fbpx
Wikipedia

Pragmaticism

"Pragmaticism" is a term used by Charles Sanders Peirce for his pragmatic philosophy starting in 1905, in order to distance himself and it from pragmatism, the original name, which had been used in a manner he did not approve of in the "literary journals". Peirce in 1905 announced his coinage "pragmaticism", saying that it was "ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers" (Collected Papers (CP) 5.414). Today, outside of philosophy, "pragmatism" is often taken to refer to a compromise of aims or principles, even a ruthless search for mercenary advantage. Peirce gave other or more specific reasons for the distinction in a surviving draft letter that year and in later writings. Peirce's pragmatism, that is, pragmaticism, differed in Peirce's view from other pragmatisms by its commitments to the spirit of strict logic, the immutability of truth, the reality of infinity, and the difference between (1) actively willing to control thought, to doubt, to weigh reasons, and (2) willing not to exert the will, willing to believe.[1] In his view his pragmatism is, strictly speaking, not itself a whole philosophy, but instead a general method for the clarification of ideas. He first publicly formulated his pragmatism as an aspect of scientific logic along with principles of statistics and modes of inference in his "Illustrations of the Logic of Science" series of articles in 1877-8.

Pragmatic maxim

Whether one chooses to call it "pragmatism" or "pragmaticism"—and Peirce himself was not always consistent about it even after the notorious renaming—his conception of pragmatic philosophy is based on one or another version of the so-called "pragmatic maxim". Here is one of his more emphatic statements of it:

Pragmaticism was originally enounced in the form of a maxim, as follows: Consider what effects, that might conceivably have practical bearings, you conceive the objects of your conception to have. Then, your conception of those effects is the whole of your conception of the object (CP 5.438).[2]

In the 1909 Century Dictionary Supplement, the entry for pragmaticism by John Dewey[3] was

pragmaticism (prag-mat′i-sizm), n. [pragmatic + ism.] A special and limited form of pragmatism, in which the pragmatism is restricted to the determining of the meaning of concepts (particularly of philosophic concepts) by consideration of the experimental differences in the conduct of life which would conceivably result from the affirmation or denial of the meaning in question.

He [the writer] framed the theory that a conception, that is, the rational purport of a word or other expression, lies exclusively in its conceivable bearing upon the conduct of life. . . . To serve the precise purpose of expressing the original definition, he begs to announce the birth of the word "pragmaticism."      C. S. Peirce, in The Monist, April, 1905, p. 166.

Pragmatism's origin

Pragmatism as a philosophical movement originated in 1872 in discussions in The Metaphysical Club among Peirce, William James, Chauncey Wright, John Fiske, Francis Ellingwood Abbot, and lawyers Nicholas St. John Green and Joseph Bangs Warner (1848-1923). The first use in print of the name pragmatism appears to have been in 1898 by James, who credited Peirce with having coined the name during the early 1870s.[4]

James, among others, regarded Peirce's 1877-8 "Illustrations of the Logic of Science" series, especially "How to Make Our Ideas Clear" (1878) as pragmatism's foundation.[5] Peirce (CP 5.11-12), like James[6] saw pragmatism as embodying familiar attitudes, in philosophy and elsewhere, elaborated into a new deliberate method of thinking and resolving dilemmas. Peirce differed from James and the early John Dewey, in some of their tangential enthusiasms, in being decidedly more rationalistic and realistic, in several senses of those terms, throughout the preponderance of his own philosophical moods.

In a 1906 manuscript,[7] Peirce wrote that, in the Metaphysical Club decades earlier, Nicholas St. John Green

often urged the importance of applying Bain's definition of belief, as "that upon which a man is prepared to act." From this definition, pragmatism is scarce more than a corollary; so that I am disposed to think of him as the grandfather of pragmatism.

James and Peirce, inspired by crucial links among belief, conduct, and disposition, agreed with Green. John Shook has said, "Chauncey Wright also deserves considerable credit, for as both Peirce and James recall, it was Wright who demanded a phenomenalist and fallibilist empiricism as a vital alternative to rationalistic speculation."[8]

Pragmatism is regarded as a distinctively American philosophy.[9] As advocated by James, John Dewey, F. C. S. Schiller, George Herbert Mead, and others, it has proved durable and popular. But Peirce did not seize on this fact to enhance his reputation, and even coined the word "pragmaticism" to distinguish his philosophical position.

Clarification of ideas in inquiry

Pragmatism starts with the idea that belief is that upon which one is prepared to act. Peirce's pragmatism is about conceptions of objects. His pragmatism is a method for fruitfully sorting out conceptual confusions caused, for example, by distinctions that make (sometimes needful) formal yet not practical differences. It equates any conception of an object with a conception of that object's effects to a general extent of those conceived effects' conceivable implications for informed practice. Those conceivable practical implications are the conception's meaning. The meaning is the consequent form of conduct or practice that would be implied by accepting the conception as true. Peirce's pragmaticism, in the strict sense, is about the conceptual elucidation of conceptions into such meanings — about how to make our ideas clear. Making them true, in the sense of proving and bearing them out in fruitful practice, goes beyond that. A conception's truth is its correspondence to the real, to that which would be found by investigation taken far enough. A conception's actual confirmation (if it occurs) is neither its meaning nor its truth per se, but an actual upshot.

In "How to Make Our Ideas Clear",[10] Peirce discusses three grades of clearness of conception:

1. Clearness of a conception familiar and readily used even if unanalyzed and undeveloped.
2. Clearness of a conception in virtue of clearness of its definition's parts, in virtue of which logicians called an idea distinct, that is, clarified by analysis of just what elements make the given idea applicable. Elsewhere, echoing Kant, Peirce calls such a definition "nominal" (CP 5.553).
3. Clearness in virtue of clearness of conceivable practical implications of the object's effects as conceived of, such as can lead to fruitful reasoning, especially on difficult problems. Here he introduces that which he later called the pragmatic maxim.

By way of example of how to clarify conceptions, he addressed conceptions about truth and the real as questions of the presuppositions of reasoning in general. To reason is to presuppose (and at least to hope), as a principle of the reasoner's self-regulation, that the truth is independent of our vagaries of opinion and is discoverable. In clearness's second grade (the "nominal" grade), he defines truth as the correspondence of a sign (in particular, a proposition) to its object, and the real as the object (be it a possibility or quality, or an actuality or brute fact, or a necessity or norm or law) to which a true sign corresponds, such that truth and the real are independent of that which you or I or any actual, definite community of inquirers think. After that needful but confined step, next in clearness's third grade (the pragmatic, practice-oriented grade) he defines truth — not as actual consensus, such that to inquire would be to poll the experts — but as that which would be reached, sooner or later but still inevitably, by research taken far enough, such that the real does depend on that ideal final opinion—a dependence to which he appeals in theoretical arguments elsewhere, for instance for the long-run validity of the rule of induction.[11] (Peirce held that one cannot have absolute theoretical assurance of having actually reached the truth, and later said that the confession of inaccuracy and one-sidedness is an essential ingredient of a true abstract statement.[12]) Peirce argues that even to argue against the independence and discoverability of truth and the real is to presuppose that there is, about that very question under argument, a truth with just such independence and discoverability. For more on Peirce's theory of truth, see the Peirce section in Pragmatic theory of truth. Peirce's discussions and definitions of truth have influenced several epistemic truth theorists and been used as foil for deflationary and correspondence theories of truth.

Peirce said that a conception's meaning consists in "all general modes of rational conduct" implied by "acceptance" of the conception—that is, if one were to accept, first of all, the conception as true, then what could one conceive to be consequent general modes of rational conduct by all who accept the conception as true?—the whole of such consequent general modes is the whole meaning. His pragmatism, since a conception is general, does not equate a conception's meaning, its intellectual purport, with any definite set of actual consequences or upshots corroborating or undermining the conception or its worth, nor does it equate its meaning, much less its truth (if it is true), with the conceived or actual benefit or cost of the conception itself, like a meme (or, say, propaganda), outside the perspective of its being true in what it purports. If it is true, its truth is not transitory but instead immutable and independent of actual trends of opinion. His pragmatism also bears no resemblance to "vulgar" pragmatism, which misleadingly connotes a ruthless and Machiavellian search for mercenary or political advantage. Rather, Peirce's pragmatic maxim is the heart of his pragmatism as a method of experimentational mental reflection[13] arriving at conceptions in terms of conceivable confirmatory and disconfirmatory circumstances—a method hospitable to the generation of explanatory hypotheses, and conducive to the employment and improvement of verification[14] to test the truth of putative knowledge.

Peirce's pragmatism, as method and theory of definitions and the clearness of ideas, is a department within his theory of inquiry,[15] which he variously called "Methodeutic" and "Philosophical or Speculative Rhetoric". He applied his pragmatism as a method throughout his work.

