fbpx
Wikipedia

Argument from authority

An argument from authority (argumentum ab auctoritate), also called an appeal to authority, or argumentum ad verecundiam, is a form of argument in which the opinion of an influential figure is used as evidence to support an argument.[1]

All sources agree this is not a valid form of logical proof, that is to say, that this is a logical fallacy [2] (also known as ad verecundiam fallacy) , and therefore, obtaining knowledge in this way is always fallible.[3][4]

However, in particular circumstances, it is sound to use as a practical although fallible way of obtaining information that can be considered generally likely to be correct if the authority is a real and pertinent intellectual authority and there is universal consensus about these statements in this field.[1][5][6][7][8] This is specially the case when the revision of all the information and data 'from scratch' would impede advances in an investigation or education. Further ways of validating a source include: evaluating the veracity of previous works by the author, their competence on the topic, their coherence, their conflicts of interest, etc.

Validity of the argument in deductive and inductive methods edit

In the deductive method edit

This argument has been considered a logical fallacy since its introduction by John Locke and Richard Whately.[9] In particular, this is a form of genetic fallacy; in which the conclusion about the validity of a statement is justified by appealing to the characteristics of the person who is speaking, such as in the ad hominem fallacy.[10] For this argument, Locke coined the term argumentum ad verecundiam (appeal to shamefacedness/modesty) because it appeals to the fear of humiliation by appearing disrespectful to a particular authority.[11]

This qualification as a logical fallacy implies that this argument is invalid when using the deductive method, and therefore it can't be presented as infallible.[12] In other words, it's logically invalid to prove a claim is true because an authority has said it. The explanation is simple: authorities can be wrong, and the only way of logically proving a claim is providing real evidence and/or a valid logical deduction of the claim from the evidence.[13][14][15]

Other related logical fallacies edit

It is also a fallacious ad hominem argument to argue that a person presenting statements lacks authority and thus their arguments do not need to be considered.[10] Other related fallacious arguments assume that a person without status or authority is inherently reliable. For instance, the appeal to poverty is the fallacy of thinking that someone is more likely to be correct because they are poor.[16] When an argument holds that a conclusion is likely to be true precisely because the one who holds or is presenting it lacks authority, it is an appeal to the common man.[17]

In the inductive method edit

However, when used in the inductive method, which implies the conclusions can never be proven or certain,[12] this argument can be considered sound and not fallacious. If a person has a credible authority, it is more likely that their assessments would be correct, especially if there is consensus about the topic between the credible sources.[citation needed]

The general form of this type of argument is:

Person A claims that X is true.
Person A is an expert in the field concerning X.
Therefore, X should be believed.[18]

Nonetheless, it would also be a fallacy, even in the inductive method, when the source of the claim is a false authority, such as when the supposed authority is not a real expert, or when supporting a claim outside of their area of expertise. This is referred to as an "argument from false authority".[19] It can also be considered a fallacy when the authority is an expert in the topic but their claims are controversial or not unanimous between other experts in the field. Some consider that it can be used in a cogent form if all sides of a discussion agree on the reliability of the cited authority in the given context.[20] This form of argument can be considered sound if both parties to the debate agree that the authority is in fact an expert;[20][21][22]

Furthermore, some claim that the act of trusting authorities is unavoidable for science to progress, since it would be a lot harder if not impossible for students and researchers to always resort to the factual evidence and demonstrations for all the knowledge they need to obtain to be able to come across new scientific findings.[23]

At the same time, others claim that authority "has no place in science",[24] meaning that the validity of claims always has to lay, ultimately, on the evidence and proofs provided, and not in the prestige of the authors.[citation needed]

Confusion about its classification as a logical fallacy but a sound inductive criterion edit

Some authors fail to distinguish between the classification of this argumentum ad verecundiam as a logical fallacy, and its classification as a fallacy within the inductive method 'only' when the authority is false or their claims disputed; but failing to address that the weight of this argument can never be more than relative and never a proof since it is logically invalid. This serious mistake has sadly been widely popularized in the last few decades, and lead to the wrong belief that the ad verecundiam argument is logically valid and therefore an absolute proof.[citation needed]

