algebras.

To a scheme and even a stack one may associate an étale topos, an fppf topos, or a Nisnevich topos. Another important example of a topos is from the crystalline site. In the case of the étale topos, these form the foundational objects of study in anabelian geometry, which studies objects in algebraic geometry that are determined entirely by the structure of their étale fundamental group.

Pathologies edit

Topos theory is, in some sense, a generalization of classical point-set topology. One should therefore expect to see old and new instances of pathological behavior. For instance, there is an example due to Pierre Deligne of a nontrivial topos that has no points (see below for the definition of points of a topos).

Geometric morphisms edit

If   and   are topoi, a geometric morphism   is a pair of adjoint functors (u,u) (where u : YX is left adjoint to u : XY) such that u preserves finite limits. Note that u automatically preserves colimits by virtue of having a right adjoint.

By Freyd's adjoint functor theorem, to give a geometric morphism XY is to give a functor uYX that preserves finite limits and all small colimits. Thus geometric morphisms between topoi may be seen as analogues of maps of locales.

If   and   are topological spaces and   is a continuous map between them, then the pullback and pushforward operations on sheaves yield a geometric morphism between the associated topoi for the sites  .

Points of topoi edit

A point of a topos   is defined as a geometric morphism from the topos of sets to  .

If X is an ordinary space and x is a point of X, then the functor that takes a sheaf F to its stalk Fx has a right adjoint (the "skyscraper sheaf" functor), so an ordinary point of X also determines a topos-theoretic point. These may be constructed as the pullback-pushforward along the continuous map x1X.

For the etale topos   of a space  , a point is a bit more refined of an object. Given a point   of the underlying scheme   a point   of the topos   is then given by a separable field extension   of   such that the associated map   factors through the original point  . Then, the factorization map

 
is an etale morphism of schemes.

More precisely, those are the global points. They are not adequate in themselves for displaying the space-like aspect of a topos, because a non-trivial topos may fail to have any. Generalized points are geometric morphisms from a topos Y (the stage of definition) to X. There are enough of these to display the space-like aspect. For example, if X is the classifying topos S[T] for a geometric theory T, then the universal property says that its points are the models of T (in any stage of definition Y).

Essential geometric morphisms edit

A geometric morphism (u,u) is essential if u has a further left adjoint u!, or equivalently (by the adjoint functor theorem) if u preserves not only finite but all small limits.

Ringed topoi edit

A ringed topos is a pair (X,R), where X is a topos and R is a commutative ring object in X. Most of the constructions of ringed spaces go through for ringed topoi. The category of R-module objects in X is an abelian category with enough injectives. A more useful abelian category is the subcategory of quasi-coherent R-modules: these are R-modules that admit a presentation.

Another important class of ringed topoi, besides ringed spaces, are the étale topoi of Deligne–Mumford stacks.

Homotopy theory of topoi edit

Michael Artin and Barry Mazur associated to the site underlying a topos a pro-simplicial set (up to homotopy).[4] (It's better to consider it in Ho(pro-SS); see Edwards) Using this inverse system of simplicial sets one may sometimes associate to a homotopy invariant in classical topology an inverse system of invariants in topos theory. The study of the pro-simplicial set associated to the étale topos of a scheme is called étale homotopy theory.[5] In good cases (if the scheme is Noetherian and geometrically unibranch), this pro-simplicial set is pro-finite.

Elementary topoi (topoi in logic) edit

Introduction edit

Since the early 20th century, the predominant axiomatic foundation of mathematics has been set theory, in which all mathematical objects are ultimately represented by sets (including functions, which map between sets). More recent work in category theory allows this foundation to be generalized using topoi; each topos completely defines its own mathematical framework. The category of sets forms a familiar topos, and working within this topos is equivalent to using traditional set-theoretic mathematics. But one could instead choose to work with many alternative topoi. A standard formulation of the axiom of choice makes sense in any topos, and there are topoi in which it is invalid. Constructivists will be interested to work in a topos without the law of excluded middle. If symmetry under a particular group G is of importance, one can use the topos consisting of all G-sets.

It is also possible to encode an algebraic theory, such as the theory of groups, as a topos, in the form of a classifying topos. The individual models of the theory, i.e. the groups in our example, then correspond to functors from the encoding topos to the category of sets that respect the topos structure.

Formal definition edit

When used for foundational work a topos will be defined axiomatically; set theory is then treated as a special case of topos theory. Building from category theory, there are multiple equivalent definitions of a topos. The following has the virtue of being concise:

A topos is a category that has the following two properties:

  • All limits taken over finite index categories exist.
  • Every object has a power object. This plays the role of the powerset in set theory.