Peirce called his pragmatism "the logic of abduction",[16] that is, the logic of inference to explanatory hypotheses. As a method conducive to hypotheses as well as predictions and testing, pragmatism leads beyond the usual duo of foundational alternatives, namely:

His approach is distinct from foundationalism, empiricist or otherwise, as well as from coherentism, by the following three dimensions:

  • Active process of theory generation, with no prior assurance of truth;
  • Subsequent application of the contingent theory in order to clarify its logical and practical implications;
  • Testing and evaluation of the provisional theory's utility for the anticipation of future experience, and that in dual senses of the word: prediction and control. Peirce's appreciation of these three dimensions serves to flesh out a physiognomy of inquiry far more solid than the flatter image of inductive generalization simpliciter, which is merely the relabeling of phenomenological patterns. Peirce's pragmatism was the first time the scientific method was proposed as an epistemology for philosophical questions.

A theory that proves itself more successful than its rivals in predicting and controlling our world is said to be nearer the truth. This is an operational notion of truth employed by scientists.

In "The Fixation of Belief", Peirce characterized inquiry in general not as the pursuit of truth per se but as the struggle to settle disturbances or conflicts of belief, irritating, inhibitory doubts, belief being that on which one is willing to act. That let Peirce frame scientific inquiry not only as a special kind of inquiry in a broader spectrum, but also, like inquiry generally, as based on actual doubts, not mere verbal doubts (such as hyperbolic doubt), which he held to be fruitless, and it let him also frame it, by the same stroke, as requiring that proof rest on propositions free from actual doubt, rather than on ultimate and absolutely indubitable propositions. He outlined four methods, ordered from least to most successful in achieving a secure fixation of belief:

  1. The method of tenacity (policy of sticking to initial belief) — which brings comforts and decisiveness, but leads to trying to ignore contrary information and others' views, as if truth were intrinsically private, not public. The method goes against the social impulse and easily falters since one may well fail to avoid noticing when another's opinion is as good as one's own initial opinion. Its successes can be brilliant but tend to be transitory.
  2. The method of authority — which overcomes disagreements but sometimes brutally. Its successes can be majestic and long-lasting, but it cannot regulate people thoroughly enough to suppress doubts indefinitely, especially when people learn about other societies present and past.
  3. The method of the a priori — which promotes conformity less brutally but fosters opinions as something like tastes, arising in conversation and comparisons of perspectives in terms of "what is agreeable to reason." Thereby it depends on fashion in paradigms and goes in circles over time. It is more intellectual and respectable but, like the first two methods, sustains accidental and capricious beliefs, destining some minds to doubt it.
  4. The method of science — the only one whereby inquiry can, by its own account, go wrong (fallibilism), and purposely tests itself and criticizes, corrects, and improves itself.

Peirce held that, in practical affairs, slow and stumbling ratiocination is often dangerously inferior to instinct and traditional sentiment, and that the scientific method is best suited to theoretical research,[17] which in turn should not be bound to the other methods and to practical ends; reason's "first rule" is that, in order to learn, one must desire to learn and, as a corollary, must not block the way of inquiry.[18] What recommends the scientific method of inquiry above all others is that it is deliberately designed to arrive, eventually, at the ultimately most secure beliefs, upon which the most successful practices can eventually be based. Starting from the idea that people seek not truth per se but instead to subdue irritating, inhibitory doubt, Peirce shows how, through the struggle, some can come to submit to truth, seek as truth the guidance of potential practice correctly to its given goal, and wed themselves to the scientific method.

Pragmaticism's name

 
William James
1842–1910
 

It is sometimes stated that James' and other philosophers' use of the word pragmatism so dismayed Peirce that he renamed his own variant pragmaticism. Susan Haack has disagreed,[19] pointing out the context in which Peirce publicly introduced the latter term in 1905. Haack's excerpt of Peirce begins below at the words "But at present ...," and continues with some ellipses. The fuller excerpt below supports her case further:

[The] word "pragmatism" has gained general recognition in a generalised sense that seems to argue power of growth and vitality. The famed psychologist, James, first took it up, seeing that his "radical empiricism" substantially answered to the writer's definition of pragmatism, albeit with a certain difference in the point of view. Next, the admirably clear and brilliant thinker, Mr. Ferdinand C. S. Schiller, casting about for a more attractive name for the "anthropomorphism" of his Riddle of the Sphinx, lit, in that most remarkable paper of his on Axioms as Postulates, upon the same designation "pragmatism," which in its original sense was in generic agreement with his own doctrine, for which he has since found the more appropriate specification "humanism," while he still retains "pragmatism" in a somewhat wider sense. So far all went happily. But at present, the word begins to be met with occasionally in the literary journals, where it gets abused in the merciless way that words have to expect when they fall into literary clutches. Sometimes the manners of the British have effloresced in scolding at the word as ill-chosen, —ill-chosen, that is, to express some meaning that it was rather designed to exclude. So then, the writer, finding his bantling "pragmatism" so promoted, feels that it is time to kiss his child good-by and relinquish it to its higher destiny; while to serve the precise purpose of expressing the original definition, he begs to announce the birth of the word "pragmaticism", which is ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers.[20]

Then, in a surviving draft letter to Calderoni, dated by the CP editors as circa that same year 1905, Peirce said regarding his above-quoted discussion:

In the April number of the Monist I proposed that the word 'pragmatism' should hereafter be used somewhat loosely to signify affiliation with Schiller, James, Dewey, Royce, and the rest of us, while the particular doctrine which I invented the word to denote, which is your first kind of pragmatism, should be called 'pragmaticism.' The extra syllable will indicate the narrower meaning.[21]

Indeed in the Monist article Peirce had said that the coinage "pragmaticism" was intended "to serve the precise purpose of expressing the original definition". Of course this does not mean that Peirce regarded his fellow pragmatist philosophers as word-kidnappers. To the contrary he had said, regarding James's and Schiller's uses of the word "pragmatism": "So far, all went happily." So it would seem that Peirce intended the coinage "pragmaticism" for two distinguishable purposes: (1) protection from literary journals and word-kidnappers, and (2) reference strictly to his own form of pragmatism, as opposed even to other pragmatisms that had not moved him to the new name. In the letter to Calderoni, Peirce did not reject all significant affiliation with fellow pragmatists, and instead said "the rest of us". Nor did he reject all such affiliation in later discussions.

However, in the following year 1906, in a manuscript "A Sketch of Logical Critics",[22] Peirce wrote:

I have always fathered my pragmaticism (as I have called it since James and Schiller made the word [pragmatism] imply "the will to believe," the mutability of truth, the soundness of Zeno's refutation of motion, and pluralism generally), upon Kant, Berkeley, and Leibniz. ...

(Peirce proceeded to criticize J. S. Mill but acknowledged probable aid from Mill's Examination.)

Then, in 1908, in his article "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God",[1] mentioning both James and the journalist, pragmatist, and literary author Giovanni Papini, Peirce wrote:

In 1871, in a Metaphysical Club in Cambridge, Mass., I used to preach this principle as a sort of logical gospel, representing the unformulated method followed by Berkeley, and in conversation about it I called it "Pragmatism." In December 1877 and January 1878 I set forth the doctrine in the Popular Science Monthly, and the two parts[23] of my essay were printed in French in the Revue Philosophique, volumes vi. and vii. Of course, the doctrine attracted no particular attention, for, as I had remarked in my opening sentence, very few people care for logic. But in 1897 Professor James remodelled the matter, and transmogrified it into a doctrine of philosophy, some parts of which I highly approved, while other and more prominent parts I regarded, and still regard, as opposed to sound logic. About the time Professor Papini discovered, to the delight of the Pragmatist school, that this doctrine was incapable of definition,[24] which would certainly seem to distinguish it from every other doctrine in whatever branch of science, I was coming to the conclusion that my poor little maxim should be called by another name; and accordingly, in April 1905, I renamed it Pragmaticism.

Peirce proceeded in "A Neglected Argument" to express both deep satisfaction and deep dismay with his fellow pragmatists. He singled F. C. S. Schiller out by name and was vague about which among the others he most particularly referred to. Peirce wrote "It seems to me a pity they should allow a philosophy so instinct with life to become infected with seeds of death. ... "

Peirce remained allied with them about:
  • the reality of generals and habits, to be understood, as are hypostatic abstractions, in terms of potential concrete effects even if unactualized;
  • the falsity of necessitarianism;
  • the character of consciousness as only "visceral or other external sensation".
but was dismayed with their "angry hatred of strict logic" and saw seeds of philosophical death in:
  • their view that "truth is mutable";
  • their view that infinity is unreal; and
  • "such confusions of thought as of active willing (willing to control thought, to doubt, and to weigh reasons) with willing not to exert the will (willing to believe)".

