fbpx
Wikipedia

Filter (mathematics)

In mathematics, a filter or order filter is a special subset of a partially ordered set (poset), describing "large" or "eventual" elements. Filters appear in order and lattice theory, but also topology, whence they originate. The notion dual to a filter is an order ideal.

The power set lattice of the set {1, 2, 3, 4}, with upper set ↑{1, 4} colored dark green. This upper set is a filter, and even a principal filter. It is not an ultrafilter, because including also the light green elements extends it to the larger nontrivial filter ↑{1}. Since the latter cannot be extended further, ↑{1} is an ultrafilter.

Special cases of filters include ultrafilters, which are filters that cannot be enlarged, and describe nonconstructive techniques in mathematical logic.

Filters on sets were introduced by Henri Cartan in 1937. Nicolas Bourbaki, in their book Topologie Générale, popularized filters as an alternative to E. H. Moore and Herman L. Smith's 1922 notion of a net; order filters generalize this notion from the specific case of a power set under inclusion to arbitrary partially ordered sets. Nevertheless, the theory of power-set filters retains interest in its own right, in part for substantial applications in topology.

Motivation edit

Fix a partially ordered set (poset) P. Intuitively, a filter F is a subset of P whose members are elements large enough to satisfy some criterion.[1] For instance, if xP, then the set of elements above x is a filter, called the principal filter at x. (If x and y are incomparable elements of P, then neither the principal filter at x nor y is contained in the other.)

Similarly, a filter on a set S contains those subsets that are sufficiently large to contain some given thing. For example, if S is the real line and xS, then the family of sets including x in their interior is a filter, called the neighborhood filter at x. The thing in this case is slightly larger than x, but it still does not contain any other specific point of the line.

The above considerations motivate the upward closure requirement in the definition below: "large enough" objects can always be made larger.

To understand the other two conditions, reverse the roles and instead consider F as a "locating scheme" to find x. In this interpretation, one searches in some space X, and expects F to describe those subsets of X that contain the goal. The goal must be located somewhere; thus the empty set  can never be in F. And if two subsets both contain the goal, then should "zoom in" to their common region.

An ultrafilter describes a "perfect locating scheme" where each scheme component gives new information (either "look here" or "look elsewhere"). Compactness is the property that "every search is fruitful," or, to put it another way, "every locating scheme ends in a search result."

A common use for a filter is to define properties that are satisfied by "generic" elements of some topological space.[2] This application generalizes the "locating scheme" to find points that might be hard to write down explicitly.

Definition edit

A subset F of a partially ordered set (P, ≤) is a filter or dual ideal if the following are satisfied:

Nontriviality
The set F is non-empty.
Downward directed
For every x, yF, there is some zF such that zx and zy.
Upward closure
For every xF and pP, the condition xp implies pF.

If, additionally, FP, then F is said to be a proper filter. Authors in set theory and mathematical logic often require all filters to be proper; this article will eschew that convention.[3] An ultrafilter is a filter contained in no other proper filter.

Filter bases edit

A subset S of F is a base or basis for F if the upper set generated by S (i.e., the smallest upwards-closed set containing S) is all of F. Every filter is a base for itself.

Moreover, if BP is nonempty and downward directed, then B generates an upper set F that is a filter (for which B is a base). Such sets are called prefilters, as well as the aforementioned filter base/basis, and F is said to be generated or spanned by B. A prefilter is proper if and only if it generates a proper filter.

Given pP, the set {x : px} is the smallest filter containing p, and sometimes written p. Such a filter is called a principal filter; p is said to be the principal element of F, or generate F.

Refinement edit

Suppose B and C are two prefilters on P, and, for each cC, there is a bB, such that bc. Then we say that B is finer than (or refines) C; likewise, C is coarser than (or coarsens) B. Refinement is a preorder on the set of prefilters. In fact, if C also refines B, then B and C are called equivalent, for they generate the same filter. Thus passage from prefilter to filter is an instance of passing from a preordering to associated partial ordering.