Formally, a power object of an object   is a pair   with  , which classifies relations, in the following sense. First note that for every object  , a morphism   ("a family of subsets") induces a subobject  . Formally, this is defined by pulling back   along  . The universal property of a power object is that every relation arises in this way, giving a bijective correspondence between relations   and morphisms  .

From finite limits and power objects one can derive that

In some applications, the role of the subobject classifier is pivotal, whereas power objects are not. Thus some definitions reverse the roles of what is defined and what is derived.

Logical functors edit

A logical functor is a functor between topoi that preserves finite limits and power objects. Logical functors preserve the structures that topoi have. In particular, they preserve finite colimits, subobject classifiers, and exponential objects.[6]

Explanation edit

A topos as defined above can be understood as a Cartesian closed category for which the notion of subobject of an object has an elementary or first-order definition. This notion, as a natural categorical abstraction of the notions of subset of a set, subgroup of a group, and more generally subalgebra of any algebraic structure, predates the notion of topos. It is definable in any category, not just topoi, in second-order language, i.e. in terms of classes of morphisms instead of individual morphisms, as follows. Given two monics m, n from respectively Y and Z to X, we say that mn when there exists a morphism p: YZ for which np = m, inducing a preorder on monics to X. When mn and nm we say that m and n are equivalent. The subobjects of X are the resulting equivalence classes of the monics to it.

In a topos "subobject" becomes, at least implicitly, a first-order notion, as follows.

As noted above, a topos is a category C having all finite limits and hence in particular the empty limit or final object 1. It is then natural to treat morphisms of the form x: 1 → X as elements xX. Morphisms f: XY thus correspond to functions mapping each element xX to the element fxY, with application realized by composition.

One might then think to define a subobject of X as an equivalence class of monics m: X′X having the same image { mx | xX′ }. The catch is that two or more morphisms may correspond to the same function, that is, we cannot assume that C is concrete in the sense that the functor C(1,-): CSet is faithful. For example the category Grph of graphs and their associated homomorphisms is a topos whose final object 1 is the graph with one vertex and one edge (a self-loop), but is not concrete because the elements 1 → G of a graph G correspond only to the self-loops and not the other edges, nor the vertices without self-loops. Whereas the second-order definition makes G and the subgraph of all self-loops of G (with their vertices) distinct subobjects of G (unless every edge is, and every vertex has, a self-loop), this image-based one does not. This can be addressed for the graph example and related examples via the Yoneda Lemma as described in the Further examples section below, but this then ceases to be first-order. Topoi provide a more abstract, general, and first-order solution.

 
Figure 1. m as a pullback of the generic subobject t along f.

As noted above, a topos C has a subobject classifier Ω, namely an object of C with an element t ∈ Ω, the generic subobject of C, having the property that every monic m: X′X arises as a pullback of the generic subobject along a unique morphism f: X → Ω, as per Figure 1. Now the pullback of a monic is a monic, and all elements including t are monics since there is only one morphism to 1 from any given object, whence the pullback of t along f: X → Ω is a monic. The monics to X are therefore in bijection with the pullbacks of t along morphisms from X to Ω. The latter morphisms partition the monics into equivalence classes each determined by a morphism f: X → Ω, the characteristic morphism of that class, which we take to be the subobject of X characterized or named by f.

All this applies to any topos, whether or not concrete. In the concrete case, namely C(1,-) faithful, for example the category of sets, the situation reduces to the familiar behavior of functions. Here the monics m: X′X are exactly the injections (one-one functions) from X′ to X, and those with a given image { mx | xX′ } constitute the subobject of X corresponding to the morphism f: X → Ω for which f−1(t) is that image. The monics of a subobject will in general have many domains, all of which however will be in bijection with each other.

To summarize, this first-order notion of subobject classifier implicitly defines for a topos the same equivalence relation on monics to X as had previously been defined explicitly by the second-order notion of subobject for any category. The notion of equivalence relation on a class of morphisms is itself intrinsically second-order, which the definition of topos neatly sidesteps by explicitly defining only the notion of subobject classifier Ω, leaving the notion of subobject of X as an implicit consequence characterized (and hence namable) by its associated morphism f: X → Ω.

Further examples and non-examples edit

Every Grothendieck topos is an elementary topos, but the converse is not true (since every Grothendieck topos is cocomplete, which is not required from an elementary topos).

The categories of finite sets, of finite G-sets (actions of a group G on a finite set), and of finite graphs are elementary topoi that are not Grothendieck topoi.

If C is a small category, then the functor category SetC (consisting of all covariant functors from C to sets, with natural transformations as morphisms) is a topos. For instance, the category Grph of graphs of the kind permitting multiple directed edges between two vertices is a topos. Such a graph consists of two sets, an edge set and a vertex set, and two functions s,t between those sets, assigning to every edge e its source s(e) and target t(e). Grph is thus equivalent to the functor category SetC, where C is the category with two objects E and V and two morphisms s,t: EV giving respectively the source and target of each edge.