There has been some controversy over Peirce's relation to other pragmatists over the years and over the question of what is owed to Peirce, with visible crests in titles such as literary essayist Edward Dahlberg's "Cutpurse Philosopher"[25] about James, in which Dahlberg claimed that Peirce had "tombstone reticences" about making accusations, and Kenneth Laine Ketner's and Walker Percy's A Thief of Peirce,[26] in which Percy described himself as "a thief of Peirce" (page 130). Meanwhile, Schiller, James's wife Alice, and James's son Henry James III believed that James had a habit of overstating his intellectual debts to others such as Peirce.[27]

In another manuscript "A Sketch of Logical Critic" dated by the CP editors as 1911,[28] Peirce discussed one of Zeno's paradoxes, that of Achilles and the Tortoise, in terms of James's and others' difficulties with it. Peirce therein expressed regret at having used a "contemptuous" manner about such difficulties in his 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism (which James had arranged), and said of James, who had died in August 1910: "Nobody has a better right to testify to the morality of his attitude toward his own thoughts than I, who knew and loved him for forty-nine or fifty years. But owing to his almost unexampled incapacity for mathematical thought, combined with intense hatred for logic — probably for its pedantry, its insistence on minute exactitude — the gêne of its barbarous formulations, etc. rendered him an easy victim to Zeno and the Achilles. ... ",[29] called James "about as perfect a lover of truth as it is possible for a man to be. ... "[30] and said: "In speaking, then, of William James as I do, I am saying the most that I could of any man's intellectual morality; and with him this was but one of a whole diadem of virtues."[31]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ a b Peirce (1908), "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God", Hibbert Journal v. 7, CP 6.452-485, EP 2:434-450, and elsewhere. See the discussion of pragmatism toward the end. Depending on the edition, it may appear in Section V or in an "additament" afterward.
  2. ^ See p. 481 in Peirce, C. S. (1905), "Issues of Pragmaticism", The Monist, vol. 15, pp. 481-499, Google Books Eprint, Internet Archive Eprint. Reprinted Collected Papers (CP) v. 5, paragraphs 438-463, see 438, and in Charles S. Peirce: Selected Writings, pp. 203–226.
  3. ^ Peirce had primary responsibility in the Century Dictionary for terms in logic, philosophy and other fields, see B:139. "Pragmatism" and presumably "pragmaticism" were among the words in Peirce's charge in the Century Dictionary – see under "P 2011-10-02 at the Wayback Machine" in the list of words at PEP-UQÀM 2011-07-06 at the Wayback Machine, the Peirce Edition Project's branch at Université du Québec à Montréal (UQÀM), which is working on Writings v. 7: Peirce's work on the Century Dictionary. However, Joseph M. Ransdell reported that PEP-UQÀM's director François Latraverse informed him that John Dewey actually wrote the Supplements definitions of "pragmatic", "pragmatism", etc.
  4. ^ As Brent (B:86) points out, in a letter November 10, 1900 (CP 8:253) to James, Peirce wrote:

    Now, however, I have a particular occasion to write. Baldwin, arrived at J in his dictionary, suddenly calls on me to do the rest of the logic, in the utmost haste, and various questions of terminology come up.
    Who originated the term pragmatism, I or you? Where did it first appear in print? What do you understand by it?

    to which James replied (CP 8:253 footnote 8) on a post card dated November 26, 1900, Widener Library (Cambridge, Massachusetts) VB2a:

    You invented 'pragmatism' for which I gave you full credit in a lecture entitled 'Philosophical conceptions and practical results' of which I sent you 2 (unacknowledged) copies a couple of years ago.

    As Brent also points out (B:88), Peirce — or as Peirce scholars recently say, Dewey (see above) — in the 1909 Century Dictionary Supplement definition of pragmatism (Wikisource), wrote:

    In an article for "The Monist" for 1905, Mr. Peirce says that he "has used it continually in philosophical conversation since, perhaps, the mid-seventies." The term was publicly introduced in print by Professor William James in 1898 in an address upon "Philosophical Conceptions and Practical Realities," in which authorship of the term and of the method is credited to Mr. Peirce.

    James, William (1898), "Philosophical Conceptions and Practical Results", delivered before the Philosophical Union of the University of California at Berkeley, August 26, 1898, and first printed in the University Chronicle 1, September 1898, pp. 287-310. Internet Archive Eprint. On p. 290::

    I refer to Mr. Charles S. Peirce, with whose very existence as a philosopher I dare say many of you are unacquainted. He is one of the most original of contemporary thinkers; and the principle of practicalism or pragmatism, as he called it, when I first heard him enunciate it at Cambridge in the early 70s is the clue or compass by following which I find myself more and more confirmed in believing we may keep our feet upon the proper trail.

    James credited Peirce again the 1901-1902 Gifford Lectures that were published as The Varieties of Religious Experience (p. 444), and then in the 1906 lectures that were published in 1907 as Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, see Lecture 2, fourth paragraph.

  5. ^ See James (1897), Will to Believe (which James dedicated to Peirce), see p. 124 and footnote via Google Books Eprint:

    Indeed, it may be said that if two apparently different definitions of the reality before us should have identical consequences, those two definitions would really be identical definitions, made delusively to appear different merely by the different verbiage in which they are expressed.¹

    ¹ See the admirably original "Illustrations of the Logic of Science," by C. S. Peirce, especially the second paper, "How to make our Thoughts clear," [sic] in the Popular Science Monthly for January, 1878.

    See also James's 1907 Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking, Lecture 2, fourth paragraph.
  6. ^ James, William (1907) Pragmatism: A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking.
  7. ^ Peirce, C. S., "The Founding of Pragmatism", manuscript written 1906, published in The Hound & Horn: A Harvard Miscellany v. II, n. 3, April–June 1929, pp. 282–5, see 283–4, reprinted 1934 as "Historical Affinities and Genesis" in Collected Papers v. 5, paragraphs 11–13, see 12.
  8. ^ Shook, John (undated), "The Metaphysical Club", the Pragmatism Cybrary. Eprint.
  9. ^ Crotty, Michael. (1998). The foundations of social research : meaning and perspective in the research process. London: Sage Publications. ISBN 0-7619-6105-4. OCLC 39076972.
  10. ^ See also "The Logic of Relatives," The Monist, Vol. 7, 1897, pp. 161-217 (via Google Books). Reprinted in CP, v. 3, paragraphs 456-552.
  11. ^ "That the rule of induction will hold good in the long run may be deduced from the principle that reality is only the object of the final opinion to which sufficient investigation would lead", in Peirce, C. S. (1878 April), "The Probability of Induction", p. 718 (Internet Archive Eprint) in Popular Science Monthly, v. 12, pp. 705-18. Reprinted (Chance, Love, and Logic, pp. 82-105), (CP 2.669-93), (Philosophical Writings of Peirce, pp. 174-89), (W 3:290-305), (EP 1:155-69).
  12. ^ Peirce, C. S. (1902), "Logical" in "Truth and Falsity and Error", Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology v. 2, see p. 718. Reprinted CP v. 5, paragraphs 565-566.
  13. ^ Peirce (1902), CP 5.13 note 1
  14. ^ See CP 1.34 Eprint (in "The Spirit of Scholasticism"), where Peirce attributes the success of modern science not so much to a novel interest in verification as to the improvement of verification.
  15. ^ See Joseph Ransdell's comments and his tabular list of titles of Peirce's proposed list of memoirs in 1902 for his Carnegie application, Eprint
  16. ^ Peirce, C.S. (1903), "Pragmatism — The Logic of Abduction", CP v. 5, paragraphs 195-205, especially paragraph 196. Eprint.
  17. ^ "Philosophy and the Conduct of Life", 1898, Lecture 1 of the Cambridge (MA) Conferences Lectures, published CP 1.616-48 in part and in Reasoning and the Logic of Things, Ketner (ed., intro.) and Putnam (intro., comm.), 105-22, reprinted in EP 2:27-41.
  18. ^ Peirce (1899), "F.R.L." [First Rule of Logic], CP v. 1, paragraphs 135-40. Eprint
  19. ^ 1998, Manifesto of a Passionate Moderate, Chicago IL: University of Chicago Press, p. 55
  20. ^ Peirce, on p p. 165-166 in "What Pragmatism Is", The Monist, v. XV, n. 2, April 1905, pp. 161-81, reprinted CP 5.411-37, see 5.414.
  21. ^ Letter to Signor Calderoni (c. 1905), CP 8.205. See under Pragmaticism in the CDPT.
  22. ^ Essential Peirce v. 2, pp. 451-62, see pp. 457-8.
  23. ^ Peirce refers to "The Fixation of Belief" and "How to Make Our Ideas Clear".
  24. ^ See for example "What Pragmatism Is Like", a translation published in October 1907 in Popular Science Monthly v. 71, pp. 351–8. Google Books Eprint. The original Italian: "Introduzione al pragmatismo", Leonardo series 3, anno 5, n. 1, February 1907, pp. 26-37, Google Books Eprint.
  25. ^ In Alms for Oblivion, University of Minnesota Press, 1967.
  26. ^ University Press of Mississippi, 1995.
  27. ^ Myers, Gerald E., William James: His Life and Thought, Yale University Press, 2001. See pp. 491-2.
  28. ^ An excerpt of it appears as "Achilles and the Tortoise" in CP 6.177-84.
  29. ^ From CP 6.182.
  30. ^ From CP 6.183.
  31. ^ From CP 6.184.