Special cases edit

Historically, filters generalized to order-theoretic lattices before arbitrary partial orders. In the case of lattices, downward direction can be written as closure under finite meets: for all x, yF, one has xyF.[4]

Linear filters edit

A linear (ultra)filter is an (ultra)filter on the lattice of vector subspaces of a given vector space, ordered by inclusion. Explicitly, a linear filter on a vector space X is a family B of vector subspaces of X such that if A, BB and C is a vector subspace of X that contains A, then ABB and CB.[5]

A linear filter is proper if it does not contain {0}.[5]

Filters on a set; subbases edit

Given a set S, the power set P(S) is partially ordered by set inclusion; filters on this poset are often just called "filters on S," in an abuse of terminology. For such posets, downward direction and upward closure reduce to:[3]

Closure under finite intersections
If A, BF, then so too is ABF.
Isotony
[6] If AF and ABS, then BF.

A proper[7]/non-degenerate[8] filter is one that does not contain , and these three conditions (including non-degeneracy) are Henri Cartan's original definition of a filter.[9][10] It is common — though not universal — to require filters on sets to be proper (whatever one's stance on poset filters); we shall again eschew this convention.

Prefilters on a set are proper if and only if they do not contain either.

For every subset T of P(S), there is a smallest filter F containing T. As with prefilters, T is said to generate or span F; a base for F is the set U of all finite intersections of T. The set T is said to be a filter subbase when F (and thus U) is proper.

Proper filters on sets have the finite intersection property.

If S = ∅, then S admits only the improper filter {∅}.

Free filters edit

A filter is said to be a free if the intersection of its members is empty. A proper principal filter is not free.

Since the intersection of any finite number of members of a filter is also a member, no proper filter on a finite set is free, and indeed is the principal filter generated by the common intersection of all of its members. But a nonprincipal filter on an infinite set is not necessarily free: a filter is free if and only if it includes the Fréchet filter (see § Examples).

Examples edit

See the image at the top of this article for a simple example of filters on the finite poset P({1, 2, 3, 4}).

Partially order ℝ → ℝ, the space of real-valued functions on , by pointwise comparison. Then the set of functions "large at infinity,"

 
is a filter on ℝ → ℝ. One can generalize this construction quite far by compactifying the domain and completing the codomain: if X is a set with distinguished subset S and Y is a poset with distinguished element m, then {f : f |Sm} is a filter in XY.

The set {{k : kN} : N ∈ ℕ} is a filter in P(ℕ). More generally, if D is any directed set, then

 
is a filter in P(D), called the tail filter. Likewise any net {xα}α∈Α generates the eventuality filter {{xβ : α ≤ β} : α ∈ Α}. A tail filter is the eventuality filter for xα = α.

The Fréchet filter on an infinite set X is

 
If (X, μ) is a measure space, then the collection {A : μ(XA) = 0} is a filter. If μ(X) = ∞, then {A : μ(XA) < ∞} is also a filter; the Fréchet filter is the case where μ is counting measure.

Given an ordinal a, a subset of a is called a club if it is closed in the order topology of a but has net-theoretic limit a. The clubs of a form a filter: the club filter♣(a).

The previous construction generalizes as follows: any club C is also a collection of dense subsets (in the ordinal topology) of a, and ♣(a) meets each element of C. Replacing C with an arbitrary collection  of dense sets, there "typically" exists a filter meeting each element of , called a generic filter. For countable , the Rasiowa–Sikorski lemma implies that such a filter must exist; for "small" uncountable , the existence of such a filter can be forced through Martin's axiom.

Let P denote the set of partial orders of limited cardinality, modulo isomorphism. Partially order P by:

AB if there exists a strictly increasing f : AB.

Then the subset of non-atomic partial orders forms a filter. Likewise, if I is the set of injective modules over some given commutative ring, of limited cardinality, modulo isomorphism, then a partial order on I is:

AB if there exists an injective linear map f : AB.[11]

Given any infinite cardinal κ, the modules in I that cannot be generated by fewer than κ elements form a filter.

Every uniform structure on a set X is a filter on X × X.

Relationship to ideals edit

The dual notion to a filter — that is, the concept obtained by reversing all and exchanging with  — is an order ideal. Because of this duality, any question of filters can be mechanically translated to a question about ideals and vice-versa; in particular, a prime or maximal filter is a filter whose corresponding ideal is (respectively) prime or maximal.