The Yoneda lemma asserts that Cop embeds in SetC as a full subcategory. In the graph example the embedding represents Cop as the subcategory of SetC whose two objects are V' as the one-vertex no-edge graph and E' as the two-vertex one-edge graph (both as functors), and whose two nonidentity morphisms are the two graph homomorphisms from V' to E' (both as natural transformations). The natural transformations from V' to an arbitrary graph (functor) G constitute the vertices of G while those from E' to G constitute its edges. Although SetC, which we can identify with Grph, is not made concrete by either V' or E' alone, the functor U: GrphSet2 sending object G to the pair of sets (Grph(V' ,G), Grph(E' ,G)) and morphism h: GH to the pair of functions (Grph(V' ,h), Grph(E' ,h)) is faithful. That is, a morphism of graphs can be understood as a pair of functions, one mapping the vertices and the other the edges, with application still realized as composition but now with multiple sorts of generalized elements. This shows that the traditional concept of a concrete category as one whose objects have an underlying set can be generalized to cater for a wider range of topoi by allowing an object to have multiple underlying sets, that is, to be multisorted.

The category of pointed sets with point-preserving functions is not a topos, since it doesn't have power objects: if   were the power object of the pointed set  , and   denotes the pointed singleton, then there is only one point-preserving function  , but the relations in   are as numerous as the pointed subsets of  . The category of abelian groups is also not a topos, for a similar reason: every group homomorphism must map 0 to 0.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Illusie 2004
  2. ^ Caramello, Olivia (2016). Grothendieck toposes as unifying `bridges' in Mathematics (PDF) (HDR). Paris Diderot University (Paris 7).
  3. ^ Caramello, Olivia (2017). Theories, Sites, Toposes: Relating and studying mathematical theories through topos-theoretic `bridges. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198758914.001.0001. ISBN 9780198758914.
  4. ^ Artin, Michael; Mazur, Barry (1969). Etale homotopy. Lecture Notes in Mathematics. Vol. 100. Springer-Verlag. doi:10.1007/BFb0080957. ISBN 978-3-540-36142-8.
  5. ^ Friedlander, Eric M. (1982), Étale homotopy of simplicial schemes, Annals of Mathematics Studies, vol. 104, Princeton University Press, ISBN 978-0-691-08317-9
  6. ^ McLarty 1992, p. 159

References edit

Some gentle papers
  • Edwards, D.A.; Hastings, H.M. (Summer 1980). "Čech Theory: its Past, Present, and Future" (PDF). Rocky Mountain Journal of Mathematics. 10 (3): 429–468. doi:10.1216/RMJ-1980-10-3-429. JSTOR 44236540.
  • Baez, John. "Topos theory in a nutshell". A gentle introduction.
  • Steven Vickers: "Toposes pour les nuls" and "Toposes pour les vraiment nuls." Elementary and even more elementary introductions to toposes as generalized spaces.
  • Illusie, Luc (2004). "What is...A Topos?" (PDF). Notices of the AMS. 51 (9): 160–1.

The following texts are easy-paced introductions to toposes and the basics of category theory. They should be suitable for those knowing little mathematical logic and set theory, even non-mathematicians.

  • Lawvere, F. William; Schanuel, Stephen H. (1997). Conceptual Mathematics: A First Introduction to Categories. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-47817-5. An "introduction to categories for computer scientists, logicians, physicists, linguists, etc." (cited from cover text).
  • Lawvere, F. William; Rosebrugh, Robert (2003). Sets for Mathematics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-01060-3. Introduces the foundations of mathematics from a categorical perspective.

Grothendieck foundational work on topoi:

The following monographs include an introduction to some or all of topos theory, but do not cater primarily to beginning students. Listed in (perceived) order of increasing difficulty.

