fbpx
Wikipedia

Divine simplicity

In monotheistic theology, the doctrine of Divine Simplicity says that God is simple (without parts).

This is the idea that God does not exist in parts but is one unified entity, with no distinct attributes; that is, God’s existence is identical to God’s essence.

Overview Edit

The general idea can be stated in this way: The being of God is identical to the "attributes" of God. Characteristics such as omnipresence, goodness, truth, eternity, etc., are identical to God's being, not qualities that make up that being as a collection, nor abstract entities inhering in God as in a substance; in other words, one can say that in God both essence and existence are one and the same.[1] This is not to say that God is a simpleton or "simple" to understand. As Peter Weigel states, "Divine simplicity is central to the classical Western concept of God."

Simplicity denies any physical or metaphysical composition in the divine being. This means God is the divine nature itself and has no accidents (properties that are not necessary) accruing to his nature. There are no real divisions or distinctions of this nature. Thus, the entirety of God is whatever is attributed to him. Divine simplicity is the hallmark of God’s utter transcendence of all else, ensuring the divine nature to be beyond the reach of ordinary categories and distinctions, or at least their ordinary application. "Simplicity in this way confers a unique ontological status that many philosophers find highly peculiar."[2] So when it comes to God's essential nature or attributes, there are no parts or accidents; this is not to be confused with, for example, God's accidental or contingent relation to the world (i.e., God's non-essential or contingent properties, not God's nature).[2][3]

Varieties of the doctrine may be found among Jewish, Christian, and Muslim philosophical theologians, especially during the height of Scholasticism, although the doctrine's origins may be traced back to ancient Greek thought, finding apotheosis in Plotinus' Enneads as the Simplex.[4][5][6]

History Edit

Views close to Divine Simplicity were held by philosophers such as: Plato, Thales and Anaximenes. Classical statements concerning divine simplicity can be found in Augustine, Anselm and Thomas Aquinas. When Christianity had just began, Philo of Alexandria mentioned how the belief of God as utterly simple was widely held.[7] One of the earliest mentions of divine simplicity in Christian theology comes from Irenaeus (130 - c. 202 AD).[8] Early Christian theology viewed simplicity as necessary for preserving God's transcendence, Athenagoras of Athens in the second century argued that God is utterly indivisible and unchangeable.[7]

Clement of Alexandria, Basil and Cyril saw simplicity as preserving the transcendence and the perfection of God.[7]

In Jewish thought Edit

In Jewish philosophy and in Kabbalah, divine simplicity is addressed via discussion of the attributes (תארים‎) of God, particularly by Jewish philosophers within the Muslim sphere of influence such as Saadia Gaon, Bahya ibn Paquda, Yehuda Halevi, and Maimonides, as well by Raabad III in Provence. A classic expression of this position is found in Maimonides' work Guide to the Perplexed:[9]

If, however, you have a desire to rise to a higher state, viz., that of reflection, and truly to hold the conviction that God is One and possesses true unity, without admitting plurality or divisibility in any sense whatever, you must understand that God has no essential attribute in any form or in any sense whatever, and that the rejection of corporeality implies the rejection of essential attributes. Those who believe that God is One, and that He has many attributes, declare the unity with their lips, and assume plurality in their thoughts.

According to Maimonides, then, there can be no plurality of faculties, moral dispositions, or essential attributes in God. Even to say that God is all-knowing, all-powerful, and all-good is to introduce plurality, if one means thereby that these qualities are separate attributes. Maimonides therefore concludes that it is not true to say that God's power is greater than ours, that God's life is more permanent than ours, or that God's knowledge is broader than ours. Maimonedes believed that statements such as "God lives" or "God is powerful" are nonsense if they are interpreted in the normal fashion, but they can be understood if one analyzes them as disguised negations. Still, Maimonedes also believed that negation is objectionable to the degree that it introduces complexity: God is neither this nor that, and ultimately any kind of verbal expression fails us. Citing Psalm 65, Maimonides concludes that the highest form of praise we can give God is silence.[10]

Some[who?] identify divine simplicity as a corollary of Divine Creation: "In the beginning God created the heaven and the earth" (Genesis 1:1). God, as creator is by definition separate from the universe and thus free of any property (and hence an absolute unity); see Negative theology.

For others, conversely, the axiom of Divine Unity (see Shema Yisrael) informs the understanding of divine simplicity. Bahya ibn Paquda (Duties of the Heart 1:8) points out that God's Oneness is "true oneness" (האחד האמת) as opposed to merely "circumstantial oneness" (האחד המקרי). He develops this idea to show that an entity which is truly one must be free of properties and thus indescribable – and unlike anything else. (Additionally such an entity would be absolutely unsubject to change, as well as utterly independent and the root of everything.)

The implication – of either approach – is so strong that the two concepts are often presented as synonymous: "God is not two or more entities, but a single entity of a oneness even more single and unique than any single thing in creation… He cannot be sub-divided into different parts – therefore, it is impossible for Him to be anything other than one. It is a positive commandment to know this, for it is written (Deuteronomy 6:4) '…the Lord is our God, the Lord is one'." (Maimonides, Mishneh Torah, Mada 1:7.)

Despite its apparent simplicity, this concept is recognised as raising many difficulties. In particular, insofar as God's simplicity does not allow for any structure – even conceptually – divine simplicity appears to entail the following dichotomy.

  • On the one hand, God is absolutely simple, containing no element of form or structure, as above.
  • On the other hand, it is understood that God's essence contains every possible element of perfection: "The First Foundation is to believe in the existence of the Creator, blessed be He. This means that there exists a Being that is perfect (complete) in all ways and He is the cause of all else that exists." (Maimonides 13 principles of faith, First Principle).

The resultant paradox is famously articulated by Moshe Chaim Luzzatto (Derekh Hashem I:1:5), describing the dichotomy as arising out of our inability to comprehend the idea of absolute unity:

God’s existence is absolutely simple, without combinations or additions of any kind. All perfections are found in Him in a perfectly simple manner. However, God does not entail separate domains – even though in truth there exist in God qualities which, within us, are separate… Indeed the true nature of His essence is that it is a single attribute, (yet) one that intrinsically encompasses everything that could be considered perfection. All perfection therefore exists in God, not as something added on to His existence, but as an integral part of His intrinsic identity… This is a concept that is very far from our ability to grasp and imagine…

The Kabbalists address this paradox by explaining that “God created a spiritual dimension… [through which God] interacts with the Universe... It is this dimension which makes it possible for us to speak of God’s multifaceted relationship to the universe without violating the basic principle of His unity and simplicity” (Aryeh Kaplan, Innerspace). The Kabbalistic approach is explained in various Chassidic writings; see for example, Shaar Hayichud, below, for a detailed discussion.

In Christian thought Edit

In Western Christian classical theism, God is simple, not composite, not made up of thing upon thing. Thomas Morris notes that divine simplicity can mean any or all of three different claims:

  1. God has no spatial parts (spatial simplicity).
  2. God has no temporal parts (temporal simplicity).
  3. God is without the sort of metaphysical complexity where God would have different parts which are distinct from himself (property simplicity).