References and further reading

  • Peirce, C. S. (1877–1878), "Illustrations of the Logic of Science" (series), Popular Science Monthly vols. 12–13. (Includes "The Fixation of Belief" and "How to Make Our Ideas Clear".)
  • Peirce, C. S.; James, William; Baldwin, James Mark; and Seth, James (1902), "Pragmatic (1) and (2) Pragmatism" in Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology, v. 2, James Mark Baldwin, ed., MacMillan, New York and London, pp. 321–323.
  • Peirce, C. S. (1905), "What Pragmatism Is", The Monist, vol. XV, no. 2, pp. 161–181, The Open Court Publishing Co., Chicago, IL, April 1905, for the Hegeler Institute. Reprinted in Collected Papers (CP) v. 5, paragraphs 411–437 and Charles S. Peirce: Selected Writings 180–202. Arisbe Eprint.
  • Peirce, C. S. (1905), "Issues of Pragmaticism", The Monist, vol. XV, no. 4, pp. 481–499, The Open Court Publishing Co., Chicago, IL, October 1905, for the Hegeler Institute. Reprinted in CP v. 5, paragraphs 438–463 and Charles S. Peirce: Selected Writings 203–226. Google Books (with a few botched pages) Eprint. Internet Archive Eprint.
  • Peirce, C. S. (1906), "Prolegomena To an Apology For Pragmaticism", The Monist, vol. XVI, no. 4, pp. 492–546, The Open Court Publishing Co., Chicago, IL, October 1906, for the Hegeler Institute. Reprinted in CP v. 4, paragraphs 530–572 and Peirce on Signs: Writings on Semiotic 249–252. .
  • Peirce, C. S. (1908), "A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God", published in part, Hibbert Journal vol. 7, pp. 90–112. Reprinted including one or another unpublished part in CP v. 6, paragraphs 452–485, Charles S. Peirce: Selected Writings 358–379, Essential Peirce v. 2, 434–450, and Peirce on Signs: Writings on Semiotic 260–278. .
Peirce collections
Other
  • Apel, Karl-Otto (1981), Charles S. Peirce: From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism, 288 pages, University of Massachusetts Press, hardcover (October 1981) (ISBN 978-0870231773, ISBN 0-87023-177-4), reprinted, Humanities Press Intl (August 1995), paperback (ISBN 978-0391038950, ISBN 0-391-03895-8).
  • Atkin, Albert (2006), "C.S. Peirce's Pragmatism" in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  • Dewey, John (1916), "The Pragmatism of Peirce" in The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods, v. 13, n. 26, December, 709–715. Google Books eprint, but much of p. 714 is missing. Reprinted or adapted in Peirce, C. S., Chance, Love, and Logic: Philosophical Essays, Morris Raphael Cohen, ed., 1923, still in print.
  • Fisch, Max, (1986), Peirce, Semeiotic, and Pragmatism, Ketner, Kenneth Laine, and Kloesel, Christian J. W., eds., Indiana University Press: catalog page, Bloomington, IN, 1986, 480 pages, cloth (ISBN 978-0-253-34317-8, ISBN 0-253-34317-8).
  • Hookway, Christopher (2000, 2003), Truth, Rationality, and Pragmatism: Themes from Peirce, Oxford University Press, USA, 328 pages, hardcover (ISBN 978-0198238362, ISBN 0-19-823836-3), new edition 2003: O.U.P. catalog page, 328 pages, paperback (ISBN 978-0199256587, ISBN 0-19-925658-6).
  • Lane, Robert (2007), "Peirce's Modal Shift: From Set Theory to Pragmaticism", Journal of the History of Philosophy, v. 45, n. 4, Oct. 2007.
  • Misak, Cheryl J. (1991), Truth and the End of Inquiry : A Peircean Account of Truth, Oxford University Press (catalog page), Oxford, UK; 2004 paperback 232 pages (ISBN 978-0-19-927059-0).
  • Nubiola, Jaime (1996), "C. S. Peirce: Pragmatism and Logicism", Philosophia Scientiae I/2, 121-130. Eprint.
  • Shook, John R., and Margolis, Joseph, eds. (2006), A Companion to Pragmatism, Blackwell (now Wiley), Malden, MA, 431 pages, hardcover (ISBN 978-1405116213, ISBN 1-4051-1621-8) .
  • Skagestad, Peter (1981), The Road of Inquiry, Charles Peirce's Pragmatic Realism, Columbia University Press: , New York, NY, 261 pages, cloth (ISBN 0-231-05004-6)

External links

Peirce, including pragmatism
  • Arisbe: The Peirce Gateway, Joseph Ransdell, ed. Over 100 online writings by Peirce as of November 24, 2010, with annotations. 100s of online papers on Peirce. The peirce-l e-forum. Much else.
  • (1998–2003), Donald Cunningham & Jean Umiker-Sebeok, Indiana U.
  • Centro Internacional de Estudos Peirceanos (CIEP) and previously (CeneP), Lucia Santaella et al., Pontifical Catholic U. of São Paulo (PUC-SP), Brazil. In Portuguese, some English.
  • Commens Digital Companion to C.S. Peirce, Mats Bergman, Sami Paavola, & João Queiroz, formerly . Includes Commens Dictionary of Peirce's Terms with Peirce's definitions, often many per term across the decades, and the Digital Encyclopedia of Charles S. Peirce (old edition still at old website).
  • Centro Studi Peirce, Carlo Sini, Rossella Fabbrichesi, et al., U. of Milan, Italy. In Italian and English. Part of Pragma.
  • Charles S. Peirce Foundation. Co-sponsoring the 2014 Peirce International Centennial Congress (100th anniversary of Peirce's death).
  • Charles S. Peirce Society
    . Quarterly journal of Peirce studies since spring 1965. of all issues.
  • Charles S. Peirce Studies, Brian Kariger, ed.
  • Pragmaticism at the Mathematics Genealogy Project
  • Collegium for the Advanced Study of Picture Act and Embodiment: The Peirce Archive. Humboldt U, Berlin, Germany. Cataloguing Peirce's innumerable drawings & graphic materials. (Prof. Aud Sissel Hoel).
  • Digital Encyclopedia of Charles S. Peirce, João Queiroz (now at UFJF) & Ricardo Gudwin (at Unicamp), eds., [[Universidade Estadual de Campinas|U. of Campinas]], Brazil, in English. 84 authors listed, 51 papers online & more listed, as of January 31, 2009. Newer edition now at Commens.
  • , Jay Zeman, ed., U. of Florida. Has 4 Peirce texts.
  • Grupo de Estudios Peirceanos (GEP) / Peirce Studies Group, Jaime Nubiola, ed., U. of Navarra, Spain. Big study site, Peirce & others in Spanish & English, bibliography, more.
  • Helsinki Peirce Research Center (HPRC), Ahti-Veikko Pietarinen et al., U. of Helsinki.
  • His Glassy Essence. Autobiographical Peirce. Kenneth Laine Ketner.
  • Institute for Studies in Pragmaticism, Kenneth Laine Ketner, Clyde Hendrick, et al., Texas Tech U. Peirce's life and works.
  • , Uwe Wirth et al., eds., Goethe U., Frankfurt, Germany. Uses frames. Click on link at bottom of its home page for English. Moved to [[University of Gießen|U. of Gießen]], Germany, not in English but see Artikel section there.
  • (1974–2003)—Institut de Recherche en Sémiotique, Communication et Éducation, Gérard Deledalle, Joëlle Réthoré, U. of Perpignan, France.
  • , Vinicius Romanini, U. of São Paulo, Brazil. English, Portuguese.
  • at Signo: Theoretical Semiotics on the Web, Louis Hébert, director, supported by U. of Québec. Theory, application, exercises of Peirce's and . English, French.
  • Peirce Edition Project (PEP), Indiana U.-Purdue U. Indianapolis (IUPUI). André De Tienne, Nathan Houser, et al. Editors of the Writings of Charles S. Peirce (W) and The Essential Peirce (EP) v. 2. Many study aids such as the Robin Catalog of Peirce's manuscripts & letters and:
    —Biographical introductions to EP 1–2 and W 1–6 & 8
    —Most of W 2 readable online.
    —. Working on W 7: Peirce's work on the Century Dictionary. .
  • Peirce's Existential Graphs, Frithjof Dau, Germany
  • Pragmatism Cybrary, David Hildebrand & John Shook.
  • (late 1990s), Institut für Didaktik der Mathematik (Michael Hoffman, Michael Otte, Universität Bielefeld, Germany). See Peirce Project Newsletter v. 3, n. 1, p. 13.
  • Semiotics according to Robert Marty, with 76 definitions of the sign by C. S. Peirce.
Related pragmatism
  • Associazione Culturale Pragma with
  • International Pragmatism Society. Journal: , Mitchell Aboulafia & John R. Shook, Editors.
  • Nordic Pragmatism Network, Henrik Rydenfelt (U. of Helsinki), coordinator. Journal: Nordic Studies in Pragmatism.
  • Pragmatism Cybrary, David Hildebrand & John R. Shook, Editors.