  • McLarty, Colin (1992). Elementary Categories, Elementary Toposes. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-158949-2. A nice introduction to the basics of category theory, topos theory, and topos logic. Assumes very few prerequisites.
  • Goldblatt, Robert (2013) [1984]. Topoi: The Categorial Analysis of Logic. Courier Corporation. ISBN 978-0-486-31796-0. A good start. Available online at Robert Goldblatt's homepage.
  • Bell, John L. (2001). "The Development of Categorical Logic". In Gabbay, D.M.; Guenthner, Franz (eds.). Handbook of Philosophical Logic. Vol. 12 (2nd ed.). Springer. pp. 279–. ISBN 978-1-4020-3091-8. Version available online at John Bell's homepage.
  • MacLane, Saunders; Moerdijk, Ieke (2012) [1994]. Sheaves in Geometry and Logic: A First Introduction to Topos Theory. Springer. ISBN 978-1-4612-0927-0. More complete, and more difficult to read.
  • Barr, Michael; Wells, Charles (2013) [1985]. Toposes, Triples and Theories. Springer. ISBN 978-1-4899-0023-4. (Online version). More concise than Sheaves in Geometry and Logic, but hard on beginners.
Reference works for experts, less suitable for first introduction
  • Edwards, D.A.; Hastings, H.M. (1976). Čech and Steenrod homotopy theories with applications to geometric topology. Lecture Notes in Maths. Vol. 542. Springer-Verlag. doi:10.1007/BFb0081083. ISBN 978-3-540-38103-7.
  • Borceux, Francis (1994). Handbook of Categorical Algebra: Volume 3, Sheaf Theory. Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications. Vol. 52. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-44180-3. The third part of "Borceux' remarkable magnum opus", as Johnstone has labelled it. Still suitable as an introduction, though beginners may find it hard to recognize the most relevant results among the huge amount of material given.
  • Johnstone, Peter T. (2014) [1977]. Topos Theory. Courier. ISBN 978-0-486-49336-7. For a long time the standard compendium on topos theory. However, even Johnstone describes this work as "far too hard to read, and not for the faint-hearted."
  • Johnstone, Peter T. (2002). Sketches of an Elephant: A Topos Theory Compendium. Vol. 2. Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-851598-2. As of early 2010, two of the scheduled three volumes of this overwhelming compendium were available.
  • Caramello, Olivia (2017). Theories, Sites, Toposes: Relating and studying mathematical theories through topos-theoretic `bridges. Oxford University Press. doi:10.1093/oso/9780198758914.001.0001. ISBN 9780198758914.
Books that target special applications of topos theory
  • Pedicchio, Maria Cristina; Tholen, Walter; Rota, G.C., eds. (2004). Categorical Foundations: Special Topics in Order, Topology, Algebra, and Sheaf Theory. Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications. Vol. 97. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0-521-83414-8. Includes many interesting special applications.