In other words, property simplicity (or metaphysical/absolute simplicity) states that the characteristics of God are not parts of God that together make up God. God is simple; God is those characteristics. For example, God does not have goodness but simply is goodness; God does not have existence but is existence – God is God's existence and God's essence is God's existence, in the words of Aquinas.[11] In other words, God is his goodness which is his nature which is his essence which is his existence.[12] As Vallicella says, "To say that God lacks metaphysical parts is to say inter alia that God is free of matter-form composition, potency-act composition, and existence-essence composition. There is also no real distinction between God as subject of his attributes and his attributes."[13] This entails that God exhausts what it means to be God (thus, in principle, there can't be more than one God).[11] It's important to clarify that the doctrine of divine simplicity is fundamentally about God's attributes – his nature or essential essence: the doctrine by itself doesn't state that God can't (for example) have the non-real/accidental (so-called) "property" of creating a universe.[11][12]

John Duns Scotus has a different – and more moderate – view of metaphysical/property simplicity than Aquinas.[14][15] Duns Scotus thinks that there's a formal distinction between God's attributes.[14][15] This formal distinction is not merely conceptual/semantical, nor is it a real/metaphysical distinction either.[14][15] The formal distinction is a logical distinction; thus, for example, omnipotence is not logically equivalent to omniscience.[14][15] So, Scotus still affirms that God's nature is not composed of metaphysical properties or parts.[14][15][16]

As Yann Schmitt says,[17]

As I already said, for a better understanding of the compatibility between divine simplicity and the distinction of attributes in God, I propose to use the notion of formal distinction developed by Duns Scotus.

FD X is formally distinct from Y if and only if (1) X and Y are inseparable even for an omnipotent being, (2) X and Y have not the same definition, (3) the

distinction exists de re.[17]

Here, the notion of de re is to be contrasted with de dicto. De dicto concerns a proposition or about what is said, whereas de re concerns the thing itself or being.[18] Thus, there is a formal distinction, for instance, between the attribute of omnipotence and the attribute of omniscience because (1) omnipotence and omniscience are inseparable for an omnipotent being (i.e. God), (2) omnipotence and omniscience do not have the same definition, and (3) the distinction between omnipotence and omniscience themselves exists de re (i.e. not merely conceptually or propositionally – de dicto).[18] Again, as a reminder, a formal distinction is a logical distinction.[16] The upshot, for Scotus, is that omnipotence and omniscience are logically distinct for God; however, God does not have the metaphysical properties or attributes of omnipotence or omniscience;[16] rather, metaphysically speaking, God is omnipotence, and God is omniscient.[16]

Spatial simplicity is endorsed by the vast majority of traditional Christian theists (who do not consider God to be a physical object). Temporal simplicity is endorsed by many theists but is highly controversial among Christian theologians. Morris describes Property simplicity as the property of having no properties, and this area is more controversial still.[19]

In the medieval era, theologians and philosophers held to a view called "constituent ontology" whereby natures were actual constituents of things. Following Aquinas, an individual nature was more like a concrete object than an abstract object. Thus, one person's humanity was not, in this sense, the same as another person's humanity; each had his own individual human nature which was individuated by the matter (materia signata) out of which each man was composed. For entities which are immaterial such as angels, there is no matter to individuate their natures, so each one just is its nature. Each angel is therefore literally one of a kind, although, this claim proved controversial.[20]

Theologians holding the doctrine of property simplicity tend to distinguish various modes of the simple being of God by negating any notion of composition from the meaning of terms used to describe it. Thus, in quantitative or spatial terms, God is simple as opposed to being made up of pieces, present in entirety everywhere, if in fact present anywhere. In terms of essences, God is simple as opposed to being made up of form and matter, or body and soul, or mind and act, and so on. If distinctions are made when speaking of God's attributes, they are distinctions of the "modes" of God's being, rather than real or essential divisions. And so, in terms of subjects and accidents, as in the phrase "goodness of God", divine simplicity allows that there is a conceptual distinction between the person of God and the personal attribute of goodness, but the doctrine disallows that God's identity or "character" is dependent upon goodness, and at the same time the doctrine dictates that it is impossible to consider the goodness in which God participates separately from the goodness which God is.[21]

Furthermore, according to Aquinas, as creatures our concepts are all drawn from the creation (the assumption of empiricism); it follows from this and divine simplicity that God's attributes can only be spoken of by analogy, since it is not true of any created thing that its properties are identical to its being.[22] Consequently, when Christian Scripture is interpreted according to the guide of divine simplicity, when it says that God is good for example, it should be taken to speak of a likeness to goodness as found in humanity and referred to in human speech. God's essence is inexpressible; this likeness is nevertheless truly comparable to God who simply is goodness, because humanity is a complex being composed by God "in the image and likeness of God."

Divine Simplicity has been dogmatized in the Catholic Church in councils like the Fourth Lateran Council and First Vatican Council, and is accepted – in some form – by most Christians (even if it's not Thomas Aquinas' view of divine simplicity).[23]

Criticism Edit

The doctrine of absolute divine simplicity (i.e. Thomistic divine simplicity) has been criticized by many Christian theologians, including John S. Feinberg, Thomas Morris, William Lane Craig, and Alvin Plantinga, who in his essay Does God Have a Nature? calls it "a dark saying indeed."[24] Plantinga gives three arguments against Thomistic divine simplicity. First, he argues our concepts can apply univocally to God, even if our language to describe God is limited, fragmentary, halting, and inchoate.[25] He argues that when we have a concept of something like being a horse, we know what it is for something to be a horse. The concept applies to an object if that object is, in fact, a horse. If none of our concepts apply to God, then it is sheer confusion to say there is such a person as God, and yet God does not have properties such as wisdom, being the creator, and being almighty. In fact, God would not have any properties for which we have concepts. God would not even have properties such as existing, being self-identical, or even being the referent of the term 'God.' If God transcends human experience, then we cannot say something univocal about God, since such a claim presupposes that we know what it means to transcend human experience, and that it applies to God. One reply to this objection is to draw a distinction between equivocal language and analogical language; the former doesn't include a univocal element at all, but the latter does include an element of univocal language.[26]

The claim that God can only be described analogically is, as Plantinga describes, a double-edged sword. If we cannot use univocal language to describe God and argue against simplicity, we are equally handicapped when it comes to the arguments for Thomistic divine simplicity. If we cannot rely on our usual modes of inference in reasoning about God, we cannot argue for the conclusion that God is not distinct from his properties. Plantinga concludes "This way of thinking begins in a pious and commendable concern for God's greatness and majesty and augustness, but it ends in agnosticism and in incoherence."[27] Edward Feser has responded to Plantinga.[28] Feser says that Plantinga is attacking a strawman when Plantinga says that proponents of analogical (religious) language are committed to the view that the language of God is metaphorical and not literal: metaphorical language is not the same thing as analogical language, so Plantinga is conflating analogy with metaphor, Feser argues.[28]

Plantinga also gives three criticisms of the doctrine of metaphysical simplicity directly, stating that it is exceedingly hard to grasp or construe the doctrine, and it is difficult to see why anyone would be inclined to accept it. First, the Thomist doctrine of simplicity states that all abstract objects are identical with God's essence and hence God himself. Plantinga states that this seems to clash with the obvious fact that the property of being a horse is distinct from the property of being a turkey and both are distinct from God and his essence.[29] One response to this objection is to note a distinction between properties and predicates.[30] A second response will note that supporters of divine simplicity don't think of God's nature as exemplifying abstract objects that are independent of God.[31]