The qualification of this type of argument as logical fallacy implies that it is not a valid way to deduce a conclusion, that is, to prove it.[12] This doesn't mean that a claim from a credible respected authority doesn't generally have a bigger probability of being correct than that of somebody who has no expertise at all; but the strength of this argument is not absolute as it's wrongfully believed by some.[12]

Use in science edit

Scientific knowledge is best established by evidence and experiment rather than argued through authority[13][14][15] as authority has no place in science.[14][25][26] Carl Sagan wrote of arguments from authority: "One of the great commandments of science is, 'Mistrust arguments from authority.' ... Too many such arguments have proved too painfully wrong. Authorities must prove their contentions like everybody else."[24] Conversely, it has been argued that science is fundamentally dependent on arguments from authority to progress as "they allow science to avoid forever revisiting the same ground".[23]

One example of the use of the appeal to authority in science dates to 1923,[27] when leading American zoologist Theophilus Painter declared, based on poor data and conflicting observations he had made,[28][29] that humans had 24 pairs of chromosomes. From the 1920s until 1956,[30] scientists propagated this "fact" based on Painter's authority,[31][32][29] despite subsequent counts totaling the correct number of 23.[28][33] Even textbooks[28] with photos showing 23 pairs incorrectly declared the number to be 24[33] based on the authority of the then-consensus of 24 pairs.[34]

This seemingly established number generated confirmation bias among researchers, and "most cytologists, expecting to detect Painter's number, virtually always did so".[34] Painter's "influence was so great that many scientists preferred to believe his count over the actual evidence",[33] and scientists who obtained the accurate number modified[35] or discarded[36] their data to agree with Painter's count.

Roots in cognitive bias edit

Arguments from authority that are based on the idea that a person should conform to the opinion of a perceived authority or authoritative group are rooted in psychological cognitive biases[37] such as the Asch effect.[38][39][40] In repeated and modified instances of the Asch conformity experiments, it was found that high-status individuals create a stronger likelihood of a subject agreeing with an obviously false conclusion, despite the subject normally being able to clearly see that the answer was incorrect.[41]

Further, humans have been shown to feel strong emotional pressure to conform to authorities and majority positions. A repeat of the experiments by another group of researchers found that "Participants reported considerable distress under the group pressure", with 59% conforming at least once and agreeing with the clearly incorrect answer, whereas the incorrect answer was much more rarely given when no such pressures were present.[42]

Another study shining light on the psychological basis of the fallacy as it relates to perceived authorities are the Milgram experiments, which demonstrated that people are more likely to go along with something when it is presented by an authority.[43] In a variation of a study where the researchers did not wear lab coats, thus reducing the perceived authority of the tasker, the obedience level dropped to 20% from the original rate, which had been higher than 50%. Obedience is encouraged by reminding the individual of what a perceived authority states and by showing them that their opinion goes against this authority.[43]

Scholars have noted that certain environments can produce an ideal situation for these processes to take hold, giving rise to groupthink.[44] In groupthink, individuals in a group feel inclined to minimize conflict and encourage conformity. Through an appeal to authority, a group member might present that opinion as a consensus and encourage the other group members to engage in groupthink by not disagreeing with this perceived consensus or authority.[45][46] One paper about the philosophy of mathematics states that, within academia,

If...a person accepts our discipline, and goes through two or three years of graduate study in mathematics, he absorbs our way of thinking, and is no longer the critical outsider he once was...If the student is unable to absorb our way of thinking, we flunk him out, of course. If he gets through our obstacle course and then decides that our arguments are unclear or incorrect, we dismiss him as a crank, crackpot, or misfit.[47]