topos, other, uses, disambiguation, this, article, needs, additional, citations, verification, please, help, improve, this, article, adding, citations, reliable, sources, unsourced, material, challenged, removed, find, sources, news, newspapers, books, scholar. For other uses see Topos disambiguation This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Topos news newspapers books scholar JSTOR July 2015 Learn how and when to remove this message In mathematics a topos US ˈ t ɒ p ɒ s UK ˈ t oʊ p oʊ s ˈ t oʊ p ɒ s plural topoi ˈ t ɒ p ɔɪ or ˈ t oʊ p ɔɪ or toposes is a category that behaves like the category of sheaves of sets on a topological space or more generally on a site Topoi behave much like the category of sets and possess a notion of localization they are a direct generalization of point set topology 1 The Grothendieck topoi find applications in algebraic geometry the more general elementary topoi are used in logic The mathematical field that studies topoi is called topos theory Contents 1 Grothendieck topos topos in geometry 1 1 Equivalent definitions 1 1 1 Giraud s axioms 1 2 Examples 1 2 1 Category of sets and G sets 1 2 2 Topoi from ringed spaces 1 2 3 Pathologies 1 3 Geometric morphisms 1 3 1 Points of topoi 1 3 2 Essential geometric morphisms 1 4 Ringed topoi 1 5 Homotopy theory of topoi 2 Elementary topoi topoi in logic 2 1 Introduction 2 2 Formal definition 2 3 Logical functors 2 4 Explanation 2 5 Further examples and non examples 3 See also 4 Notes 5 ReferencesGrothendieck topos topos in geometry editSince the introduction of sheaves into mathematics in the 1940s a major theme has been to study a space by studying sheaves on a space This idea was expounded by Alexander Grothendieck by introducing the notion of a topos The main utility of this notion is in the abundance of situations in mathematics where topological heuristics are very effective but an honest topological space is lacking it is sometimes possible to find a topos formalizing the heuristic An important example of this programmatic idea is the etale topos of a scheme Another illustration of the capability of Grothendieck topoi to incarnate the essence of different mathematical situations is given by their use as bridges for connecting theories which albeit written in possibly very different languages share a common mathematical content 2 3 Equivalent definitions edit A Grothendieck topos is a category C which satisfies any one of the following three properties A theorem of Jean Giraud states that the properties below are all equivalent There is a small category D and an inclusion C Presh D that admits a finite limit preserving left adjoint C is the category of sheaves on a Grothendieck site C satisfies Giraud s axioms below Here Presh D denotes the category of contravariant functors from D to the category of sets such a contravariant functor is frequently called a presheaf Giraud s axioms edit Giraud s axioms for a category C are C has a small set of generators and admits all small colimits Furthermore fiber products distribute over coproducts That is given a set I an I indexed coproduct mapping to A and a morphism A A the pullback is an I indexed coproduct of the pullbacks i I B i A A i I B i A A displaystyle left coprod i in I B i right times A A cong coprod i in I B i times A A nbsp Sums in C are disjoint In other words the fiber product of X and Y over their sum is the initial object in C All equivalence relations in C are effective The last axiom needs the most explanation If X is an object of C an equivalence relation R on X is a map R X X in C such that for any object Y in C the induced map Hom Y R Hom Y X Hom Y X gives an ordinary equivalence relation on the set Hom Y X Since C has colimits we may form the coequalizer of the two maps R X call this X R The equivalence relation is effective if the canonical map R X X R X displaystyle R to X times X R X nbsp is an isomorphism Examples edit Giraud s theorem already gives sheaves on sites as a complete list of examples Note however that nonequivalent sites often give rise to equivalent topoi As indicated in the introduction sheaves on ordinary topological spaces motivate many of the basic definitions and results of topos theory Category of sets and G sets edit The category of sets is an important special case it plays the role of a point in topos theory Indeed a set may be thought of as a sheaf on a point since functors on the singleton category with a single object and only the identity morphism are just specific sets in the category of sets Similarly there is a topos B G displaystyle BG nbsp for any group G displaystyle G nbsp which is equivalent to the category of G displaystyle G nbsp sets We construct this as the category of presheaves on the category with one object but now the set of morphisms is given by the group G displaystyle G nbsp Since any functor must give a G displaystyle G nbsp action on the target this gives the category of G displaystyle G nbsp sets Similarly for a groupoid G displaystyle mathcal G nbsp the category of presheaves on G displaystyle mathcal G nbsp gives a collection of sets indexed by the set of objects in G displaystyle mathcal G nbsp and the automorphisms of an object in G displaystyle mathcal G nbsp has an action on the target of the functor Topoi from ringed spaces edit More exotic examples and the raison d etre of topos theory come from algebraic geometry The basic example of a topos comes from the Zariski topos of a scheme For each scheme X displaystyle X nbsp there is a site Open X displaystyle text Open X nbsp of objects given by open subsets and morphisms given by inclusions whose category of presheaves forms the Zariski topos X Z a r displaystyle X Zar nbsp But once distinguished classes of morphisms are considered there are multiple generalizations of this which leads to non trivial mathematics Moreover topoi give the foundations for studying schemes purely as functors on the category of algebras To a scheme and even a stack one may associate an etale topos an fppf topos or a Nisnevich topos Another important example of a topos is from the crystalline site In the case of the etale topos these form the foundational objects of study in anabelian geometry which studies objects in algebraic geometry that are determined entirely by the structure of their etale fundamental group Pathologies edit Topos theory is in some sense a generalization of classical point set topology One should