A filter is an ultrafilter if and only if the corresponding ideal is minimal.

In model theory edit

For every filter F on a set S, the set function defined by

 
is finitely additive — a "measure," if that term is construed rather loosely. Moreover, the measures so constructed are defined everywhere if F is an ultrafilter. Therefore, the statement
 
can be considered somewhat analogous to the statement that φ holds "almost everywhere." That interpretation of membership in a filter is used (for motivation, not actual proofs) in the theory of ultraproducts in model theory, a branch of mathematical logic.

In topology edit

In general topology and analysis, filters are used to define convergence in a manner similar to the role of sequences in a metric space. They unify the concept of a limit across the wide variety of arbitrary topological spaces.

To understand the need for filters, begin with the equivalent concept of a net. A sequence is usually indexed by the natural numbers , which are a totally ordered set. Nets generalize the notion of a sequence by replacing with an arbitrary directed set. In certain categories of topological spaces, such as first-countable spaces, sequences characterize most topological properties, but this is not true in general. However, nets — as well as filters — always do characterize those topological properties.

Filters do not involve any set external to the topological space X, whereas sequences and nets rely on other directed sets. For this reason, the collection of all filters on X is always a set, whereas the collection of all X-valued nets is a proper class.

Neighborhood bases edit

Any point x in the topological space X defines a neighborhood filter or system Nx: namely, the family of all sets containing x in their interior. A set N of neighborhoods of x is a neighborhood base at x if N generates Nx. Equivalently, SX is a neighborhood of x if and only if there exists NN such that NS.

Convergent filters and cluster points edit

A prefilter B converges to a point x, written Bx, if and only if B generates a filter F that contains the neighborhood filter Nx — explicitly, for every neighborhood U of x, there is some VB such that VU. Less explicitly, Bx if and only if B refines Nx, and any neighborhood base at x can replace Nx in this condition. Clearly, every neighborhood base at x converges to x.

A filter F (which generates itself) converges to x if NxF. The above can also be reversed to characterize the neighborhood filter Nx: Nx is the finest filter coarser than each filter converging to x.

If Bx, then x is called a limit (point) of B. The prefilter B is said to cluster at x (or have x as a cluster point) if and only if each element of B has non-empty intersection with each neighborhood of x. Every limit point is a cluster point but the converse is not true in general. However, every cluster point of an ultrafilter is a limit point.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Koutras et al. 2021.
  2. ^ Igarashi, Ayumi; Zwicker, William S. (16 February 2021). "Fair division of graphs and of tangled cakes". arXiv:2102.08560 [math.CO].
  3. ^ a b Dugundji 1966, pp. 211–213.
  4. ^ Davey, B. A.; Priestley, H. A. (1990). Introduction to Lattices and Order. Cambridge Mathematical Textbooks. Cambridge University Press. p. 184.
  5. ^ a b Bergman & Hrushovski 1998.
  6. ^ Dolecki & Mynard 2016, pp. 27–29.
  7. ^ Goldblatt, R. Lectures on the Hyperreals: an Introduction to Nonstandard Analysis. p. 32.
  8. ^ Narici & Beckenstein 2011, pp. 2–7.
  9. ^ Cartan 1937a.
  10. ^ Cartan 1937b.
  11. ^ Bumby, R. T. (1965-12-01). "Modules which are isomorphic to submodules of each other". Archiv der Mathematik. 16 (1): 184–185. doi:10.1007/BF01220018. ISSN 1420-8938.