Corporate environments are similarly vulnerable to appeals to perceived authorities and experts leading to groupthink,[48] as are governments and militaries.[49]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b "Fallacies". University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill.
  2. ^ Sadler, Troy (2006). "Promoting Discourse and Argumentation in Science Teacher Education". Journal of Science Teacher Education. 17 (4): 330. doi:10.1007/s10972-006-9025-4. S2CID 144949172.
  3. ^ Cummings, Louise (2015). "Argument from Authority". Reasoning and Public Health: New Ways of Coping with Uncertainty. Springer. pp. 67–92. doi:10.1007/978-3-319-15013-0_4. ISBN 9783319150130. The argument from authority has had many detractors throughout the long history of logic. It is not difficult to see why this is the case. After all, the argument resorts to the use of opinion to support a claim rather than a range of more objective sources of support (e.g. evidence from experiments)...These difficulties and other weaknesses of authority arguments have found these arguments maligned in the logical treatises of several historical thinkers...'argument from authority has been mentioned in lists of valid argument-forms as often as in lists of Fallacies'
  4. ^ Underwood, R.H. (1994). "Logic and the Common law Trial". American Journal of Trial Advocacy: 166.
  5. ^ Lewiński, Marcin (2008). "Comments on 'Black box arguments'". Argumentation. 22 (3): 447–451. doi:10.1007/s10503-008-9095-x.
  6. ^ Eemeren, Frans (2010). Strategic Maneuvering in Argumentative Discourse: Extending the Pragma-dialectical Theory of Argumentation. John Benjamins. p. 203. ISBN 978-9027211194.
  7. ^ Bedau, Mark (2009). The ethics of protocells. Boston, Massachusetts; London, England: Mit Press. pp. 341. ISBN 978-0-262-01262-1.
  8. ^ Goodwin, Jean; McKerrow, Raymie (2011). "Accounting for the force of the appeal to authority". OSSA Conference Archive.
  9. ^ Hansen, Vilhem (1998). "Locke and Whately on the Argumentum ad Ignorantiam". Philosophy & Rhetoric, Vol. 31, No. 1. Vol. 31. Penn State University Press. p. 60. JSTOR 40237981. (...) Locke thought no better or worse of the ad ignorantiam than he did of ad verecundiam or ad hominem (…) At the end of his discussion of the ad hominem as a fallacy, Whately says, "The same observations will apply to 'argumentum ad verecundiam' and the rest" (1853, 3.1). (…) If we use this analysis of the ad hominem as a model for how Whately thought of the other ad arguments, then the ad verecundiam will be an argument with premises that say that amazing authority . . . [or] some venerable institution" and a conclusion claiming that the one to whom the ad verecundiam is addressed ought to accept the conclusion in question on pain of being at odds with those commitments. Similarly, an ad populum argument will be one that includes among its premises the claim that such and such is a widely held opinion or commitment "of the multitude" and the conclusion will be that the person to whom the argument is directed is bound to accept a logical consequence of the commitments invoked. {{cite book}}: |journal= ignored (help)
  10. ^ a b Williamson, Owen. "Master List of Logical Fallacies". The University of Texas at El Paso.
  11. ^ Goodwin, Jean (May 1998). "Forms of Authority and the Real Ad Verecundiam". Argumentation. 12 (2): 267–280 – via Springer Science+Business Media.
  12. ^ a b c d Garrett, Aaron (2014). The Routledge Companion to Eighteenth Century Philosophy. Routledge. p. 280. ISBN 9781317807926. demonstrations proceed deductively while probable reasoning involves inductive inferences.
  13. ^ a b McBride, Michael. . Yale University. Archived from the original on 2010-07-24. Retrieved 2017-08-10.
  14. ^ a b c Zinser, Otto (1984). Basic Principles of Experimental Psychology. McGraw-Hill. p. 37. ISBN 9780070728455.
  15. ^ a b Stephen, Leslie (1882). The Science of Ethics. G. P. Putnam's sons. p. viii.
  16. ^ Ruggiero, Tim. "Logical Fallacies".
  17. ^ Bennett, Bo. "Appeal to the Common Man". Logically Fallacious.
  18. ^ Curtis, Gary N. "Misleading Appeal to Authority". The Fallacy Files. Retrieved 2021-07-08.
  19. ^ "Argument from False Authority". Logically Fallcious.