Secondly, Plantinga argues, if one restricts the realm of abstract objects that are identical with God to only the properties that God exemplifies, the doctrine is still problematic. Metaphysical simplicity states that God has no accidental (i.e. contingent) properties. Yet, it clearly does seem that God has accidental properties such as having created Adam, and knowing that Adam sinned. Some of God's characteristics characterize him in every possible world and some do not.[32] Plantinga also argues that the conflation of God's actuality with his potentiality inherits all the problems of the essence-accident complexity and is furthermore vexed in its own right. Just as it seems there are characteristics that God has but could have lacked, it also seems the case that there are characteristics that God lacks but could have had. No doubt God has not created all the persons he will create. If so, there is at least one individual essence such that God does not now have, but will have the characteristic of causing that essence to be instantiated. If so, God has potentiality with respect to that characteristic.[33] Feser notes that someone who holds to divine simplicity does not have to hold to this view of divine simplicity. Instead, one can think that God has "Cambridge" properties, which are properties in a loose sense (e.g. "property" of being a husband; "property" of creating a universe).[28]

Plantinga's third critique challenges the very heart of simplicity. Metaphysical simplicity claims that there is no divine composition, meaning that there is no complexity of properties in God and that he is identical with his nature and each of his properties. There are two difficulties with this view. First, if God is identical with each of his properties, then each of his properties is identical with each of his other properties, so God has only one property. This flies in the face of the idea that God has both power and mercifulness, neither of which is identical with the other. Secondly, if God is identical with his properties, then, since each of God's properties is a property, it follows that God is a property as well. In this case, God has just one property: himself. The problem is that properties do not in and of themselves cause anything. No property could have created the world, and no property could know anything at all. If God is a property, then he isn't a person but a mere abstract object, having no power, life, love, or even awareness.[34] Feser notes that this objection assumes a Platonist metaphysics about abstract objects. Supporters of divine simplicity don't think of God as a Platonic-abstract property, nor as impersonal (but, instead, God is Personal, God is Personhood, and God is Intelligent).[2] Secondly, God doesn't merely 'have' concrete properties on divine simplicity; rather, for God, God just is God's essential "properties" (i.e. attributes of God). Thirdly, again, there is a distinction between properties and predicates, so there is no problem (for humans) in distinguishing between things like power and mercy in our ordinary experience, even though--for divine simplicity--there is a sense in which power and mercy are the same thing in God.[28][35] Vallicella also responds to Plantinga by arguing that all of Plantinga's objections assume a non-constituent ontology, but that is just what a supporter of divine simplicity would deny; thus, Plantinga's arguments are unconvincing.[13]

Alfred J. Freddoso showed in his 1983 review of Does God Have a Nature? that Plantinga's critique is lacking the required depth of analysis to propose jettisoning the theological basis of the doctrine of divine simplicity laid in Christian thought by Augustine, Anselm, Bonaventure, Aquinas, Scotus, and Ockham, among others.[36]

Craig calls the Thomistic view of property simplicity "philosophically and theologically unacceptable." He also states that divine simplicity is open to powerful objections. On the doctrine of divine simplicity, God is absolutely similar in all possible worlds. Since the statement "God knows x" is equivalent to "x is true," it becomes inexplicable why those worlds vary if in every one God knows, loves, and wills the same things.[20] Feser has responded to Craig's objections to divine simplicity.[37][38][39] Morris states that it is an idea whose implications are difficult to defend and whose advantages can be had in other ways. It is also an idea whose motivation, under close scrutiny, is not so convincing.[40] John S. Feinberg concludes: "These philosophical problems plus the biblical considerations raised earlier lead me to conclude that simplicity is not one of the divine attributes. This doesn't mean that God has physical parts, but that the implications of the doctrine of metaphysical simplicity are too problematic to maintain the doctrine."[41] Jordan Barrett has responded to the claim that divine simplicity isn't biblical.[42]

Brower and Bergmann give a truthmaker defense of divine simplicity.[21] For example, when we say that, "God is omnibenevolent", we mean that "God is his omnibenevolence"; this means that (contra Plantinga) God is not identical to a property of omnibenevolence, instead, God is identical to God's goodness which means that God is identical to himself.[43][21] As Vallicella says, "Accordingly, to say that God is identical to his omniscience is just to say that God is identical to the truthmaker of ‘God is omniscient.’ And that amounts to saying that God is identical to God. In this way one avoids the absurdity of saying that God is identical to a property. What God is identical to is not the property of omniscience but the referent of ‘God’s omniscience,’ which turns out to be God himself. And similarly for the rest of God’s intrinsic and essential attributes."[44] Finally, there could be truthmaker theory/defense that is a more moderate version of divine simplicity that sits between absolute divine simplicity (e.g. God is not composed of metaphysical parts/complexity) and minimal divine simplicity (i.e. God not composed of spatial/temporal/material parts).[45] For this view, God wouldn't be composed but would still be complex. Moderate divine simplicity affirms that God is not composed of metaphysical parts, but says that God is still metaphysically complex. This moderate view can be combined with a version of truthmaker theory. As Yann says, "The minimal truthmaker requirement can then be assumed without any contradiction with divine simplicity. <God is good> is true in virtue of a perfection of God, that is God’s goodness. <God is omniscient> is true in virtue of another perfection of God, God’s omniscience. We do not have to say that God is identical with His goodness or His omniscience."[46]

The Bible Edit

Writers such as Herman Bavinck and Louis Berkhof among others have argued that the doctrine of Divine Simplicity is affirmed by the Epistle of John, as the writer seems to identify God with love (1 John 4:8) and with light (1 John 1:5). Advocates of the doctrine have also argued that it is affirmed by Old Testament passages such as Exodus 3:14, argued to identify God as "being", Deuteronomy 6:4, which has been seen as affirming the oneness of God and Jeremiah 23:6, argued to identify God with righteousness. Though critics of the doctrine have argued that it is unlikely that the biblical writers had metaphysics in mind in the verses used, arguing that the lack of explicit verses on the doctrine imply against it.[47]

Other theologians such as Charles Ryrie have argued that divine simplicity underscores the scriptural view of God's self-existence.[48]

In Islamic thought Edit

Rigorous views of divine simplicity were championed by the Mu'tazili, which resulted in a radically apophatic theology. By postulating a distinction between Existence and Essence for all created beings, which was perceived to be uniquely absent in God, Al-Farabi established another model of divine simplicity. Ibn Sinā supported and elaborated this position, Al-Ghazali contested this identification of Divine essence and existence, but still saw all Divine attributes and acts as enveloped in and indistinct from the Divine Essence, this latter view of divine simplicity was shared with some of the most trenchant critics of the Muslim philosophical writers, like Ibn Taymiyyah.[49]