References edit

Further reading edit

filter, mathematics, filters, sets, filter, theory, other, uses, filter, disambiguation, this, article, includes, list, general, references, lacks, sufficient, corresponding, inline, citations, please, help, improve, this, article, introducing, more, precise, . For filters on sets see Filter set theory For other uses see Filter disambiguation This article includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this article by introducing more precise citations June 2017 Learn how and when to remove this template message In mathematics a filter or order filter is a special subset of a partially ordered set poset describing large or eventual elements Filters appear in order and lattice theory but also topology whence they originate The notion dual to a filter is an order ideal The power set lattice of the set 1 2 3 4 with upper set 1 4 colored dark green This upper set is a filter and even a principal filter It is not an ultrafilter because including also the light green elements extends it to the larger nontrivial filter 1 Since the latter cannot be extended further 1 is an ultrafilter Special cases of filters include ultrafilters which are filters that cannot be enlarged and describe nonconstructive techniques in mathematical logic Filters on sets were introduced by Henri Cartan in 1937 Nicolas Bourbaki in their book Topologie Generale popularized filters as an alternative to E H Moore and Herman L Smith s 1922 notion of a net order filters generalize this notion from the specific case of a power set under inclusion to arbitrary partially ordered sets Nevertheless the theory of power set filters retains interest in its own right in part for substantial applications in topology Contents 1 Motivation 2 Definition 2 1 Filter bases 2 1 1 Refinement 3 Special cases 3 1 Linear filters 3 2 Filters on a set subbases 3 2 1 Free filters 4 Examples 5 Relationship to ideals 6 In model theory 7 In topology 7 1 Neighborhood bases 7 1 1 Convergent filters and cluster points 8 See also 9 Notes 10 References 11 Further readingMotivation editFix a partially ordered set poset P Intuitively a filter F is a subset of P whose members are elements large enough to satisfy some criterion 1 For instance if x P then the set of elements above x is a filter called the principal filter at x If x and y are incomparable elements of P then neither the principal filter at x nor y is contained in the other Similarly a filter on a set S contains those subsets that are sufficiently large to contain some given thing For example if S is the real line and x S then the family of sets including x in their interior is a filter called the neighborhood filter at x The thing in this case is slightly larger than x but it still does not contain any other specific point of the line The above considerations motivate the upward closure requirement in the definition below large enough objects can always be made larger To understand the other two conditions reverse the roles and instead consider F as a locating scheme to find x In this interpretation one searches in some space X and expects F to describe those subsets of X that contain the goal The goal must be located somewhere thus the empty set can never be in F And if two subsets both contain the goal then should zoom in to their common region An ultrafilter describes a perfect locating scheme where each scheme component gives new information either look here or look elsewhere Compactness is the property that every search is fruitful or to put it another way every locating scheme ends in a search result A common use for a filter is to define properties that are satisfied by generic elements of some topological space 2 This application generalizes the locating scheme to find points that might be hard to write down explicitly Definition editA subset F of a partially ordered set P is a filter or dual ideal if the following are satisfied Nontriviality The set F is non empty Downward directed For every x y F there is some z F such that z x and z y Upward closure For every x F and p P the condition x p implies p F If additionally F P then F is said to be a proper filter Authors in set theory and mathematical logic often require all filters to be proper this article will eschew that convention 3 An ultrafilter is a filter contained in no other proper filter Filter bases edit A subset S of F is a base or basis for F if the upper set generated by S i e the smallest upwards closed set containing S is all of F Every filter is a base for itself Moreover if B P is nonempty and downward directed then B generates an upper set F that is a filter for which B is a base Such sets are called prefilters as well as the aforementioned filter base basis and F is said to be generated or spanned by B A prefilter is proper if and only if it generates a proper filter Given p P the set x p x is the smallest filter containing p and sometimes written p Such a filter is called a principal filter p is said to be the principal