pragmaticism, term, used, charles, sanders, peirce, pragmatic, philosophy, starting, 1905, order, distance, himself, from, pragmatism, original, name, which, been, used, manner, approve, literary, journals, peirce, 1905, announced, coinage, pragmaticism, sayin. Pragmaticism is a term used by Charles Sanders Peirce for his pragmatic philosophy starting in 1905 in order to distance himself and it from pragmatism the original name which had been used in a manner he did not approve of in the literary journals Peirce in 1905 announced his coinage pragmaticism saying that it was ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers Collected Papers CP 5 414 Today outside of philosophy pragmatism is often taken to refer to a compromise of aims or principles even a ruthless search for mercenary advantage Peirce gave other or more specific reasons for the distinction in a surviving draft letter that year and in later writings Peirce s pragmatism that is pragmaticism differed in Peirce s view from other pragmatisms by its commitments to the spirit of strict logic the immutability of truth the reality of infinity and the difference between 1 actively willing to control thought to doubt to weigh reasons and 2 willing not to exert the will willing to believe 1 In his view his pragmatism is strictly speaking not itself a whole philosophy but instead a general method for the clarification of ideas He first publicly formulated his pragmatism as an aspect of scientific logic along with principles of statistics and modes of inference in his Illustrations of the Logic of Science series of articles in 1877 8 Contents 1 Pragmatic maxim 2 Pragmatism s origin 3 Clarification of ideas in inquiry 4 Pragmaticism s name 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References and further reading 8 External linksPragmatic maxim EditWhether one chooses to call it pragmatism or pragmaticism and Peirce himself was not always consistent about it even after the notorious renaming his conception of pragmatic philosophy is based on one or another version of the so called pragmatic maxim Here is one of his more emphatic statements of it Pragmaticism was originally enounced in the form of a maxim as follows Consider what effects that might conceivably have practical bearings you conceive the objects of your conception to have Then your conception of those effects is the whole of your conception of the object CP 5 438 2 In the 1909 Century Dictionary Supplement the entry for pragmaticism by John Dewey 3 was pragmaticism prag mat i sizm n pragmatic ism A special and limited form of pragmatism in which the pragmatism is restricted to the determining of the meaning of concepts particularly of philosophic concepts by consideration of the experimental differences in the conduct of life which would conceivably result from the affirmation or denial of the meaning in question He the writer framed the theory that a conception that is the rational purport of a word or other expression lies exclusively in its conceivable bearing upon the conduct of life To serve the precise purpose of expressing the original definition he begs to announce the birth of the word pragmaticism C S Peirce in The Monist April 1905 p 166 Pragmatism s origin EditPragmatism as a philosophical movement originated in 1872 in discussions in The Metaphysical Club among Peirce William James Chauncey Wright John Fiske Francis Ellingwood Abbot and lawyers Nicholas St John Green and Joseph Bangs Warner 1848 1923 The first use in print of the name pragmatism appears to have been in 1898 by James who credited Peirce with having coined the name during the early 1870s 4 James among others regarded Peirce s 1877 8 Illustrations of the Logic of Science series especially How to Make Our Ideas Clear 1878 as pragmatism s foundation 5 Peirce CP 5 11 12 like James 6 saw pragmatism as embodying familiar attitudes in philosophy and elsewhere elaborated into a new deliberate method of thinking and resolving dilemmas Peirce differed from James and the early John Dewey in some of their tangential enthusiasms in being decidedly more rationalistic and realistic in several senses of those terms throughout the preponderance of his own philosophical moods In a 1906 manuscript 7 Peirce wrote that in the Metaphysical Club decades earlier Nicholas St John Greenoften urged the importance of applying Bain s definition of belief as that upon which a man is prepared to act From this definition pragmatism is scarce more than a corollary so that I am disposed to think of him as the grandfather of pragmatism James and Peirce inspired by crucial links among belief conduct and disposition agreed with Green John Shook has said Chauncey Wright also deserves considerable credit for as both Peirce and James recall it was Wright who demanded a phenomenalist and fallibilist empiricism as a vital alternative to rationalistic speculation 8 Pragmatism is regarded as a distinctively American philosophy 9 As advocated by James John Dewey F C S Schiller George Herbert Mead and others it has proved durable and popular But Peirce did not seize on this fact to enhance his reputation and even coined the word pragmaticism to distinguish his philosophical position Clarification of ideas in inquiry EditPragmatism starts with the idea that belief is that upon which one is prepared to act Peirce s pragmatism is about conceptions of objects His pragmatism is a method for fruitfully sorting out conceptual confusions caused for example by distinctions that make sometimes needful formal yet not practical differences It equates any conception of an object with a conception of that object s effects to a general extent of those conceived effects conceivable implications for informed practice Those conceivable practical implications are the conception s meaning The meaning is the consequent form of conduct or practice that would be implied by accepting the conception as true Peirce s pragmaticism in the strict sense is about the conceptual elucidation of conceptions into such meanings about how to make our ideas clear Making them true in the sense of proving and bearing them out in fruitful practice goes beyond that A conception s truth is its correspondence to the real to that which would be found by investigation taken far enough A conception s actual confirmation if it occurs is neither its meaning nor its truth per se but an actual upshot In How to Make Our Ideas Clear 10 Peirce discusses three grades of clearness of conception 1 Clearness of a conception familiar and readily used even if unanalyzed and undeveloped 2 Clearness of a conception in virtue of clearness of its definition s parts in virtue of which logicians called an idea distinct that is clarified by analysis of just what elements make the given idea applicable Elsewhere echoing Kant Peirce calls such a definition nominal CP 5 553 3 Clearness in virtue of clearness of conceivable practical implications of the object s effects as conceived of such as can lead to fruitful reasoning especially on difficult problems Here he introduces that which he later called the pragmatic maxim By way of example of how to clarify conceptions he addressed conceptions about truth and the real as questions of the presuppositions of reasoning in general To reason is to presuppose and at least to hope as a principle of the reasoner s self regulation that the truth is independent of our vagaries of opinion and is discoverable In clearness s second grade the nominal grade he defines truth as the correspondence of a sign in particular a proposition to its object and the real as the object be it a possibility or quality or an actuality or brute fact or a necessity or norm or law to which a true sign corresponds such that truth and the real are independent of that which you or I or any actual definite community of inquirers think After that needful but confined step next in clearness s third grade the pragmatic practice oriented grade he defines truth not as actual consensus such that to inquire would be to poll the experts but as that which would be reached sooner or later but still inevitably by research taken far enough such that the real does depend on that ideal final opinion a dependence to which he appeals in theoretical arguments elsewhere for instance for the long run validity of the rule of induction 11 Peirce held that one cannot have absolute theoretical assurance of having actually reached the truth and later said that the confession of inaccuracy and one sidedness is an essential ingredient of a true abstract statement 12 Peirce argues that even to argue against the independence and discoverability of truth and the real is to presuppose that there is about that very question under argument a truth with just such independence and discoverability For more on Peirce s theory of truth see the Peirce section in Pragmatic theory of truth Peirce s discussions and definitions of truth have influenced several epistemic truth theorists and been used as foil for deflationary and correspondence theories of truth Peirce said that a conception s meaning consists in all general modes of rational conduct implied by acceptance of the conception that is if one were to accept first of all the conception as true then what could one conceive to be consequent general modes of rational conduct by all who accept the conception as true the whole of such consequent general modes is the whole meaning His pragmatism since a conception is general does not equate a conception s meaning its intellectual purport with any definite set of actual consequences or upshots corroborating or undermining the conception or its worth nor does it equate its meaning