therefore expect to see old and new instances of pathological behavior For instance there is an example due to Pierre Deligne of a nontrivial topos that has no points see below for the definition of points of a topos Geometric morphisms edit If X displaystyle X nbsp and Y displaystyle Y nbsp are topoi a geometric morphism u X Y displaystyle u X to Y nbsp is a pair of adjoint functors u u where u Y X is left adjoint to u X Y such that u preserves finite limits Note that u automatically preserves colimits by virtue of having a right adjoint By Freyd s adjoint functor theorem to give a geometric morphism X Y is to give a functor u Y X that preserves finite limits and all small colimits Thus geometric morphisms between topoi may be seen as analogues of maps of locales If X displaystyle X nbsp and Y displaystyle Y nbsp are topological spaces and u displaystyle u nbsp is a continuous map between them then the pullback and pushforward operations on sheaves yield a geometric morphism between the associated topoi for the sites Open X Open Y displaystyle text Open X text Open Y nbsp Points of topoi edit A point of a topos X displaystyle X nbsp is defined as a geometric morphism from the topos of sets to X displaystyle X nbsp If X is an ordinary space and x is a point of X then the functor that takes a sheaf F to its stalk Fx has a right adjoint the skyscraper sheaf functor so an ordinary point of X also determines a topos theoretic point These may be constructed as the pullback pushforward along the continuous map x 1 X For the etale topos X e t displaystyle X et nbsp of a space X displaystyle X nbsp a point is a bit more refined of an object Given a point x Spec k x X displaystyle x text Spec kappa x to X nbsp of the underlying scheme X displaystyle X nbsp a point x displaystyle x nbsp of the topos X e t displaystyle X et nbsp is then given by a separable field extension k displaystyle k nbsp of k x displaystyle kappa x nbsp such that the associated map x Spec k X displaystyle x text Spec k to X nbsp factors through the original point x displaystyle x nbsp Then the factorization mapSpec k Spec k x displaystyle text Spec k to text Spec kappa x nbsp is an etale morphism of schemes More precisely those are the global points They are not adequate in themselves for displaying the space like aspect of a topos because a non trivial topos may fail to have any Generalized points are geometric morphisms from a topos Y the stage of definition to X There are enough of these to display the space like aspect For example if X is the classifying topos S T for a geometric theory T then the universal property says that its points are the models of T in any stage of definition Y Essential geometric morphisms edit A geometric morphism u u is essential if u has a further left adjoint u or equivalently by the adjoint functor theorem if u preserves not only finite but all small limits Ringed topoi edit Main article Ringed topos A ringed topos is a pair X R where X is a topos and R is a commutative ring object in X Most of the constructions of ringed spaces go through for ringed topoi The category of R module objects in X is an abelian category with enough injectives A more useful abelian category is the subcategory of quasi coherent R modules these are R modules that admit a presentation Another important class of ringed topoi besides ringed spaces are the etale topoi of Deligne Mumford stacks Homotopy theory of topoi edit Michael Artin and Barry Mazur associated to the site underlying a topos a pro simplicial set up to homotopy 4 It s better to consider it in Ho pro SS see Edwards Using this inverse system of simplicial sets one may sometimes associate to a homotopy invariant in classical topology an inverse system of invariants in topos theory The study of the pro simplicial set associated to the etale topos of a scheme is called etale homotopy theory 5 In good cases if the scheme is Noetherian and geometrically unibranch this pro simplicial set is pro finite Elementary topoi topoi in logic editIntroduction edit Since the early 20th century the predominant axiomatic foundation of mathematics has been set theory in which all mathematical objects are ultimately represented by sets including functions which map between sets More recent work in category theory allows this foundation to be generalized using topoi each topos completely defines its own mathematical framework The category of sets forms a familiar topos and working within this topos is equivalent to using traditional set theoretic mathematics But one could instead choose to work with many alternative topoi A standard formulation of the axiom of choice makes sense in any topos and there are topoi in which it is invalid Constructivists will be interested to work in a topos without the law of excluded middle If symmetry under a particular group G is of importance one can use the topos consisting of all G sets It is also possible to encode an algebraic theory such as the theory of groups as a topos in the form of a classifying topos The individual models of the theory i e the groups in our example then correspond to functors from the encoding topos to the category of sets that respect the topos structure Formal definition edit When used for foundational work a topos will be defined axiomatically set theory is then treated as a special case of topos theory Building from category theory there are multiple equivalent definitions of a topos The following has the virtue of being concise A topos is a category that has the following two properties All limits taken over finite index categories exist Every object has a power object This plays the role of the powerset in set theory Formally a power object of an object X displaystyle X nbsp is a pair P X X displaystyle PX ni X nbsp with X P X X displaystyle ni X subseteq PX times X nbsp which classifies relations in the following sense First note that for every object I displaystyle I nbsp a morphism r I P X displaystyle r colon I to PX nbsp a family of subsets induces a subobject i x x r i I X displaystyle i x x in r i subseteq I times X nbsp Formally this is defined by pulling back X displaystyle ni X nbsp along r X I X P X X displaystyle r times X I times X to PX times X nbsp The universal property of a power object is that every relation arises in this way giving a bijective correspondence between relations R I X displaystyle R subseteq I times X nbsp and morphisms r I P X displaystyle