element of F or generate F Refinement edit Suppose B and C are two prefilters on P and for each c C there is a b B such that b c Then we say that B is finer than or refines C likewise C is coarser than or coarsens B Refinement is a preorder on the set of prefilters In fact if C also refines B then B and C are called equivalent for they generate the same filter Thus passage from prefilter to filter is an instance of passing from a preordering to associated partial ordering Special cases editHistorically filters generalized to order theoretic lattices before arbitrary partial orders In the case of lattices downward direction can be written as closure under finite meets for all x y F one has x y F 4 Linear filters edit A linear ultra filter is an ultra filter on the lattice of vector subspaces of a given vector space ordered by inclusion Explicitly a linear filter on a vector space X is a family B of vector subspaces of X such that if A B B and C is a vector subspace of X that contains A then A B B and C B 5 A linear filter is proper if it does not contain 0 5 Filters on a set subbases edit Main article Filter set theory Families F displaystyle mathcal F nbsp of sets over W displaystyle Omega nbsp vteIs necessarily true of F displaystyle mathcal F colon nbsp or is F displaystyle mathcal F nbsp closed under Directedby displaystyle supseteq nbsp A B displaystyle A cap B nbsp A B displaystyle A cup B nbsp B A displaystyle B setminus A nbsp W A displaystyle Omega setminus A nbsp A 1 A 2 displaystyle A 1 cap A 2 cap cdots nbsp A 1 A 2 displaystyle A 1 cup A 2 cup cdots nbsp W F displaystyle Omega in mathcal F nbsp F displaystyle varnothing in mathcal F nbsp F I P p system nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp Semiring nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp NeverSemialgebra Semifield nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp NeverMonotone class nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp only if A i displaystyle A i searrow nbsp only if A i displaystyle A i nearrow nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp 𝜆 system Dynkin System nbsp nbsp nbsp only ifA B displaystyle A subseteq B nbsp nbsp nbsp only if A i displaystyle A i nearrow nbsp orthey are disjoint nbsp nbsp NeverRing Order theory nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp Ring Measure theory nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp Neverd Ring nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp Never𝜎 Ring nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp NeverAlgebra Field nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp Never𝜎 Algebra 𝜎 Field nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp NeverDual ideal nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp Filter nbsp nbsp nbsp Never Never nbsp nbsp nbsp F displaystyle varnothing not in mathcal F nbsp nbsp Prefilter Filter base nbsp nbsp nbsp Never Never nbsp nbsp nbsp F displaystyle varnothing not in mathcal F nbsp nbsp Filter subbase nbsp nbsp nbsp Never Never nbsp nbsp nbsp F displaystyle varnothing not in mathcal F nbsp nbsp Open Topology nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp even arbitrary displaystyle cup nbsp nbsp nbsp NeverClosed Topology nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp even arbitrary displaystyle cap nbsp nbsp nbsp nbsp NeverIs necessarily true of F displaystyle mathcal F colon nbsp or is F displaystyle mathcal F nbsp closed under directeddownward finiteintersections finiteunions relativecomplements complementsin W displaystyle Omega nbsp countableintersections countableunions contains W displaystyle Omega nbsp contains displaystyle varnothing nbsp FiniteIntersectionPropertyAdditionally a semiring is a p system where every complement B A displaystyle B setminus A nbsp is equal to a finite disjoint union of sets in F displaystyle mathcal F nbsp A semialgebra is a semiring where every complement W A displaystyle Omega setminus A nbsp is equal to a finite disjoint union of sets in F displaystyle mathcal F nbsp A B A 1 A 2 displaystyle A B A 1 A 2 ldots nbsp are arbitrary elements of F displaystyle mathcal F nbsp and it is assumed that F displaystyle mathcal F neq varnothing nbsp Given a set S the power set P S is partially ordered by set inclusion filters on this poset are often just called filters on S in an abuse of terminology For such posets downward direction and upward closure reduce to 3 Closure under finite intersections If A B F then so too is A B F Isotony 6 If A F and A B S then B F A proper 7 non degenerate 8 filter is one that does not contain and these three conditions including non degeneracy are Henri Cartan s original definition of a filter 9 10 It is common though not universal to require filters on sets to be proper whatever one s stance on poset filters we shall again eschew this convention Prefilters on a set are proper if and only if they do not contain either For every subset T of P S there is a smallest filter F containing T As with