much less its truth if it is true with the conceived or actual benefit or cost of the conception itself like a meme or say propaganda outside the perspective of its being true in what it purports If it is true its truth is not transitory but instead immutable and independent of actual trends of opinion His pragmatism also bears no resemblance to vulgar pragmatism which misleadingly connotes a ruthless and Machiavellian search for mercenary or political advantage Rather Peirce s pragmatic maxim is the heart of his pragmatism as a method of experimentational mental reflection 13 arriving at conceptions in terms of conceivable confirmatory and disconfirmatory circumstances a method hospitable to the generation of explanatory hypotheses and conducive to the employment and improvement of verification 14 to test the truth of putative knowledge Peirce s pragmatism as method and theory of definitions and the clearness of ideas is a department within his theory of inquiry 15 which he variously called Methodeutic and Philosophical or Speculative Rhetoric He applied his pragmatism as a method throughout his work Peirce called his pragmatism the logic of abduction 16 that is the logic of inference to explanatory hypotheses As a method conducive to hypotheses as well as predictions and testing pragmatism leads beyond the usual duo of foundational alternatives namely Deduction from self evident truths or rationalism Induction from experiential phenomena or empiricism His approach is distinct from foundationalism empiricist or otherwise as well as from coherentism by the following three dimensions Active process of theory generation with no prior assurance of truth Subsequent application of the contingent theory in order to clarify its logical and practical implications Testing and evaluation of the provisional theory s utility for the anticipation of future experience and that in dual senses of the word prediction and control Peirce s appreciation of these three dimensions serves to flesh out a physiognomy of inquiry far more solid than the flatter image of inductive generalization simpliciter which is merely the relabeling of phenomenological patterns Peirce s pragmatism was the first time the scientific method was proposed as an epistemology for philosophical questions A theory that proves itself more successful than its rivals in predicting and controlling our world is said to be nearer the truth This is an operational notion of truth employed by scientists In The Fixation of Belief Peirce characterized inquiry in general not as the pursuit of truth per se but as the struggle to settle disturbances or conflicts of belief irritating inhibitory doubts belief being that on which one is willing to act That let Peirce frame scientific inquiry not only as a special kind of inquiry in a broader spectrum but also like inquiry generally as based on actual doubts not mere verbal doubts such as hyperbolic doubt which he held to be fruitless and it let him also frame it by the same stroke as requiring that proof rest on propositions free from actual doubt rather than on ultimate and absolutely indubitable propositions He outlined four methods ordered from least to most successful in achieving a secure fixation of belief The method of tenacity policy of sticking to initial belief which brings comforts and decisiveness but leads to trying to ignore contrary information and others views as if truth were intrinsically private not public The method goes against the social impulse and easily falters since one may well fail to avoid noticing when another s opinion is as good as one s own initial opinion Its successes can be brilliant but tend to be transitory The method of authority which overcomes disagreements but sometimes brutally Its successes can be majestic and long lasting but it cannot regulate people thoroughly enough to suppress doubts indefinitely especially when people learn about other societies present and past The method of the a priori which promotes conformity less brutally but fosters opinions as something like tastes arising in conversation and comparisons of perspectives in terms of what is agreeable to reason Thereby it depends on fashion in paradigms and goes in circles over time It is more intellectual and respectable but like the first two methods sustains accidental and capricious beliefs destining some minds to doubt it The method of science the only one whereby inquiry can by its own account go wrong fallibilism and purposely tests itself and criticizes corrects and improves itself Peirce held that in practical affairs slow and stumbling ratiocination is often dangerously inferior to instinct and traditional sentiment and that the scientific method is best suited to theoretical research 17 which in turn should not be bound to the other methods and to practical ends reason s first rule is that in order to learn one must desire to learn and as a corollary must not block the way of inquiry 18 What recommends the scientific method of inquiry above all others is that it is deliberately designed to arrive eventually at the ultimately most secure beliefs upon which the most successful practices can eventually be based Starting from the idea that people seek not truth per se but instead to subdue irritating inhibitory doubt Peirce shows how through the struggle some can come to submit to truth seek as truth the guidance of potential practice correctly to its given goal and wed themselves to the scientific method Pragmaticism s name Edit William James1842 1910 F C S Schiller1863 1937It is sometimes stated that James and other philosophers use of the word pragmatism so dismayed Peirce that he renamed his own variant pragmaticism Susan Haack has disagreed 19 pointing out the context in which Peirce publicly introduced the latter term in 1905 Haack s excerpt of Peirce begins below at the words But at present and continues with some ellipses The fuller excerpt below supports her case further The word pragmatism has gained general recognition in a generalised sense that seems to argue power of growth and vitality The famed psychologist James first took it up seeing that his radical empiricism substantially answered to the writer s definition of pragmatism albeit with a certain difference in the point of view Next the admirably clear and brilliant thinker Mr Ferdinand C S Schiller casting about for a more attractive name for the anthropomorphism of his Riddle of the Sphinx lit in that most remarkable paper of his on Axioms as Postulates upon the same designation pragmatism which in its original sense was in generic agreement with his own doctrine for which he has since found the more appropriate specification humanism while he still retains pragmatism in a somewhat wider sense So far all went happily But at present the word begins to be met with occasionally in the literary journals where it gets abused in the merciless way that words have to expect when they fall into literary clutches Sometimes the manners of the British have effloresced in scolding at the word as ill chosen ill chosen that is to express some meaning that it was rather designed to exclude So then the writer finding his bantling pragmatism so promoted feels that it is time to kiss his child good by and relinquish it to its higher destiny while to serve the precise purpose of expressing the original definition he begs to announce the birth of the word pragmaticism which is ugly enough to be safe from kidnappers 20 Then in a surviving draft letter to Calderoni dated by the CP editors as circa that same year 1905 Peirce said regarding his above quoted discussion In the April number of the Monist I proposed that the word pragmatism should hereafter be used somewhat loosely to signify affiliation with Schiller James Dewey Royce and the rest of us while the particular doctrine which I invented the word to denote which is your first kind of pragmatism should be called pragmaticism The extra syllable will indicate the narrower meaning 21 Indeed in the Monist article Peirce had said that the coinage pragmaticism was intended to serve the precise purpose of expressing the original definition Of course this does not mean that Peirce regarded his fellow pragmatist philosophers as word kidnappers To the contrary he had said regarding James s and Schiller s uses of the word pragmatism So far all went happily So it would seem that Peirce intended the coinage pragmaticism for two distinguishable purposes 1 protection from literary journals and word kidnappers and 2 reference strictly to his own form of pragmatism as opposed even to other pragmatisms that had not moved him to the new name In the letter to Calderoni Peirce did not reject all significant affiliation with fellow pragmatists and instead said the rest of us Nor did he reject all such affiliation in later discussions However in the following year 1906 in a manuscript A Sketch of Logical Critics 22 Peirce wrote I have always fathered my pragmaticism as I have called it since James and Schiller made the word pragmatism imply the will to believe the mutability of truth the soundness of Zeno s refutation of motion and pluralism generally upon Kant Berkeley and Leibniz Peirce proceeded to criticize J S Mill but acknowledged probable aid from Mill s Examination Then in 1908 in his article A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God 1 mentioning both James and the journalist pragmatist and literary author Giovanni Papini Peirce wrote In 1871 in a Metaphysical Club in Cambridge Mass I used to preach this principle as a sort of logical gospel representing the unformulated method followed by Berkeley and in conversation about it I called it Pragmatism