  20. ^ a b "Fallacies". University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill.
  21. ^ Lewiński, Marcin (2008). "Comments on 'Black box arguments'". Argumentation. 22 (3): 447–451. doi:10.1007/s10503-008-9095-x.
  22. ^ Eemeren, Frans (2010). Strategic Maneuvering in Argumentative Discourse: Extending the Pragma-dialectical Theory of Argumentation. John Benjamins. p. 203. ISBN 978-9027211194.
  23. ^ a b Sismondo, Sergio (1999). "Scepticism and Authority in Popular Science (review)", Queen's Quarterly, Kingston, Vol. 106, Iss. 1, (Spring 1999). p106.
  24. ^ a b Sagan, Carl (July 6, 2011). The Demon-Haunted World: Science as a Candle in the Dark. Ballantine Books. ISBN 9780307801043.
  25. ^ Stevenson, I. (1990). Some of My Journeys in Medicine (PDF). The University of Southwestern Louisiana. p. 18.
  26. ^ Quick, James Campbell; Little, Laura M.; Cooper, Cary L.; Gibbs, Philip C.; Nelson, Debra (2010). "Organizational Behavior". International Review of Industrial and Organizational Psychology: 278.
  27. ^ Painter, Theophilus S. (April 1923), "Studies in mammalian spermatogenesis. II. The spermatogenesis of man", Journal of Experimental Zoology, 37 (3): 291–336, doi:10.1002/jez.1400370303
  28. ^ a b c Glass, Bentley (1990). Theophilus Shickel Painter (PDF). Washington, DC: National Academy of Sciences. pp. 316–17.
  29. ^ a b Mertens, Thomas (October 1979). "The Role of Factual Knowledge in Biology Teaching". The American Biology Teacher. 41 (7): 395–419. doi:10.2307/4446671. JSTOR 4446671.
  30. ^ Tjio, Joe Hin; Levan, Albert (May 1956), "The Chromosome Number of Man", Hereditas, 42 (1–2): 723–4, doi:10.1111/j.1601-5223.1956.tb03010.x, PMID 345813
  31. ^ O'Connor, Clare (2008), Human Chromosome Number, Nature, retrieved April 24, 2014
  32. ^ Gartler, Stanley (2006). "The Chromosome Number in Humans: A Brief History". Nature Reviews Genetics. 7 (8): 655–60. doi:10.1038/nrg1917. PMID 16847465. S2CID 21365693.
  33. ^ a b c Orrell, David PhD. (2008). The Future of Everything: The Science of Prediction. pp. 184–85.
  34. ^ a b Kevles, Daniel J. (1985). "Human Chromosomes--Down's Disorder and the Binder's Mistakes" (PDF). Engineering and Science: 9.
  35. ^ T. C., Hsu (1979). "Out of the Dark Ages: Human and Mammalian Cytogenetics: An Historical Perspective" (PDF). Cell. 18 (4): 1375–1376. doi:10.1016/0092-8674(79)90249-6. S2CID 54330665.
  36. ^ Unger, Lawrence; Blystone, Robert (1996). (PDF). Bioscene. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2006-09-05. Retrieved 2016-03-24.
  37. ^ Sammut, Gordon; Bauer, Martin W (2011). "Social Influence: Modes and Modalities". The Social Psychology of Communication (PDF). pp. 87–106. doi:10.1057/9780230297616_5. ISBN 978-0-230-24736-9.
  38. ^ Delameter, Andrew (2017). "Contrasting Scientific & Non-Scientific Approaches to Acquiring Knowledge". City University of New York.
  39. ^ Sheldon, Brian; Macdonald, Geraldine (2010). A Textbook of Social Work. Routledge. p. 40. ISBN 9781135282615.
  40. ^ Bates, Jordan (16 March 2016). "12 Psychological Tactics Donald Trump Uses to Manipulate the Masses". 11. Appeals to Authority.
  41. ^ McLeod, Samuel (2008), Asch Experiment, Simply Psychology
  42. ^ Webley, Paul, A partial and non-evaluative history of the Asch effect, University of Exeter
  43. ^ a b Milgram, S (1965). "Some conditions of obedience and disobedience to authority". Human Relations. 18 (1): 57–76. doi:10.1177/001872676501800105. S2CID 37505499.
  44. ^ "December 2014 – Page 2". Disrupted Physician. 22 December 2014.
  45. ^ Definition of GROUPTHINK. (2017). Merriam-webster.com. Retrieved from https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/groupthink
  46. ^ Rossi, Stacey (2006). "Examination of Exclusion Rates in Massachusetts Public Schools" (PDF).{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link)
  47. ^ David, Phillip J.; Hersh, Reuben (1998). (PDF). Princeton University Press. p. 8. Archived from the original (PDF) on 2016-03-04.
  48. ^ Lookwin, B. (2015). . Archived from the original on 2017-09-12. Retrieved 2017-09-12.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: numeric names: authors list (link)
  49. ^ Janis, Irving L. (1971). "Groupthink" (PDF). Psychology Today.