prefilters T is said to generate or span F a base for F is the set U of all finite intersections of T The set T is said to be a filter subbase when F and thus U is proper Proper filters on sets have the finite intersection property If S then S admits only the improper filter Free filters edit A filter is said to be a free if the intersection of its members is empty A proper principal filter is not free Since the intersection of any finite number of members of a filter is also a member no proper filter on a finite set is free and indeed is the principal filter generated by the common intersection of all of its members But a nonprincipal filter on an infinite set is not necessarily free a filter is free if and only if it includes the Frechet filter see Examples Examples editSee the image at the top of this article for a simple example of filters on the finite poset P 1 2 3 4 Partially order ℝ ℝ the space of real valued functions on ℝ by pointwise comparison Then the set of functions large at infinity f lim x f x displaystyle left f lim x to pm infty f x infty right text nbsp is a filter on ℝ ℝ One can generalize this construction quite far by compactifying the domain and completing the codomain if X is a set with distinguished subset S and Y is a poset with distinguished element m then f f S m is a filter in X Y The set k k N N ℕ is a filter in P ℕ More generally if D is any directed set then k k N N D displaystyle k k geq N N in D nbsp is a filter in P D called the tail filter Likewise any net xa a A generates the eventuality filter xb a b a A A tail filter is the eventuality filter for xa a The Frechet filter on an infinite set X is A X A finite displaystyle A X setminus A text finite text nbsp If X m is a measure space then the collection A m X A 0 is a filter If m X then A m X A lt is also a filter the Frechet filter is the case where m is counting measure Given an ordinal a a subset of a is called a club if it is closed in the order topology of a but has net theoretic limit a The clubs of a form a filter the club filter a The previous construction generalizes as follows any club C is also a collection of dense subsets in the ordinal topology of a and a meets each element of C Replacing C with an arbitrary collection C of dense sets there typically exists a filter meeting each element of C called a generic filter For countable C the Rasiowa Sikorski lemma implies that such a filter must exist for small uncountable C the existence of such a filter can be forced through Martin s axiom Let P denote the set of partial orders of limited cardinality modulo isomorphism Partially order P by A B if there exists a strictly increasing f A B Then the subset of non atomic partial orders forms a filter Likewise if I is the set of injective modules over some given commutative ring of limited cardinality modulo isomorphism then a partial order on I is A B if there exists an injective linear map f A B 11 Given any infinite cardinal k the modules in I that cannot be generated by fewer than k elements form a filter Every uniform structure on a set X is a filter on X X Relationship to ideals editMain article Ideal order theory The dual notion to a filter that is the concept obtained by reversing all and exchanging with is an order ideal Because of this duality any question of filters can be mechanically translated to a question about ideals and vice versa in particular a prime or maximal filter is a filter whose corresponding ideal is respectively prime or maximal A filter is an ultrafilter if and only if the corresponding ideal is minimal In model theory editSee also Filter quantifier For every filter F on a set S the set function defined bym A 1 if A F 0 if S A F is undefined otherwise displaystyle m A begin cases 1 amp text if A in F 0 amp text if S smallsetminus A in F text is undefined amp text otherwise end cases nbsp is finitely additive a measure if that term is construed rather loosely Moreover the measures so constructed are defined everywhere if F is an ultrafilter Therefore the statement x S f x F displaystyle left x in S varphi x right in F nbsp can be considered somewhat analogous to the statement that f holds almost everywhere That interpretation of membership in a filter is used for motivation not actual proofs in the theory of ultraproducts in model theory a branch of mathematical logic In topology editMain article Filters in topology In general topology and analysis filters are used to define convergence in a manner similar to the role of sequences in a metric space They unify the concept of a limit across the wide variety of arbitrary topological spaces To understand the need for filters begin with the equivalent concept of a net A sequence is usually indexed by the natural numbers ℕ which are a totally ordered set Nets generalize the notion of a sequence by replacing ℕ with an arbitrary directed set In certain categories of topological spaces such as first countable spaces sequences characterize most topological properties but this is not true