See also Edit

References Edit

  1. ^ "Summa Theologiae: The simplicity of God (Prima Pars, Q. 3)". newadvent.com. Retrieved 2019-10-09.
  2. ^ a b c "Divine Simplicity | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  3. ^ "Divine Simplicity". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2019.
  4. ^ Bussanich John, Plotinus's metaphysics of the One in The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus, ed. Lloyd P.Gerson, p. 42, 1996, Cambridge University Press, UK. For instances, see Plotinus, Second Ennead, Fourth Tractate, Section 8 (Stephen MacKenna's translation, Sacred Texts)
  5. ^ "The Enneads of Plotinus: The Fifth Ennead: Fourth Tractate: Section 1". www.sacred-texts.com.
  6. ^ "The Enneads of Plotinus: The Second Ennead: Ninth Tractate: Section 1". www.sacred-texts.com.
  7. ^ a b c "Divine Simplicity | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy". Retrieved 2022-05-28.
  8. ^ Simons, Jonatán (2023-09-28). Divine Simplicity in the Theology of Irenaeus. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-67763-0.
  9. ^ "Moses Maimonides, Guide for the Perplexed, Part 1, chapter 50". Friedländer tr. [1904], at sacred-texts.com. Retrieved 2013-10-29.
  10. ^ Seeskin, Kenneth (2006-01-24). "Maimonedes". Retrieved 22 April 2014. {{cite journal}}: Cite journal requires |journal= (help)
  11. ^ a b c "Divine Simplicity | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  12. ^ a b "Divine Simplicity". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2019.
  13. ^ a b "Divine Simplicity". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2019.
  14. ^ a b c d e "Scotus, John Duns | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  15. ^ a b c d e "John Duns Scotus". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2019.
  16. ^ a b c d "Scotus, John Duns | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  17. ^ a b Schmitt, Y. (2013). The deadlock of absolute divine simplicity.^ International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion, 74, 117–130
  18. ^ a b "De re/De dicto – Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  19. ^ Morris, Thomas V. (1997). Our idea of God : an introduction to philosophical theology. Vancouver, B.C.: Regent College Pub. p. 114. ISBN 978-1573831017.
  20. ^ a b Craig, William Lane. "Divine Simplicity". Retrieved 22 April 2014.
  21. ^ a b c "Divine Simplicity". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2019.
  22. ^ White, Thomas Joseph (2022). "Divine Simplicity". St Andrews Encyclopaedia of Theology.
  23. ^ "Divine Simplicity | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  24. ^ Plantinga, Alvin. "Does God Have a Nature?" in Plantinga, Alvin, and James F. Sennett. 1998. The analytic theist: an Alvin Plantinga reader. Grand Rapids, Mich: W.B. Eerdmans Pub. Co., 228. ISBN 978-0802842299
  25. ^ Plantinga, Alvin (2000). Does God have a nature? (Reprinted ed.). Milwaukee: Marquette Univ. Press. p. 18. ISBN 978-0874621457.
  26. ^ "Divine Simplicity | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  27. ^ Plantinga, Alvin (2000). Does God have a nature? (Reprinted ed.). Milwaukee: Marquette Univ. Press. p. 26. ISBN 978-0874621457.
  28. ^ a b c d Edward Feser. Five Proofs of the Existence of God. San Francisco, California:Ignatius Press, 2017
  29. ^ Plantinga, Alvin (2000). Does God have a nature? (Reprinted ed.). Milwaukee: Marquette Univ. Press. p. 37. ISBN 978-0874621457.
  30. ^ "Divine Simplicity | Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy".
  31. ^ Edward Feser. Five Proofs of the Existence of God. San Francisco, California:Ignatius Press, 2017
  32. ^ Plantinga, Alvin (2000). Does God have a nature? (Reprinted ed.). Milwaukee: Marquette Univ. Press. p. 43. ISBN 978-0874621457.
  33. ^ Plantinga, Alvin (2000). Does God have a nature? (Reprinted ed.). Milwaukee: Marquette Univ. Press. p. 46. ISBN 978-0874621457.
  34. ^ Plantinga, Alvin (2000). Does God have a nature? (Reprinted ed.). Milwaukee: Marquette Univ. Press. p. 47. ISBN 978-0874621457.
  35. ^ "Divine Simplicity". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. 2019.
  36. ^ Freddoso A (1983). "Review of Does God Have a Nature?". Christian Scholar's Review. University of Notre Dame. 12 (2): 78–83.
  37. ^ "Keep It Simple | Edward Feser".
  38. ^ "Edward Feser: William Lane Craig on divine simplicity". November 2009.
  39. ^ "Edward Feser: Craig on divine simplicity and theistic personalism". 15 April 2016.
  40. ^ Morris, Thomas V. (1997). Our idea of God : an introduction to philosophical theology. Vancouver, B.C.: Regent College Pub. p. 115. ISBN 978-1573831017.
  41. ^ John S. Feinberg (2006). No One Like Him: the doctrine of God (Revised ed.). Wheaton. Ill.: Crossway Books. p. 335. ISBN 978-1581348118.
  42. ^ Barrett, J. P. (2017). Divine Simplicity: A Biblical and Trinitarian Account. United Kingdom: Fortress Press.
  43. ^ Bergmann, Michael, and Jeffrey Brower. “A Theistic Argument against Platonism (and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity)” In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 2, edited by Dean Zimmerman, 357–386. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2006.
  44. ^ Vallicella, William F., "Divine Simplicity", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2019/entries/divine-simplicity/>
  45. ^ Yann (2013). The deadlock of absolute divine simplicity. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 74 (1):117–130.
  46. ^ Schmitt, Yann (2013). The deadlock of absolute divine simplicity. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 74 (1):117–130.
  47. ^ Dolezal, James E. (2011-11-09). God Without Parts. Wipf & Stock Publishers. ISBN 978-1-4982-6155-5.
  48. ^ Ryrie, Charles C. (1999-01-11). Basic Theology: A Popular Systematic Guide to Understanding Biblical Truth. Moody Publishers. ISBN 978-1-57567-498-8.
  49. ^ Arberry, A.J. (2007). Revelation and Reason in Islam. New York: Routledge. pp. 104–108. ISBN 978-0415438872.

Bibliography Edit

  • Burell, David. Aquinas: God and Action. London; Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1979.
  • Burell, David. Knowing the Unknowable God: Ibn-Sina, Maimonides, Aquinas. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press, 1986.
  • Brower, Jeffrey. "Making Sense of Divine Simplicity", Faith and Philosophy 25 (1) (2008): 3–30.
  • Dolezal, James. God without Parts: Divine Simplicity and the Metaphysics of God's Absoluteness. Eugene: Pickwick Publications, 2011.
  • Dolezal, James. "Trinity, Simplicity and the Status of God's Personal Relations", International Journal of Systematic Theology 16 (1) (2014): 79–98.
  • Leftow, Brian. "Is God an Abstract Object?". Nous. 1990.
  • Maimonides, Moses. The Guide of the Perplexed, trans. M Friedländer. New York: Dover, 1956.
  • Plantinga, Alvin. Does God Have a Nature?. Milwaukee: Marquette University Press, 1980.
  • Plato. Parmenides. Many editions.
  • Plotinus. Enneads V, 4, 1; VI, 8, 17; VI, 9, 9–10. Many editions.
  • Pseudo-Dionysius. The Divine Names in Pseudo-Dionysius: The Complete Works, trans. Colm Luibheid. New York: Paulist Press, 1987.
  • Radde-Gallwitz, Andrew. Basil of Caesarea, Gregory of Nyssa, and the Transformation of Divine Simplicity. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009.
  • Stump, Eleonore and Kretzmann, Norman. “Absolute Simplicity”. Faith and Philosophy. 1985.
  • Thomas Aquinas. On Being and Essence (De Esse et Essentia), 2nd ed., trans. Armand Maurer, CSB. Toronto: Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1968.
  • Thomas Aquinas. Summa Theologica I, Q. 3, A. 3 "On the Simplicity of God". Many editions.
  • Weigel, Peter. Aquinas on Simplicity: An Investigation into the Foundations of His Philosophical Theology. Bern: Peter Lang, 2008.
  • Wolterstorff, Nicholas. "Divine Simplicity", In Philosophical Perspectives 5: Philosophy of Religion. Atascadero, Calif.: Ridgeview Publishing, 1991, 531–552.