r colon I to PX nbsp From finite limits and power objects one can derive that All colimits taken over finite index categories exist The category has a subobject classifier The category is Cartesian closed In some applications the role of the subobject classifier is pivotal whereas power objects are not Thus some definitions reverse the roles of what is defined and what is derived Logical functors edit A logical functor is a functor between topoi that preserves finite limits and power objects Logical functors preserve the structures that topoi have In particular they preserve finite colimits subobject classifiers and exponential objects 6 Explanation edit A topos as defined above can be understood as a Cartesian closed category for which the notion of subobject of an object has an elementary or first order definition This notion as a natural categorical abstraction of the notions of subset of a set subgroup of a group and more generally subalgebra of any algebraic structure predates the notion of topos It is definable in any category not just topoi in second order language i e in terms of classes of morphisms instead of individual morphisms as follows Given two monics m n from respectively Y and Z to X we say that m n when there exists a morphism p Y Z for which np m inducing a preorder on monics to X When m n and n m we say that m and n are equivalent The subobjects of X are the resulting equivalence classes of the monics to it In a topos subobject becomes at least implicitly a first order notion as follows As noted above a topos is a category C having all finite limits and hence in particular the empty limit or final object 1 It is then natural to treat morphisms of the form x 1 X as elements x X Morphisms f X Y thus correspond to functions mapping each element x X to the element fx Y with application realized by composition One might then think to define a subobject of X as an equivalence class of monics m X X having the same image mx x X The catch is that two or more morphisms may correspond to the same function that is we cannot assume that C is concrete in the sense that the functor C 1 C Set is faithful For example the category Grph of graphs and their associated homomorphisms is a topos whose final object 1 is the graph with one vertex and one edge a self loop but is not concrete because the elements 1 G of a graph G correspond only to the self loops and not the other edges nor the vertices without self loops Whereas the second order definition makes G and the subgraph of all self loops of G with their vertices distinct subobjects of G unless every edge is and every vertex has a self loop this image based one does not This can be addressed for the graph example and related examples via the Yoneda Lemma as described in the Further examples section below but this then ceases to be first order Topoi provide a more abstract general and first order solution nbsp Figure 1 m as a pullback of the generic subobject t along f As noted above a topos C has a subobject classifier W namely an object of C with an element t W the generic subobject of C having the property that every monic m X X arises as a pullback of the generic subobject along a unique morphism f X W as per Figure 1 Now the pullback of a monic is a monic and all elements including t are monics since there is only one morphism to 1 from any given object whence the pullback of t along f X W is a monic The monics to X are therefore in bijection with the pullbacks of t along morphisms from X to W The latter morphisms partition the monics into equivalence classes each determined by a morphism f X W the characteristic morphism of that class which we take to be the subobject of X characterized or named by f All this applies to any topos whether or not concrete In the concrete case namely C 1 faithful for example the category of sets the situation reduces to the familiar behavior of functions Here the monics m X X are exactly the injections one one functions from X to X and those with a given image mx x X constitute the subobject of X corresponding to the morphism f X W for which f 1 t is that image The monics of a subobject will in general have many domains all of which however will be in bijection with each other To summarize this first order notion of subobject classifier implicitly defines for a topos the same equivalence relation on monics to X as had previously been defined explicitly by the second order notion of subobject for any category The notion of equivalence relation on a class of morphisms is itself intrinsically second order which the definition of topos neatly sidesteps by explicitly defining only the notion of subobject classifier W leaving the notion of subobject of X as an implicit consequence characterized and hence namable by its associated morphism f X W Further examples and non examples edit Every Grothendieck topos is an elementary topos but the converse is not true since every Grothendieck topos is cocomplete which is not required from an elementary topos The categories of finite sets of finite G sets actions of a group G on a finite set and of finite graphs are elementary topoi that are not Grothendieck topoi If C is a small category then the functor category SetC consisting of all covariant functors from C to sets with natural transformations as morphisms is a topos For instance the category Grph of graphs of the kind permitting multiple directed edges between two vertices is a topos Such a graph consists of two sets an edge set and a vertex set and two functions s t between those sets assigning to every edge e its source s e and target t e Grph is thus equivalent to the functor category SetC where C is the category with two objects E and V and two morphisms s t E V giving respectively the source and target of each edge The Yoneda lemma asserts that Cop embeds in SetC as a full subcategory In the graph example the embedding represents Cop as the subcategory of SetC whose two objects are V as the one vertex no edge graph and E as the two vertex one edge graph both as functors and whose two nonidentity morphisms are the two graph homomorphisms from V to E both as natural transformations The natural transformations from V to an arbitrary graph functor G constitute the vertices of G while those from E to G constitute its edges Although SetC which we can identify with Grph is not made concrete by either V or E alone the functor U Grph Set2 sending object G to the pair of