In December 1877 and January 1878 I set forth the doctrine in the Popular Science Monthly and the two parts 23 of my essay were printed in French in the Revue Philosophique volumes vi and vii Of course the doctrine attracted no particular attention for as I had remarked in my opening sentence very few people care for logic But in 1897 Professor James remodelled the matter and transmogrified it into a doctrine of philosophy some parts of which I highly approved while other and more prominent parts I regarded and still regard as opposed to sound logic About the time Professor Papini discovered to the delight of the Pragmatist school that this doctrine was incapable of definition 24 which would certainly seem to distinguish it from every other doctrine in whatever branch of science I was coming to the conclusion that my poor little maxim should be called by another name and accordingly in April 1905 I renamed it Pragmaticism Peirce proceeded in A Neglected Argument to express both deep satisfaction and deep dismay with his fellow pragmatists He singled F C S Schiller out by name and was vague about which among the others he most particularly referred to Peirce wrote It seems to me a pity they should allow a philosophy so instinct with life to become infected with seeds of death Peirce remained allied with them about the reality of generals and habits to be understood as are hypostatic abstractions in terms of potential concrete effects even if unactualized the falsity of necessitarianism the character of consciousness as only visceral or other external sensation but was dismayed with their angry hatred of strict logic and saw seeds of philosophical death in their view that truth is mutable their view that infinity is unreal and such confusions of thought as of active willing willing to control thought to doubt and to weigh reasons with willing not to exert the will willing to believe There has been some controversy over Peirce s relation to other pragmatists over the years and over the question of what is owed to Peirce with visible crests in titles such as literary essayist Edward Dahlberg s Cutpurse Philosopher 25 about James in which Dahlberg claimed that Peirce had tombstone reticences about making accusations and Kenneth Laine Ketner s and Walker Percy s A Thief of Peirce 26 in which Percy described himself as a thief of Peirce page 130 Meanwhile Schiller James s wife Alice and James s son Henry James III believed that James had a habit of overstating his intellectual debts to others such as Peirce 27 In another manuscript A Sketch of Logical Critic dated by the CP editors as 1911 28 Peirce discussed one of Zeno s paradoxes that of Achilles and the Tortoise in terms of James s and others difficulties with it Peirce therein expressed regret at having used a contemptuous manner about such difficulties in his 1903 Harvard lectures on pragmatism which James had arranged and said of James who had died in August 1910 Nobody has a better right to testify to the morality of his attitude toward his own thoughts than I who knew and loved him for forty nine or fifty years But owing to his almost unexampled incapacity for mathematical thought combined with intense hatred for logic probably for its pedantry its insistence on minute exactitude the gene of its barbarous formulations etc rendered him an easy victim to Zeno and the Achilles 29 called James about as perfect a lover of truth as it is possible for a man to be 30 and said In speaking then of William James as I do I am saying the most that I could of any man s intellectual morality and with him this was but one of a whole diadem of virtues 31 See also EditCharles Sanders Peirce bibliography Entitative graph Existential graph Hypostatic abstraction Inquiry Logical graph Philosophy of mathematics Philosophy of science Pragmatic maxim Pragmatic theory of truth Scientific method Semeiotic Sign relation Truth theoryNotes Edit a b Peirce 1908 A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God Hibbert Journal v 7 CP 6 452 485 EP 2 434 450 and elsewhere See the discussion of pragmatism toward the end Depending on the edition it may appear in Section V or in an additament afterward See p 481 in Peirce C S 1905 Issues of Pragmaticism The Monist vol 15 pp 481 499 Google Books Eprint Internet Archive Eprint Reprinted Collected Papers CP v 5 paragraphs 438 463 see 438 and in Charles S Peirce Selected Writings pp 203 226 Peirce had primary responsibility in the Century Dictionary for terms in logic philosophy and other fields see B 139 Pragmatism and presumably pragmaticism were among the words in Peirce s charge in the Century Dictionary see under P Archived 2011 10 02 at the Wayback Machine in the list of words at PEP UQAM Archived 2011 07 06 at the Wayback Machine the Peirce Edition Project s branch at Universite du Quebec a Montreal UQAM which is working on Writings v 7 Peirce s work on the Century Dictionary However Joseph M Ransdell reported that PEP UQAM s director Francois Latraverse informed him that John Dewey actually wrote the Supplements definitions of pragmatic pragmatism etc As Brent B 86 points out in a letter November 10 1900 CP 8 253 to James Peirce wrote Now however I have a particular occasion to write Baldwin arrived at J in his dictionary suddenly calls on me to do the rest of the logic in the utmost haste and various questions of terminology come up Who originated the term pragmatism I or you Where did it first appear in print What do you understand by it to which James replied CP 8 253 footnote 8 on a post card dated November 26 1900 Widener Library Cambridge Massachusetts VB2a You invented pragmatism for which I gave you full credit in a lecture entitled Philosophical conceptions and practical results of which I sent you 2 unacknowledged copies a couple of years ago As Brent also points out B 88 Peirce or as Peirce scholars recently say Dewey see above in the 1909 Century Dictionary Supplement definition of pragmatism Wikisource wrote In an article for The Monist for 1905 Mr Peirce says that he has used it continually in philosophical conversation since perhaps the mid seventies The term was publicly introduced in print by Professor William James in 1898 in an address upon Philosophical Conceptions and Practical Realities in which authorship of the term and of the method is credited to Mr Peirce James William 1898 Philosophical Conceptions and Practical Results delivered before the Philosophical Union of the University of California at Berkeley August 26 1898 and first printed in the University Chronicle 1 September 1898 pp 287 310 Internet Archive Eprint On p 290 I refer to Mr Charles S Peirce with whose very existence as a philosopher I dare say many of you are unacquainted He is one of the most original of contemporary thinkers and the principle of practicalism or pragmatism as he called it when I first heard him enunciate it at Cambridge in the early 70s is the clue or compass by following which I find myself more and more confirmed in believing we may keep our feet upon the proper trail James credited Peirce again the 1901 1902 Gifford Lectures that were published as The Varieties of Religious Experience p 444 and then in the 1906 lectures that were published in 1907 as Pragmatism A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking see Lecture 2 fourth paragraph See James 1897 Will to Believe which James dedicated to Peirce see p 124 and footnote via Google Books Eprint Indeed it may be said that if two apparently different definitions of the reality before us should have identical consequences those two definitions would really be identical definitions made delusively to appear different merely by the different verbiage in which they are expressed See the admirably original Illustrations of the Logic of Science by C S Peirce especially the second paper How to make our Thoughts clear sic in the Popular Science Monthly for January 1878 See also James s 1907 Pragmatism A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking Lecture 2 fourth paragraph James William 1907 Pragmatism A New Name for Some Old Ways of Thinking Peirce C S The Founding of Pragmatism manuscript written 1906 published in The Hound amp Horn A Harvard Miscellany v II n 3 April June 1929 pp 282 5 see 283 4 reprinted 1934 as Historical Affinities and Genesis in Collected Papers v 5 paragraphs 11 13 see 12 Shook John undated The Metaphysical Club the Pragmatism Cybrary Eprint Crotty Michael 1998 The foundations of social research meaning and perspective in the research process London Sage Publications ISBN 0 7619 6105 4 OCLC 39076972 See also The Logic of Relatives The Monist Vol 7 1897 pp 161 217 via Google Books Reprinted in CP v 3 paragraphs 456 552 That the rule of induction will hold good in the long run may be deduced from the principle that reality is only the object of the final opinion to which sufficient investigation would lead in Peirce C S 1878 April The Probability of Induction p 718 Internet Archive Eprint in Popular Science Monthly v 12 pp 705 18 Reprinted Chance Love and Logic pp 82 105 CP 2 669 93 Philosophical Writings of Peirce pp 174 89 W 3 290 305 EP 1 155 69 Peirce C S 1902 Logical in Truth and Falsity and Error Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology v 2 see p 718 Reprinted CP v 5 paragraphs 565 566 Peirce 1902 CP 5 13 note 1 See CP 1 34 Eprint in The Spirit of Scholasticism where Peirce attributes the success of modern science not so much to a novel interest in verification as to the improvement of verification See Joseph Ransdell s comments and his tabular list of titles of Peirce s proposed list of memoirs in 1902 for his Carnegie application Eprint