External links Edit

  • Divine Simplicity Reasonable Faith
  • Divine Simplicity, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • Divine Simplicity, Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • God and Other Necessary Beings, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
  • , Dovber Schneuri - A detailed explanation of the paradox of divine simplicity.

divine, simplicity, confused, with, monotheism, this, article, require, copy, editing, grammar, style, cohesion, tone, spelling, assist, editing, april, 2023, learn, when, remove, this, template, message, monotheistic, theology, doctrine, divine, simplicity, s. Not to be confused with monotheism This article may require copy editing for grammar style cohesion tone or spelling You can assist by editing it April 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message In monotheistic theology the doctrine of Divine Simplicity says that God is simple without parts This is the idea that God does not exist in parts but is one unified entity with no distinct attributes that is God s existence is identical to God s essence Contents 1 Overview 2 History 3 In Jewish thought 4 In Christian thought 4 1 Criticism 4 2 The Bible 5 In Islamic thought 6 See also 7 References 8 Bibliography 9 External linksOverview EditThe general idea can be stated in this way The being of God is identical to the attributes of God Characteristics such as omnipresence goodness truth eternity etc are identical to God s being not qualities that make up that being as a collection nor abstract entities inhering in God as in a substance in other words one can say that in God both essence and existence are one and the same 1 This is not to say that God is a simpleton or simple to understand As Peter Weigel states Divine simplicity is central to the classical Western concept of God Simplicity denies any physical or metaphysical composition in the divine being This means God is the divine nature itself and has no accidents properties that are not necessary accruing to his nature There are no real divisions or distinctions of this nature Thus the entirety of God is whatever is attributed to him Divine simplicity is the hallmark of God s utter transcendence of all else ensuring the divine nature to be beyond the reach of ordinary categories and distinctions or at least their ordinary application Simplicity in this way confers a unique ontological status that many philosophers find highly peculiar 2 So when it comes to God s essential nature or attributes there are no parts or accidents this is not to be confused with for example God s accidental or contingent relation to the world i e God s non essential or contingent properties not God s nature 2 3 Varieties of the doctrine may be found among Jewish Christian and Muslim philosophical theologians especially during the height of Scholasticism although the doctrine s origins may be traced back to ancient Greek thought finding apotheosis in Plotinus Enneads as the Simplex 4 5 6 History EditViews close to Divine Simplicity were held by philosophers such as Plato Thales and Anaximenes Classical statements concerning divine simplicity can be found in Augustine Anselm and Thomas Aquinas When Christianity had just began Philo of Alexandria mentioned how the belief of God as utterly simple was widely held 7 One of the earliest mentions of divine simplicity in Christian theology comes from Irenaeus 130 c 202 AD 8 Early Christian theology viewed simplicity as necessary for preserving God s transcendence Athenagoras of Athens in the second century argued that God is utterly indivisible and unchangeable 7 Clement of Alexandria Basil and Cyril saw simplicity as preserving the transcendence and the perfection of God 7 In Jewish thought EditSee also Jewish principles of faith Nature of God Tzimtzum Apophatic theology Judaism Free will in Theology In Jewish thought and Kuzari Question of attributes In Jewish philosophy and in Kabbalah divine simplicity is addressed via discussion of the attributes תארים of God particularly by Jewish philosophers within the Muslim sphere of influence such as Saadia Gaon Bahya ibn Paquda Yehuda Halevi and Maimonides as well by Raabad III in Provence A classic expression of this position is found in Maimonides work Guide to the Perplexed 9 If however you have a desire to rise to a higher state viz that of reflection and truly to hold the conviction that God is One and possesses true unity without admitting plurality or divisibility in any sense whatever you must understand that God has no essential attribute in any form or in any sense whatever and that the rejection of corporeality implies the rejection of essential attributes Those who believe that God is One and that He has many attributes declare the unity with their lips and assume plurality in their thoughts According to Maimonides then there can be no plurality of faculties moral dispositions or essential attributes in God Even to say that God is all knowing all powerful and all good is to introduce plurality if one means thereby that these qualities are separate attributes Maimonides therefore concludes that it is not true to say that God s power is greater than ours that God s life is more permanent than ours or that God s knowledge is broader than ours Maimonedes believed that statements such as God lives or God is powerful are nonsense if they are interpreted in the normal fashion but they can be understood if one analyzes them as disguised negations Still Maimonedes also believed that negation is objectionable to the degree that it introduces complexity God is neither this nor that and ultimately any kind of verbal expression fails us Citing Psalm 65 Maimonides concludes that the highest form of praise we can give God is silence 10 Some who identify divine simplicity as a corollary of Divine Creation In the beginning God created the heaven and the earth Genesis 1 1 God as creator is by definition separate from the universe and thus free of any property and hence an absolute unity see Negative theology For others conversely the axiom of Divine Unity see Shema Yisrael informs the understanding of divine simplicity Bahya ibn Paquda Duties of the Heart 1 8 points out that God s Oneness is true oneness האחד האמת as opposed to merely circumstantial oneness האחד המקרי He develops this idea to show that an entity which is truly one must be free of properties and thus indescribable and unlike anything else Additionally such an entity would be absolutely unsubject to change as well as utterly independent and the root of everything Torah org The Judaism SiteThe implication of either approach is so strong that the two concepts are often presented as synonymous God is not two or more entities but a single entity of a oneness even more single and unique than any single thing in creation He cannot be sub divided into different parts therefore it is impossible for Him to be anything other than one It is a positive commandment to know this for it is written Deuteronomy 6 4 the Lord is our God the Lord is one Maimonides Mishneh Torah Mada 1 7 Despite its apparent simplicity this concept is recognised as raising many difficulties In particular insofar as God s simplicity does not allow for any structure even conceptually divine simplicity appears to entail the following dichotomy On the one hand God is absolutely simple containing no element of form or structure as above On the other hand it is understood that God s essence contains every possible element of perfection The First Foundation is to believe in the existence of the Creator blessed be He This means that there exists a Being that is perfect complete in all ways and He is the cause of all else that exists Maimonides 13 principles of faith First Principle The resultant paradox is famously articulated by Moshe Chaim Luzzatto Derekh Hashem I 1 5 describing the dichotomy as arising out of our inability to comprehend the idea of absolute unity God s existence is absolutely simple without combinations or additions of any kind All perfections are found in Him in a perfectly simple manner However God does not entail separate domains even though in truth there exist in God qualities which within us are separate Indeed the true nature of His essence is that it is a single attribute yet one that intrinsically encompasses everything that could be considered perfection All perfection therefore exists in God not as something added on to His existence but as an integral part of His intrinsic identity This is a concept that is very far from our ability to grasp and imagine The Kabbalists address this paradox by explaining that God created a spiritual dimension through which God interacts with the