sets Grph V G Grph E G and morphism h G H to the pair of functions Grph V h Grph E h is faithful That is a morphism of graphs can be understood as a pair of functions one mapping the vertices and the other the edges with application still realized as composition but now with multiple sorts of generalized elements This shows that the traditional concept of a concrete category as one whose objects have an underlying set can be generalized to cater for a wider range of topoi by allowing an object to have multiple underlying sets that is to be multisorted The category of pointed sets with point preserving functions is not a topos since it doesn t have power objects if P X displaystyle PX nbsp were the power object of the pointed set X displaystyle X nbsp and 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp denotes the pointed singleton then there is only one point preserving function r 1 P X displaystyle r colon 1 to PX nbsp but the relations in 1 X displaystyle 1 times X nbsp are as numerous as the pointed subsets of X displaystyle X nbsp The category of abelian groups is also not a topos for a similar reason every group homomorphism must map 0 to 0 See also edit nbsp Mathematics portal History of topos theory Homotopy hypothesis Intuitionistic type theory topos Quasitopos Geometric logicNotes edit Illusie 2004 Caramello Olivia 2016 Grothendieck toposes as unifying bridges in Mathematics PDF HDR Paris Diderot University Paris 7 Caramello Olivia 2017 Theories Sites Toposes Relating and studying mathematical theories through topos theoretic bridges Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 oso 9780198758914 001 0001 ISBN 9780198758914 Artin Michael Mazur Barry 1969 Etale homotopy Lecture Notes in Mathematics Vol 100 Springer Verlag doi 10 1007 BFb0080957 ISBN 978 3 540 36142 8 Friedlander Eric M 1982 Etale homotopy of simplicial schemes Annals of Mathematics Studies vol 104 Princeton University Press ISBN 978 0 691 08317 9 McLarty 1992 p 159References editSome gentle papers Edwards D A Hastings H M Summer 1980 Cech Theory its Past Present and Future PDF Rocky Mountain Journal of Mathematics 10 3 429 468 doi 10 1216 RMJ 1980 10 3 429 JSTOR 44236540 Baez John Topos theory in a nutshell A gentle introduction Steven Vickers Toposes pour les nuls and Toposes pour les vraiment nuls Elementary and even more elementary introductions to toposes as generalized spaces Illusie Luc 2004 What is A Topos PDF Notices of the AMS 51 9 160 1 The following texts are easy paced introductions to toposes and the basics of category theory They should be suitable for those knowing little mathematical logic and set theory even non mathematicians Lawvere F William Schanuel Stephen H 1997 Conceptual Mathematics A First Introduction to Categories Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 47817 5 An introduction to categories for computer scientists logicians physicists linguists etc cited from cover text Lawvere F William Rosebrugh Robert 2003 Sets for Mathematics Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 01060 3 Introduces the foundations of mathematics from a categorical perspective Grothendieck foundational work on topoi Grothendieck A Verdier J L 1972 Theorie des Topos et Cohomologie Etale des Schemas Lecture notes in mathematics Vol 269 Springer doi 10 1007 BFb0081551 ISBN 978 3 540 37549 4 Tome 2 270 doi 10 1007 BFb0061319 ISBN 978 3 540 37987 4 The following monographs include an introduction to some or all of topos theory but do not cater primarily to beginning students Listed in perceived order of increasing difficulty McLarty Colin 1992 Elementary Categories Elementary Toposes Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 158949 2 A nice introduction to the basics of category theory topos theory and topos logic Assumes very few prerequisites Goldblatt Robert 2013 1984 Topoi The Categorial Analysis of Logic Courier Corporation ISBN 978 0 486 31796 0 A good start Available online at Robert Goldblatt s homepage Bell John L 2001 The Development of Categorical Logic In Gabbay D M Guenthner Franz eds Handbook of Philosophical Logic Vol 12 2nd ed Springer pp 279 ISBN 978 1 4020 3091 8 Version available online at John Bell s homepage MacLane Saunders Moerdijk Ieke 2012 1994 Sheaves in Geometry and Logic A First Introduction to Topos Theory Springer ISBN 978 1 4612 0927 0 More complete and more difficult to read Barr Michael Wells Charles 2013 1985 Toposes Triples and Theories Springer ISBN 978 1 4899 0023 4 Online version More concise than Sheaves in Geometry and Logic but hard on beginners Reference works for experts less suitable for first introduction Edwards D A Hastings H M 1976 Cech and Steenrod homotopy theories with applications to geometric topology Lecture Notes in Maths Vol 542 Springer Verlag doi 10 1007 BFb0081083 ISBN 978 3 540 38103 7 Borceux Francis 1994 Handbook of Categorical Algebra Volume 3 Sheaf Theory Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications Vol 52 Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 44180 3 The third part of Borceux remarkable magnum opus as Johnstone has labelled it Still suitable as an introduction though beginners may find it hard to recognize the most relevant results among the huge amount of material given Johnstone Peter T 2014 1977 Topos Theory Courier ISBN 978 0 486 49336 7 For a long time the standard compendium on topos theory However even Johnstone describes this work as far too hard to read and not for the faint hearted Johnstone Peter T 2002 Sketches of an Elephant A Topos Theory Compendium Vol 2 Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 851598 2 As of early 2010 two of the scheduled three volumes of this overwhelming compendium were available Caramello Olivia 2017 Theories Sites Toposes Relating and studying mathematical theories through topos theoretic bridges Oxford University Press doi 10 1093 oso 9780198758914 001 0001 ISBN 9780198758914 Books that target special applications of topos theory Pedicchio Maria Cristina Tholen Walter Rota G C eds 2004 Categorical Foundations Special Topics in Order Topology Algebra and Sheaf Theory Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications Vol 97 Cambridge University Press ISBN 978 0 521 83414 8 Includes many interesting special applications Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Topos amp oldid 1209239884 Elementary topoi topoi in logic, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.