in general However nets as well as filters always do characterize those topological properties Filters do not involve any set external to the topological space X whereas sequences and nets rely on other directed sets For this reason the collection of all filters on X is always a set whereas the collection of all X valued nets is a proper class Neighborhood bases edit Any point x in the topological space X defines a neighborhood filter or system N x namely the family of all sets containing x in their interior A set N of neighborhoods of x is a neighborhood base at x if N generates N x Equivalently S X is a neighborhood of x if and only if there exists N N such that N S Convergent filters and cluster points edit A prefilter B converges to a point x written B x if and only if B generates a filter F that contains the neighborhood filter N x explicitly for every neighborhood U of x there is some V B such that V U Less explicitly B x if and only if B refines N x and any neighborhood base at x can replace N x in this condition Clearly every neighborhood base at x converges to x A filter F which generates itself converges to x if N x F The above can also be reversed to characterize the neighborhood filter N x N x is the finest filter coarser than each filter converging to x If B x then x is called a limit point of B The prefilter B is said to cluster at x or have x as a cluster point if and only if each element of B has non empty intersection with each neighborhood of x Every limit point is a cluster point but the converse is not true in general However every cluster point of an ultrafilter is a limit point See also editFiltration mathematics Filtration probability theory Model of information available at a given point of a random process Filtration abstract algebra Generic filter in set theory given a collection of dense open subsets of a poset a filter that meets all sets in that collectionPages displaying wikidata descriptions as a fallback Ideal set theory Non empty family of sets that is closed under finite unions and subsetsNotes edit Koutras et al 2021 Igarashi Ayumi Zwicker William S 16 February 2021 Fair division of graphs and of tangled cakes arXiv 2102 08560 math CO a b Dugundji 1966 pp 211 213 Davey B A Priestley H A 1990 Introduction to Lattices and Order Cambridge Mathematical Textbooks Cambridge University Press p 184 a b Bergman amp Hrushovski 1998 Dolecki amp Mynard 2016 pp 27 29 Goldblatt R Lectures on the Hyperreals an Introduction to Nonstandard Analysis p 32 Narici amp Beckenstein 2011 pp 2 7 Cartan 1937a Cartan 1937b Bumby R T 1965 12 01 Modules which are isomorphic to submodules of each other Archiv der Mathematik 16 1 184 185 doi 10 1007 BF01220018 ISSN 1420 8938 References editNicolas Bourbaki General Topology Topologie Generale ISBN 0 387 19374 X Ch 1 4 Provides a good reference for filters in general topology Chapter I and for Cauchy filters in uniform spaces Chapter II Bourbaki Nicolas 1987 1981 Topological Vector Spaces Chapters 1 5 Elements de mathematique Translated by Eggleston H G Madan S Berlin New York Springer Verlag ISBN 3 540 13627 4 OCLC 17499190 Burris Stanley Sankappanavar Hanamantagouda P 2012 A Course in Universal Algebra PDF Springer Verlag ISBN 978 0 9880552 0 9 Archived from the original on 1 April 2022 Cartan Henri 1937a Theorie des filtres Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des seances de l Academie des sciences 205 595 598 Cartan Henri 1937b Filtres et ultrafiltres Comptes rendus hebdomadaires des seances de l Academie des sciences 205 777 779 Dolecki Szymon Mynard Frederic 2016 Convergence Foundations Of Topology New Jersey World Scientific Publishing Company ISBN 978 981 4571 52 4 OCLC 945169917 Dugundji James 1966 Topology Boston Allyn and Bacon ISBN 978 0 697 06889 7 OCLC 395340485 Koutras Costas D Moyzes Christos Nomikos Christos Tsaprounis Konstantinos Zikos Yorgos 20 October 2021 On Weak Filters and Ultrafilters Set Theory From and for Knowledge Representation Logic Journal of the IGPL doi 10 1093 jigpal jzab030 MacIver R David 1 July 2004 Filters in Analysis and Topology PDF Archived from the original PDF on 2007 10 09 Provides an introductory review of filters in topology and in metric spaces Narici Lawrence Beckenstein Edward 2011 Topological Vector Spaces Pure and applied mathematics Second ed Boca Raton FL CRC Press ISBN 978 1584888666 OCLC 144216834 Willard Stephen 2004 1970 General Topology Mineola N Y Dover Publications ISBN 978 0 486 43479 7 OCLC 115240 Wilansky Albert 2013 Modern Methods in Topological Vector Spaces Mineola New York Dover Publications Inc ISBN 978 0 486 49353 4 OCLC 849801114 Further reading editBergman George M Hrushovski Ehud 1998 Linear ultrafilters Communications in Algebra 26 12 4079 4113 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 54 9927 doi 10 1080 00927879808826396 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Filter mathematics amp oldid 1206875528 directed downward, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.