Universe It is this dimension which makes it possible for us to speak of God s multifaceted relationship to the universe without violating the basic principle of His unity and simplicity Aryeh Kaplan Innerspace The Kabbalistic approach is explained in various Chassidic writings see for example Shaar Hayichud below for a detailed discussion In Christian thought EditSee also Classical theism Trinity and Nontrinitarianism In Western Christian classical theism God is simple not composite not made up of thing upon thing Thomas Morris notes that divine simplicity can mean any or all of three different claims God has no spatial parts spatial simplicity God has no temporal parts temporal simplicity God is without the sort of metaphysical complexity where God would have different parts which are distinct from himself property simplicity In other words property simplicity or metaphysical absolute simplicity states that the characteristics of God are not parts of God that together make up God God is simple God is those characteristics For example God does not have goodness but simply is goodness God does not have existence but is existence God is God s existence and God s essence is God s existence in the words of Aquinas 11 In other words God is his goodness which is his nature which is his essence which is his existence 12 As Vallicella says To say that God lacks metaphysical parts is to say inter alia that God is free of matter form composition potency act composition and existence essence composition There is also no real distinction between God as subject of his attributes and his attributes 13 This entails that God exhausts what it means to be God thus in principle there can t be more than one God 11 It s important to clarify that the doctrine of divine simplicity is fundamentally about God s attributes his nature or essential essence the doctrine by itself doesn t state that God can t for example have the non real accidental so called property of creating a universe 11 12 John Duns Scotus has a different and more moderate view of metaphysical property simplicity than Aquinas 14 15 Duns Scotus thinks that there s a formal distinction between God s attributes 14 15 This formal distinction is not merely conceptual semantical nor is it a real metaphysical distinction either 14 15 The formal distinction is a logical distinction thus for example omnipotence is not logically equivalent to omniscience 14 15 So Scotus still affirms that God s nature is not composed of metaphysical properties or parts 14 15 16 As Yann Schmitt says 17 As I already said for a better understanding of the compatibility between divine simplicity and the distinction of attributes in God I propose to use the notion of formal distinction developed by Duns Scotus FD X is formally distinct from Y if and only if 1 X and Y are inseparable even for an omnipotent being 2 X and Y have not the same definition 3 thedistinction exists de re 17 Here the notion of de re is to be contrasted with de dicto De dicto concerns a proposition or about what is said whereas de re concerns the thing itself or being 18 Thus there is a formal distinction for instance between the attribute of omnipotence and the attribute of omniscience because 1 omnipotence and omniscience are inseparable for an omnipotent being i e God 2 omnipotence and omniscience do not have the same definition and 3 the distinction between omnipotence and omniscience themselves exists de re i e not merely conceptually or propositionally de dicto 18 Again as a reminder a formal distinction is a logical distinction 16 The upshot for Scotus is that omnipotence and omniscience are logically distinct for God however God does not have the metaphysical properties or attributes of omnipotence or omniscience 16 rather metaphysically speaking God is omnipotence and God is omniscient 16 Spatial simplicity is endorsed by the vast majority of traditional Christian theists who do not consider God to be a physical object Temporal simplicity is endorsed by many theists but is highly controversial among Christian theologians Morris describes Property simplicity as the property of having no properties and this area is more controversial still 19 In the medieval era theologians and philosophers held to a view called constituent ontology whereby natures were actual constituents of things Following Aquinas an individual nature was more like a concrete object than an abstract object Thus one person s humanity was not in this sense the same as another person s humanity each had his own individual human nature which was individuated by the matter materia signata out of which each man was composed For entities which are immaterial such as angels there is no matter to individuate their natures so each one just is its nature Each angel is therefore literally one of a kind although this claim proved controversial 20 Theologians holding the doctrine of property simplicity tend to distinguish various modes of the simple being of God by negating any notion of composition from the meaning of terms used to describe it Thus in quantitative or spatial terms God is simple as opposed to being made up of pieces present in entirety everywhere if in fact present anywhere In terms of essences God is simple as opposed to being made up of form and matter or body and soul or mind and act and so on If distinctions are made when speaking of God s attributes they are distinctions of the modes of God s being rather than real or essential divisions And so in terms of subjects and accidents as in the phrase goodness of God divine simplicity allows that there is a conceptual distinction between the person of God and the personal attribute of goodness but the doctrine disallows that God s identity or character is dependent upon goodness and at the same time the doctrine dictates that it is impossible to consider the goodness in which God participates separately from the goodness which God is 21 Furthermore according to Aquinas as creatures our concepts are all drawn from the creation the assumption of empiricism it follows from this and divine simplicity that God s attributes can only be spoken of by analogy since it is not true of any created thing that its properties are identical to its being 22 Consequently when Christian Scripture is interpreted according to the guide of divine simplicity when it says that God is good for example it should be taken to speak of a likeness to goodness as found in humanity and referred to in human speech God s essence is inexpressible this likeness is nevertheless truly comparable to God who simply is goodness because humanity is a complex being composed by God in the image and likeness of God Divine Simplicity has been dogmatized in the Catholic Church in councils like the Fourth Lateran Council and First Vatican Council and is accepted in some form by most Christians even if it s not Thomas Aquinas view of divine simplicity 23 Criticism Edit The doctrine of absolute divine simplicity i e Thomistic divine simplicity has been criticized by many Christian theologians including John S Feinberg Thomas Morris William Lane Craig and Alvin Plantinga who in his essay Does God Have a Nature calls it a dark saying indeed 24 Plantinga gives three arguments against Thomistic divine simplicity First he argues our concepts can apply univocally to God even if our language to describe God is limited fragmentary halting and inchoate 25 He argues that when we have a concept of something like being a horse we know what it is for something to be a horse The concept applies to an object if that object is in fact a horse If none of our concepts apply to God then it is sheer confusion to say there is such a person as God and yet God does not have properties such as wisdom being the creator and being almighty In fact God would not have any properties for which we have concepts God would not even have properties such as existing being self identical or even being the referent of the term God If God transcends human experience then we cannot say something univocal about God since such a claim presupposes that we know what it means to transcend human experience and that it applies to God One reply to this objection is to draw a distinction between equivocal language and analogical language the former doesn t include a univocal element at all but the latter does include an element of univocal language 26 The claim that God can only be described analogically is as Plantinga describes a double edged sword If we cannot use univocal language to describe God and argue against simplicity we are equally handicapped when it comes to the arguments for Thomistic divine simplicity If we cannot rely on our usual modes of inference