argument, from, authority, wikiquote, quotations, related, argument, from, authority, argumentum, auctoritate, also, called, appeal, authority, argumentum, verecundiam, form, argument, which, opinion, influential, figure, used, evidence, support, argument, sou. Wikiquote has quotations related to Argument from authority An argument from authority argumentum ab auctoritate also called an appeal to authority or argumentum ad verecundiam is a form of argument in which the opinion of an influential figure is used as evidence to support an argument 1 All sources agree this is not a valid form of logical proof that is to say that this is a logical fallacy 2 also known as ad verecundiam fallacy and therefore obtaining knowledge in this way is always fallible 3 4 However in particular circumstances it is sound to use as a practical although fallible way of obtaining information that can be considered generally likely to be correct if the authority is a real and pertinent intellectual authority and there is universal consensus about these statements in this field 1 5 6 7 8 This is specially the case when the revision of all the information and data from scratch would impede advances in an investigation or education Further ways of validating a source include evaluating the veracity of previous works by the author their competence on the topic their coherence their conflicts of interest etc Contents 1 Validity of the argument in deductive and inductive methods 1 1 In the deductive method 1 1 1 Other related logical fallacies 1 2 In the inductive method 1 3 Confusion about its classification as a logical fallacy but a sound inductive criterion 2 Use in science 3 Roots in cognitive bias 4 See also 5 ReferencesValidity of the argument in deductive and inductive methods editIn the deductive method edit This argument has been considered a logical fallacy since its introduction by John Locke and Richard Whately 9 In particular this is a form of genetic fallacy in which the conclusion about the validity of a statement is justified by appealing to the characteristics of the person who is speaking such as in the ad hominem fallacy 10 For this argument Locke coined the term argumentum ad verecundiam appeal to shamefacedness modesty because it appeals to the fear of humiliation by appearing disrespectful to a particular authority 11 This qualification as a logical fallacy implies that this argument is invalid when using the deductive method and therefore it can t be presented as infallible 12 In other words it s logically invalid to prove a claim is true because an authority has said it The explanation is simple authorities can be wrong and the only way of logically proving a claim is providing real evidence and or a valid logical deduction of the claim from the evidence 13 14 15 Other related logical fallacies edit It is also a fallacious ad hominem argument to argue that a person presenting statements lacks authority and thus their arguments do not need to be considered 10 Other related fallacious arguments assume that a person without status or authority is inherently reliable For instance the appeal to poverty is the fallacy of thinking that someone is more likely to be correct because they are poor 16 When an argument holds that a conclusion is likely to be true precisely because the one who holds or is presenting it lacks authority it is an appeal to the common man 17 In the inductive method edit Further information Inductivism However when used in the inductive method which implies the conclusions can never be proven or certain 12 this argument can be considered sound and not fallacious If a person has a credible authority it is more likely that their assessments would be correct especially if there is consensus about the topic between the credible sources citation needed The general form of this type of argument is Person A claims that X is true Person A is an expert in the field concerning X Therefore X should be believed 18 Nonetheless it would also be a fallacy even in the inductive method when the source of the claim is a false authority such as when the supposed authority is not a real expert or when supporting a claim outside of their area of expertise This is referred to as an argument from false authority 19 It can also be considered a fallacy when the authority is an expert in the topic but their claims are controversial or not unanimous between other experts in the field Some consider that it can be used in a cogent form if all sides of a discussion agree on the reliability of the cited authority in the given context 20 This form of argument can