in reasoning about God we cannot argue for the conclusion that God is not distinct from his properties Plantinga concludes This way of thinking begins in a pious and commendable concern for God s greatness and majesty and augustness but it ends in agnosticism and in incoherence 27 Edward Feser has responded to Plantinga 28 Feser says that Plantinga is attacking a strawman when Plantinga says that proponents of analogical religious language are committed to the view that the language of God is metaphorical and not literal metaphorical language is not the same thing as analogical language so Plantinga is conflating analogy with metaphor Feser argues 28 Plantinga also gives three criticisms of the doctrine of metaphysical simplicity directly stating that it is exceedingly hard to grasp or construe the doctrine and it is difficult to see why anyone would be inclined to accept it First the Thomist doctrine of simplicity states that all abstract objects are identical with God s essence and hence God himself Plantinga states that this seems to clash with the obvious fact that the property of being a horse is distinct from the property of being a turkey and both are distinct from God and his essence 29 One response to this objection is to note a distinction between properties and predicates 30 A second response will note that supporters of divine simplicity don t think of God s nature as exemplifying abstract objects that are independent of God 31 Secondly Plantinga argues if one restricts the realm of abstract objects that are identical with God to only the properties that God exemplifies the doctrine is still problematic Metaphysical simplicity states that God has no accidental i e contingent properties Yet it clearly does seem that God has accidental properties such as having created Adam and knowing that Adam sinned Some of God s characteristics characterize him in every possible world and some do not 32 Plantinga also argues that the conflation of God s actuality with his potentiality inherits all the problems of the essence accident complexity and is furthermore vexed in its own right Just as it seems there are characteristics that God has but could have lacked it also seems the case that there are characteristics that God lacks but could have had No doubt God has not created all the persons he will create If so there is at least one individual essence such that God does not now have but will have the characteristic of causing that essence to be instantiated If so God has potentiality with respect to that characteristic 33 Feser notes that someone who holds to divine simplicity does not have to hold to this view of divine simplicity Instead one can think that God has Cambridge properties which are properties in a loose sense e g property of being a husband property of creating a universe 28 Plantinga s third critique challenges the very heart of simplicity Metaphysical simplicity claims that there is no divine composition meaning that there is no complexity of properties in God and that he is identical with his nature and each of his properties There are two difficulties with this view First if God is identical with each of his properties then each of his properties is identical with each of his other properties so God has only one property This flies in the face of the idea that God has both power and mercifulness neither of which is identical with the other Secondly if God is identical with his properties then since each of God s properties is a property it follows that God is a property as well In this case God has just one property himself The problem is that properties do not in and of themselves cause anything No property could have created the world and no property could know anything at all If God is a property then he isn t a person but a mere abstract object having no power life love or even awareness 34 Feser notes that this objection assumes a Platonist metaphysics about abstract objects Supporters of divine simplicity don t think of God as a Platonic abstract property nor as impersonal but instead God is Personal God is Personhood and God is Intelligent 2 Secondly God doesn t merely have concrete properties on divine simplicity rather for God God just is God s essential properties i e attributes of God Thirdly again there is a distinction between properties and predicates so there is no problem for humans in distinguishing between things like power and mercy in our ordinary experience even though for divine simplicity there is a sense in which power and mercy are the same thing in God 28 35 Vallicella also responds to Plantinga by arguing that all of Plantinga s objections assume a non constituent ontology but that is just what a supporter of divine simplicity would deny thus Plantinga s arguments are unconvincing 13 Alfred J Freddoso showed in his 1983 review of Does God Have a Nature that Plantinga s critique is lacking the required depth of analysis to propose jettisoning the theological basis of the doctrine of divine simplicity laid in Christian thought by Augustine Anselm Bonaventure Aquinas Scotus and Ockham among others 36 Craig calls the Thomistic view of property simplicity philosophically and theologically unacceptable He also states that divine simplicity is open to powerful objections On the doctrine of divine simplicity God is absolutely similar in all possible worlds Since the statement God knows x is equivalent to x is true it becomes inexplicable why those worlds vary if in every one God knows loves and wills the same things 20 Feser has responded to Craig s objections to divine simplicity 37 38 39 Morris states that it is an idea whose implications are difficult to defend and whose advantages can be had in other ways It is also an idea whose motivation under close scrutiny is not so convincing 40 John S Feinberg concludes These philosophical problems plus the biblical considerations raised earlier lead me to conclude that simplicity is not one of the divine attributes This doesn t mean that God has physical parts but that the implications of the doctrine of metaphysical simplicity are too problematic to maintain the doctrine 41 Jordan Barrett has responded to the claim that divine simplicity isn t biblical 42 Brower and Bergmann give a truthmaker defense of divine simplicity 21 For example when we say that God is omnibenevolent we mean that God is his omnibenevolence this means that contra Plantinga God is not identical to a property of omnibenevolence instead God is identical to God s goodness which means that God is identical to himself 43 21 As Vallicella says Accordingly to say that God is identical to his omniscience is just to say that God is identical to the truthmaker of God is omniscient And that amounts to saying that God is identical to God In this way one avoids the absurdity of saying that God is identical to a property What God is identical to is not the property of omniscience but the referent of God s omniscience which turns out to be God himself And similarly for the rest of God s intrinsic and essential attributes 44 Finally there could be truthmaker theory defense that is a more moderate version of divine simplicity that sits between absolute divine simplicity e g God is not composed of metaphysical parts complexity and minimal divine simplicity i e God not composed of spatial temporal material parts 45 For this view God wouldn t be composed but would still be complex Moderate divine simplicity affirms that God is not composed of metaphysical parts but says that God is still metaphysically complex This moderate view can be combined with a version of truthmaker theory As Yann says The minimal truthmaker requirement can then be assumed without any contradiction with divine simplicity lt God is good gt is true in virtue of a perfection of God that is God s goodness lt God is omniscient gt is true in virtue of another perfection of God God s omniscience We do not have to say that God is identical with His goodness or His omniscience 46 The Bible Edit Writers such as Herman Bavinck and Louis Berkhof among others have argued that the doctrine of Divine Simplicity is affirmed by the Epistle of John as the writer seems to identify God with love 1 John 4 8 and with light 1 John 1 5 Advocates of the doctrine have also argued that it is affirmed by Old Testament passages such as Exodus 3 14 argued to identify God as being Deuteronomy 6 4 which has been seen as affirming the oneness of God and Jeremiah 23 6 argued to identify God with righteousness Though critics of the doctrine have argued that it is unlikely that the biblical writers had metaphysics in mind in the verses used arguing that the lack of explicit verses on the doctrine imply