be considered sound if both parties to the debate agree that the authority is in fact an expert 20 21 22 Furthermore some claim that the act of trusting authorities is unavoidable for science to progress since it would be a lot harder if not impossible for students and researchers to always resort to the factual evidence and demonstrations for all the knowledge they need to obtain to be able to come across new scientific findings 23 At the same time others claim that authority has no place in science 24 meaning that the validity of claims always has to lay ultimately on the evidence and proofs provided and not in the prestige of the authors citation needed Confusion about its classification as a logical fallacy but a sound inductive criterion edit Some authors fail to distinguish between the classification of this argumentum ad verecundiam as a logical fallacy and its classification as a fallacy within the inductive method only when the authority is false or their claims disputed but failing to address that the weight of this argument can never be more than relative and never a proof since it is logically invalid This serious mistake has sadly been widely popularized in the last few decades and lead to the wrong belief that the ad verecundiam argument is logically valid and therefore an absolute proof citation needed The qualification of this type of argument as logical fallacy implies that it is not a valid way to deduce a conclusion that is to prove it 12 This doesn t mean that a claim from a credible respected authority doesn t generally have a bigger probability of being correct than that of somebody who has no expertise at all but the strength of this argument is not absolute as it s wrongfully believed by some 12 Use in science editScientific knowledge is best established by evidence and experiment rather than argued through authority 13 14 15 as authority has no place in science 14 25 26 Carl Sagan wrote of arguments from authority One of the great commandments of science is Mistrust arguments from authority Too many such arguments have proved too painfully wrong Authorities must prove their contentions like everybody else 24 Conversely it has been argued that science is fundamentally dependent on arguments from authority to progress as they allow science to avoid forever revisiting the same ground 23 One example of the use of the appeal to authority in science dates to 1923 27 when leading American zoologist Theophilus Painter declared based on poor data and conflicting observations he had made 28 29 that humans had 24 pairs of chromosomes From the 1920s until 1956 30 scientists propagated this fact based on Painter s authority 31 32 29 despite subsequent counts totaling the correct number of 23 28 33 Even textbooks 28 with photos showing 23 pairs incorrectly declared the number to be 24 33 based on the authority of the then consensus of 24 pairs 34 This seemingly established number generated confirmation bias among researchers and most cytologists expecting to detect Painter s number virtually always did so 34 Painter s influence was so great that many scientists preferred to believe his count over the actual evidence 33 and scientists who obtained the accurate number modified 35 or discarded 36 their data to agree with Painter s count Roots in cognitive bias editArguments from authority that are based on the idea that a person should conform to the opinion of a perceived authority or authoritative group are rooted in psychological cognitive biases 37 such as the Asch effect 38 39 40 In repeated and modified instances of the Asch conformity experiments it was found that high status individuals create a stronger likelihood of a subject agreeing with an obviously false conclusion despite the subject normally being able to clearly see that the answer was incorrect 41 Further humans have been shown to feel strong emotional pressure to conform to authorities and majority positions A repeat of the experiments by another group of researchers found that Participants reported considerable distress under the group pressure with 59 conforming at least once and agreeing with the clearly incorrect answer whereas the incorrect answer was much more rarely given when no such pressures were present 42 Another study shining light on the psychological basis of the fallacy as it relates to perceived authorities are the Milgram experiments which demonstrated that people are more likely to go along with something when it is presented by an authority 43 In a variation of a study where the researchers did not wear lab coats thus reducing the perceived authority