against it 47 Other theologians such as Charles Ryrie have argued that divine simplicity underscores the scriptural view of God s self existence 48 In Islamic thought EditRigorous views of divine simplicity were championed by the Mu tazili which resulted in a radically apophatic theology By postulating a distinction between Existence and Essence for all created beings which was perceived to be uniquely absent in God Al Farabi established another model of divine simplicity Ibn Sina supported and elaborated this position Al Ghazali contested this identification of Divine essence and existence but still saw all Divine attributes and acts as enveloped in and indistinct from the Divine Essence this latter view of divine simplicity was shared with some of the most trenchant critics of the Muslim philosophical writers like Ibn Taymiyyah 49 See also EditAseity Ein Sof A Jewish Kabalistic concept of divine unity Essence Energies Distinction Trinitarian doctrine of the Eastern Orthodox Church Euthyphro dilemma Pantheism conception of God Tawhid the Islamic concept of divine unity Unitarianism concept of divine unity opposite Trinitarianism Wahdat al Wujood Sufi conception of God which borders on Pantheistic and Panentheistic conceptions References Edit Summa Theologiae The simplicity of God Prima Pars Q 3 newadvent com Retrieved 2019 10 09 a b c Divine Simplicity Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Divine Simplicity The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2019 Bussanich John Plotinus s metaphysics of the One in The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus ed Lloyd P Gerson p 42 1996 Cambridge University Press UK For instances see Plotinus Second Ennead Fourth Tractate Section 8 Stephen MacKenna s translation Sacred Texts The Enneads of Plotinus The Fifth Ennead Fourth Tractate Section 1 www sacred texts com The Enneads of Plotinus The Second Ennead Ninth Tractate Section 1 www sacred texts com a b c Divine Simplicity Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 2022 05 28 Simons Jonatan 2023 09 28 Divine Simplicity in the Theology of Irenaeus Brill ISBN 978 90 04 67763 0 Moses Maimonides Guide for the Perplexed Part 1 chapter 50 Friedlander tr 1904 at sacred texts com Retrieved 2013 10 29 Seeskin Kenneth 2006 01 24 Maimonedes Retrieved 22 April 2014 a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a Cite journal requires journal help a b c Divine Simplicity Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy a b Divine Simplicity The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2019 a b Divine Simplicity The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2019 a b c d e Scotus John Duns Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy a b c d e John Duns Scotus The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2019 a b c d Scotus John Duns Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy a b Schmitt Y 2013 The deadlock of absolute divine simplicity International Journal for the Philosophy of Religion 74 117 130 a b De re De dicto Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy Morris Thomas V 1997 Our idea of God an introduction to philosophical theology Vancouver B C Regent College Pub p 114 ISBN 978 1573831017 a b Craig William Lane Divine Simplicity Retrieved 22 April 2014 a b c Divine Simplicity The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2019 White Thomas Joseph 2022 Divine Simplicity St Andrews Encyclopaedia of Theology Divine Simplicity Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Plantinga Alvin Does God Have a Nature in Plantinga Alvin and James F Sennett 1998 The analytic theist an Alvin Plantinga reader Grand Rapids Mich W B Eerdmans Pub Co 228 ISBN 978 0802842299 Plantinga Alvin 2000 Does God have a nature Reprinted ed Milwaukee Marquette Univ Press p 18 ISBN 978 0874621457 Divine Simplicity Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Plantinga Alvin 2000 Does God have a nature Reprinted ed Milwaukee Marquette Univ Press p 26 ISBN 978 0874621457 a b c d Edward Feser Five Proofs of the Existence of God San Francisco California Ignatius Press 2017 Plantinga Alvin 2000 Does God have a nature Reprinted ed Milwaukee Marquette Univ Press p 37 ISBN 978 0874621457 Divine Simplicity Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Edward Feser Five Proofs of the Existence of God San Francisco California Ignatius Press 2017 Plantinga Alvin 2000 Does God have a nature Reprinted ed Milwaukee Marquette Univ Press p 43 ISBN 978 0874621457 Plantinga Alvin 2000 Does God have a nature Reprinted ed Milwaukee Marquette Univ Press p 46 ISBN 978 0874621457 Plantinga Alvin 2000 Does God have a nature Reprinted ed Milwaukee Marquette Univ Press p 47 ISBN 978 0874621457 Divine Simplicity The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University 2019 Freddoso A 1983 Review of Does God Have a Nature Christian Scholar s Review University of Notre Dame 12 2 78 83 Keep It Simple Edward Feser Edward Feser William Lane Craig on divine simplicity November 2009 Edward Feser Craig on divine simplicity and theistic personalism 15 April 2016 Morris Thomas V 1997 Our idea of God an introduction to philosophical theology Vancouver B C Regent College Pub p 115 ISBN 978 1573831017 John S Feinberg 2006 No One Like Him the doctrine of God Revised ed Wheaton Ill Crossway Books p 335 ISBN 978 1581348118 Barrett J P 2017 Divine Simplicity A Biblical and Trinitarian Account United Kingdom Fortress Press Bergmann Michael and Jeffrey Brower A Theistic Argument against Platonism and in Support of Truthmakers and Divine Simplicity In Oxford Studies in Metaphysics 2 edited by Dean Zimmerman 357 386 Oxford Oxford University Press 2006 Vallicella William F Divine Simplicity The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2019 Edition Edward N Zalta ed URL lt https plato stanford edu archives spr2019 entries divine simplicity gt Yann 2013 The deadlock of absolute divine simplicity International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 74 1 117 130 Schmitt Yann 2013 The deadlock of absolute divine simplicity International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 74 1 117 130 Dolezal James E 2011 11 09 God Without Parts Wipf amp Stock Publishers ISBN 978 1 4982 6155 5 Ryrie Charles C 1999 01 11 Basic Theology A Popular Systematic Guide to Understanding Biblical Truth Moody Publishers ISBN 978 1 57567 498 8 Arberry A J 2007 Revelation and Reason in Islam New York Routledge pp 104 108 ISBN 978 0415438872 Bibliography EditBurell David Aquinas God and Action London Routledge amp Kegan Paul 1979 Burell David Knowing the Unknowable God Ibn Sina Maimonides Aquinas Notre Dame Notre Dame University Press 1986 Brower Jeffrey Making Sense of Divine Simplicity Faith and Philosophy 25 1 2008 3 30 Dolezal James God without Parts Divine Simplicity and the Metaphysics of God s Absoluteness Eugene Pickwick Publications 2011 Dolezal James Trinity Simplicity and the Status of God s Personal Relations International Journal of Systematic Theology 16 1 2014 79 98 Leftow Brian Is God an Abstract Object Nous 1990 Maimonides Moses The Guide of the Perplexed trans M Friedlander New York Dover 1956 Plantinga Alvin Does God Have a Nature Milwaukee Marquette University Press 1980 Plato Parmenides Many editions Plotinus Enneads V 4 1 VI 8 17 VI 9 9 10 Many editions Pseudo Dionysius The Divine Names in Pseudo Dionysius The Complete Works trans Colm Luibheid New York Paulist Press 1987 Radde Gallwitz Andrew Basil of Caesarea Gregory of Nyssa and the Transformation of Divine Simplicity Oxford Oxford University Press 2009 Stump Eleonore and Kretzmann Norman Absolute Simplicity Faith and Philosophy 1985 Thomas Aquinas On Being and Essence De Esse et Essentia 2nd ed trans Armand Maurer CSB Toronto Pontifical Institute of Medieval Studies 1968 Thomas Aquinas Summa Theologica I Q 3 A 3 On the Simplicity of God Many editions Weigel Peter Aquinas on Simplicity An Investigation into the Foundations of His Philosophical Theology Bern Peter Lang 2008 Wolterstorff Nicholas Divine Simplicity In Philosophical Perspectives 5 Philosophy of Religion Atascadero Calif Ridgeview Publishing 1991 531 552 External links EditDivine Simplicity Reasonable Faith Divine Simplicity Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Divine Simplicity Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy God and Other Necessary Beings Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Shaar HaYichud The Gate of Unity Dovber Schneuri A detailed explanation of the paradox of divine simplicity Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Divine simplicity amp oldid 1178946487, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.