of the tasker the obedience level dropped to 20 from the original rate which had been higher than 50 Obedience is encouraged by reminding the individual of what a perceived authority states and by showing them that their opinion goes against this authority 43 Scholars have noted that certain environments can produce an ideal situation for these processes to take hold giving rise to groupthink 44 In groupthink individuals in a group feel inclined to minimize conflict and encourage conformity Through an appeal to authority a group member might present that opinion as a consensus and encourage the other group members to engage in groupthink by not disagreeing with this perceived consensus or authority 45 46 One paper about the philosophy of mathematics states that within academia If a person accepts our discipline and goes through two or three years of graduate study in mathematics he absorbs our way of thinking and is no longer the critical outsider he once was If the student is unable to absorb our way of thinking we flunk him out of course If he gets through our obstacle course and then decides that our arguments are unclear or incorrect we dismiss him as a crank crackpot or misfit 47 Corporate environments are similarly vulnerable to appeals to perceived authorities and experts leading to groupthink 48 as are governments and militaries 49 See also editAuthority bias Credentialism Ethos Ipse dixit Manifesto of the Ninety Three Milgram experiment Name dropping Nobel disease Philosophy of testimony Divine command theory Euthyphro dilemmaReferences edit a b Fallacies University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Sadler Troy 2006 Promoting Discourse and Argumentation in Science Teacher Education Journal of Science Teacher Education 17 4 330 doi 10 1007 s10972 006 9025 4 S2CID 144949172 Cummings Louise 2015 Argument from Authority Reasoning and Public Health New Ways of Coping with Uncertainty Springer pp 67 92 doi 10 1007 978 3 319 15013 0 4 ISBN 9783319150130 The argument from authority has had many detractors throughout the long history of logic It is not difficult to see why this is the case After all the argument resorts to the use of opinion to support a claim rather than a range of more objective sources of support e g evidence from experiments These difficulties and other weaknesses of authority arguments have found these arguments maligned in the logical treatises of several historical thinkers argument from authority has been mentioned in lists of valid argument forms as often as in lists of Fallacies Underwood R H 1994 Logic and the Common law Trial American Journal of Trial Advocacy 166 Lewinski Marcin 2008 Comments on Black box arguments Argumentation 22 3 447 451 doi 10 1007 s10503 008 9095 x Eemeren Frans 2010 Strategic Maneuvering in Argumentative Discourse Extending the Pragma dialectical Theory of Argumentation John Benjamins p 203 ISBN 978 9027211194 Bedau Mark 2009 The ethics of protocells Boston Massachusetts London England Mit Press pp 341 ISBN 978 0 262 01262 1 Goodwin Jean McKerrow Raymie 2011 Accounting for the force of the appeal to authority OSSA Conference Archive Hansen Vilhem 1998 Locke and Whately on the Argumentum ad Ignorantiam Philosophy amp Rhetoric Vol 31 No 1 Vol 31 Penn State University Press p 60 JSTOR 40237981 Locke thought no better or worse of the ad ignorantiam than he did of ad verecundiam or ad hominem At the end of his discussion of the ad hominem as a fallacy Whately says The same observations will apply to argumentum ad verecundiam and the rest 1853 3 1 If we use this analysis of the ad hominem as a model for how Whately thought of the other ad arguments then the ad verecundiam will be an argument with premises that say that amazing authority or some venerable institution and a conclusion claiming that the one to whom the ad verecundiam is addressed ought to accept the conclusion in question on pain of being at odds with those commitments Similarly an ad populum argument will be one that includes among its premises the claim that such and such is a widely held opinion or commitment of the multitude and the conclusion will be that the person to whom the argument is directed is bound to accept a logical consequence of the commitments invoked a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a journal ignored help a b Williamson Owen Master List of Logical Fallacies The University of Texas at El Paso Goodwin Jean May 1998 Forms of Authority and the Real Ad Verecundiam Argumentation 12 2 267 280 via Springer Science Business Media a b c d Garrett Aaron 2014 The Routledge Companion to Eighteenth Century Philosophy Routledge p 280 ISBN 9781317807926 demonstrations proceed deductively while probable reasoning involves inductive inferences a b McBride Michael Retrospective Scientific Evaluation Yale University Archived from the original on 2010 07 24 Retrieved 2017 08 10 a b c Zinser Otto 1984 Basic Principles of Experimental Psychology McGraw Hill p 37 ISBN 9780070728455 a b Stephen Leslie 1882 The Science of Ethics G P Putnam s sons p viii Ruggiero Tim Logical Fallacies Bennett Bo Appeal to the Common Man Logically Fallacious Curtis Gary N Misleading Appeal to Authority The Fallacy Files Retrieved 2021 07 08 Argument from False Authority Logically Fallcious a b Fallacies University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill Lewinski Marcin 2008 Comments on Black box arguments Argumentation 22 3 447 451 doi 10 1007 s10503 008 9095 x Eemeren Frans 2010 Strategic Maneuvering in Argumentative Discourse Extending the Pragma dialectical Theory of Argumentation John Benjamins p 203 ISBN 978 9027211194 a b Sismondo Sergio 1999 Scepticism and Authority in Popular Science review Queen s Quarterly Kingston Vol 106 Iss 1 Spring 1999 p106 a b Sagan Carl July 6 2011 The Demon Haunted World Science as a Candle in the Dark Ballantine Books ISBN 9780307801043 Stevenson I 1990 Some of My Journeys in Medicine PDF The University of Southwestern Louisiana p 18 Quick James Campbell Little Laura M Cooper Cary L Gibbs Philip C Nelson Debra 2010 Organizational Behavior International Review of Industrial and Organizational Psychology 278 Painter Theophilus S April 1923 Studies in mammalian spermatogenesis II The spermatogenesis of man Journal of Experimental Zoology 37 3 291 336 doi 10 1002 jez 1400370303 a b c Glass Bentley 1990 Theophilus Shickel Painter PDF Washington DC National Academy of Sciences pp 316 17 a b Mertens Thomas October 1979 The Role of Factual Knowledge in Biology Teaching The American Biology Teacher 41 7 395 419 doi 10 2307 4446671 JSTOR 4446671 Tjio Joe Hin Levan Albert May 1956 The Chromosome Number of Man Hereditas 42 1 2 723 4 doi 10 1111 j 1601 5223 1956 tb03010 x PMID 345813 O Connor Clare 2008 Human Chromosome Number Nature retrieved April 24 2014 Gartler Stanley 2006 The Chromosome Number in Humans A Brief History Nature Reviews Genetics 7 8 655 60 doi 10 1038 nrg1917 PMID 16847465 S2CID 21365693 a b c Orrell David PhD 2008 The Future of Everything The Science of Prediction pp 184 85 a b Kevles Daniel J 1985 Human Chromosomes Down s Disorder and the Binder s Mistakes PDF Engineering and Science 9 T C Hsu 1979 Out of the Dark Ages Human and Mammalian Cytogenetics An Historical Perspective PDF Cell 18 4 1375 1376 doi 10 1016 0092 8674 79 90249 6 S2CID 54330665 Unger Lawrence Blystone Robert 1996 Paradigm Lost The Human Chromosome Story PDF Bioscene Archived from the original PDF on 2006 09 05 Retrieved 2016 03 24 Sammut Gordon Bauer Martin W 2011 Social Influence Modes and Modalities The Social Psychology of Communication PDF pp 87 106 doi 10 1057 9780230297616 5 ISBN 978 0 230 24736 9 Delameter Andrew 2017 Contrasting Scientific amp Non Scientific Approaches to Acquiring Knowledge City University of New York Sheldon Brian Macdonald Geraldine 2010 A Textbook of Social Work Routledge p 40 ISBN 9781135282615 Bates Jordan 16 March 2016 12 Psychological Tactics Donald Trump Uses to Manipulate the Masses 11 Appeals to Authority McLeod Samuel 2008 Asch Experiment Simply Psychology Webley Paul A partial and non evaluative history of the Asch effect University of Exeter a b Milgram S 1965 Some conditions of obedience and disobedience to authority Human Relations 18 1 57 76 doi 10 1177 001872676501800105 S2CID 37505499 December 2014 Page 2 Disrupted Physician 22 December 2014 Definition of GROUPTHINK 2017 Merriam webster com Retrieved from https www merriam webster com dictionary groupthink Rossi Stacey 2006 Examination of Exclusion Rates in Massachusetts Public Schools PDF a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint numeric names authors list link David Phillip J Hersh Reuben 1998 New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics PDF Princeton University Press p 8 Archived from the original PDF on 2016 03 04 Lookwin B 2015 Biopharma Training Archived from the original on 2017 09 12 Retrieved 2017 09 12 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint numeric names authors list link Janis Irving L 1971 Groupthink PDF Psychology Today Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Argument from authority amp oldid 1217328434, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.