Peirce C S 1903 Pragmatism The Logic of Abduction CP v 5 paragraphs 195 205 especially paragraph 196 Eprint Philosophy and the Conduct of Life 1898 Lecture 1 of the Cambridge MA Conferences Lectures published CP 1 616 48 in part and in Reasoning and the Logic of Things Ketner ed intro and Putnam intro comm 105 22 reprinted in EP 2 27 41 Peirce 1899 F R L First Rule of Logic CP v 1 paragraphs 135 40 Eprint 1998 Manifesto of a Passionate Moderate Chicago IL University of Chicago Press p 55 Peirce on p p 165 166 in What Pragmatism Is The Monist v XV n 2 April 1905 pp 161 81 reprinted CP 5 411 37 see 5 414 Letter to Signor Calderoni c 1905 CP 8 205 See under Pragmaticism in the CDPT Essential Peirce v 2 pp 451 62 see pp 457 8 Peirce refers to The Fixation of Belief and How to Make Our Ideas Clear See for example What Pragmatism Is Like a translation published in October 1907 in Popular Science Monthly v 71 pp 351 8 Google Books Eprint The original Italian Introduzione al pragmatismo Leonardo series 3 anno 5 n 1 February 1907 pp 26 37 Google Books Eprint In Alms for Oblivion University of Minnesota Press 1967 University Press of Mississippi 1995 Myers Gerald E William James His Life and Thought Yale University Press 2001 See pp 491 2 An excerpt of it appears as Achilles and the Tortoise in CP 6 177 84 From CP 6 182 From CP 6 183 From CP 6 184 References and further reading EditPeirce C S 1877 1878 Illustrations of the Logic of Science series Popular Science Monthly vols 12 13 Includes The Fixation of Belief and How to Make Our Ideas Clear Peirce C S James William Baldwin James Mark and Seth James 1902 Pragmatic 1 and 2 Pragmatism in Dictionary of Philosophy and Psychology v 2 James Mark Baldwin ed MacMillan New York and London pp 321 323 Peirce C S 1905 What Pragmatism Is The Monist vol XV no 2 pp 161 181 The Open Court Publishing Co Chicago IL April 1905 for the Hegeler Institute Reprinted in Collected Papers CP v 5 paragraphs 411 437 and Charles S Peirce Selected Writings 180 202 Arisbe Eprint Peirce C S 1905 Issues of Pragmaticism The Monist vol XV no 4 pp 481 499 The Open Court Publishing Co Chicago IL October 1905 for the Hegeler Institute Reprinted in CP v 5 paragraphs 438 463 and Charles S Peirce Selected Writings 203 226 Google Books with a few botched pages Eprint Internet Archive Eprint Peirce C S 1906 Prolegomena To an Apology For Pragmaticism The Monist vol XVI no 4 pp 492 546 The Open Court Publishing Co Chicago IL October 1906 for the Hegeler Institute Reprinted in CP v 4 paragraphs 530 572 and Peirce on Signs Writings on Semiotic 249 252 Eprint Peirce C S 1908 A Neglected Argument for the Reality of God published in part Hibbert Journal vol 7 pp 90 112 Reprinted including one or another unpublished part in CP v 6 paragraphs 452 485 Charles S Peirce Selected Writings 358 379 Essential Peirce v 2 434 450 and Peirce on Signs Writings on Semiotic 260 278 Eprint Peirce collectionsPeirce C S 1931 35 1958 Collected Papers of Charles Sanders Peirce vols 1 6 1931 35 Charles Hartshorne and Paul Weiss eds vols 7 8 1958 Arthur W Burks ed Harvard University Press Cambridge Massachusetts In print from HUP permanent dead link and online via InteLex Peirce C S 1976 The New Elements of Mathematics by Charles S Peirce 4 volumes in 5 Carolyn Eisele ed Mouton Publishers The Hague Netherlands 1976 Humanities Press Atlantic Highlands New Jersey Out of print Peirce C S 1981 Writings of Charles S Peirce A Chronological Edition vols 1 6 amp 8 of a projected 30 Peirce Edition Project eds Indiana University Press Bloomington and Indianapolis Indiana In print from IUP permanent dead link and online first six volumes via InteLex Peirce C S 1992 Pragmatism as a Principle and Method of Right Thinking The 1903 Harvard Lectures on Pragmatism Patricia Ann Turisi ed State University of New York Press Albany NY 1997 In print from SUNY A study edition of Peirce s lecture manuscripts including unused drafts which had been previously published in abridged form Peirce C S 1992 1998 The Essential Peirce Selected Philosophical Writings Volume 1 1867 1893 1992 Nathan Houser and Christian Kloesel eds and Volume 2 1893 1913 including the 1903 lectures on pragmatism 1998 Peirce Edition Project eds Bloomington and Indianapolis Indiana Indiana University Press In print from IUP OtherApel Karl Otto 1981 Charles S Peirce From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism 288 pages University of Massachusetts Press hardcover October 1981 ISBN 978 0870231773 ISBN 0 87023 177 4 reprinted Humanities Press Intl August 1995 paperback ISBN 978 0391038950 ISBN 0 391 03895 8 Atkin Albert 2006 C S Peirce s Pragmatism in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Eprint Dewey John 1916 The Pragmatism of Peirce in The Journal of Philosophy Psychology and Scientific Methods v 13 n 26 December 709 715 Google Books eprint but much of p 714 is missing Reprinted or adapted in Peirce C S Chance Love and Logic Philosophical Essays Morris Raphael Cohen ed 1923 still in print Fisch Max 1986 Peirce Semeiotic and Pragmatism Ketner Kenneth Laine and Kloesel Christian J W eds Indiana University Press catalog page Bloomington IN 1986 480 pages cloth ISBN 978 0 253 34317 8 ISBN 0 253 34317 8 Hookway Christopher 2000 2003 Truth Rationality and Pragmatism Themes from Peirce Oxford University Press USA 328 pages hardcover ISBN 978 0198238362 ISBN 0 19 823836 3 new edition 2003 O U P catalog page 328 pages paperback ISBN 978 0199256587 ISBN 0 19 925658 6 Lane Robert 2007 Peirce s Modal Shift From Set Theory to Pragmaticism Journal of the History of Philosophy v 45 n 4 Oct 2007 Misak Cheryl J 1991 Truth and the End of Inquiry A Peircean Account of Truth Oxford University Press catalog page Oxford UK 2004 paperback 232 pages ISBN 978 0 19 927059 0 Nubiola Jaime 1996 C S Peirce Pragmatism and Logicism Philosophia Scientiae I 2 121 130 Eprint Shook John R and Margolis Joseph eds 2006 A Companion to Pragmatism Blackwell now Wiley Malden MA 431 pages hardcover ISBN 978 1405116213 ISBN 1 4051 1621 8 Blackwell catalog page Skagestad Peter 1981 The Road of Inquiry Charles Peirce s Pragmatic Realism Columbia University Press catalog page New York NY 261 pages cloth ISBN 0 231 05004 6 External links EditPeirce including pragmatismArisbe The Peirce Gateway Joseph Ransdell ed Over 100 online writings by Peirce as of November 24 2010 with annotations 100s of online papers on Peirce The peirce l e forum Much else Center for Applied Semiotics CAS 1998 2003 Donald Cunningham amp Jean Umiker Sebeok Indiana U Centro Internacional de Estudos Peirceanos CIEP and previously Centro de Estudos Peirceanos CeneP Lucia Santaella et al Pontifical Catholic U of Sao Paulo PUC SP Brazil In Portuguese some English Commens Digital Companion to C S Peirce Mats Bergman Sami Paavola amp Joao Queiroz formerly Commens at Helsinki U Includes Commens Dictionary of Peirce s Terms with Peirce s definitions often many per term across the decades and the Digital Encyclopedia of Charles S Peirce old edition still at old website Centro Studi Peirce Carlo Sini Rossella Fabbrichesi et al U of Milan Italy In Italian and English Part of Pragma Charles S Peirce Foundation Co sponsoring the 2014 Peirce International Centennial Congress 100th anniversary of Peirce s death Charles S Peirce Society Transactions of the Charles S Peirce Society Quarterly journal of Peirce studies since spring 1965 Table of Contents of all issues Charles S Peirce Studies Brian Kariger ed Pragmaticism at the Mathematics Genealogy Project Collegium for the Advanced Study of Picture Act and Embodiment The Peirce Archive Humboldt U Berlin Germany Cataloguing Peirce s innumerable drawings amp graphic materials More info Prof Aud Sissel Hoel Digital Encyclopedia of Charles S Peirce Joao Queiroz now at UFJF amp Ricardo Gudwin at Unicamp eds Universidade Estadual de Campinas U of Campinas Brazil in English 84 authors listed 51 papers online amp more listed as of January 31 2009 Newer edition now at Commens Existential Graphs Jay Zeman ed U of Florida Has 4 Peirce texts Grupo de Estudios Peirceanos GEP Peirce Studies Group Jaime Nubiola ed U of Navarra Spain Big study site Peirce amp others in Spanish amp English bibliography more Helsinki Peirce Research Center HPRC Ahti Veikko Pietarinen et al U of Helsinki His Glassy Essence Autobiographical Peirce Kenneth Laine Ketner Institute for Studies in Pragmaticism Kenneth Laine Ketner Clyde Hendrick et al Texas Tech U Peirce s life and works International Research Group on Abductive Inference Uwe Wirth et al eds Goethe U Frankfurt Germany Uses frames Click on link at bottom of its home page for English Moved to University of Giessen U of Giessen Germany home page not in English but see Artikel section there L I R S C E 1974 2003 Institut de Recherche en Semiotique Communication et Education Gerard Deledalle Joelle Rethore U of Perpignan France Minute Semeiotic Vinicius Romanini U of Sao Paulo Brazil English Portuguese Peirce at Signo Theoretical Semiotics on the Web Louis Hebert director supported by U of Quebec Theory application exercises of Peirce s Semiotics and Esthetics English French Peirce Edition Project PEP Indiana U Purdue U Indianapolis IUPUI Andre De Tienne Nathan Houser et al Editors of the Writings of Charles S Peirce W and The Essential Peirce EP v 2 Many study aids such as the Robin Catalog of Peirce s manuscripts amp letters and Biographical introductions to EP 1 2 and W 1 6 amp 8 Most of W 2 readable online PEP s branch at Universite du Quebec a Montreal UQAM Working on W 7 Peirce s work on the Century Dictionary Definition of the week Peirce s Existential Graphs Frithjof Dau Germany Pragmatism Cybrary David Hildebrand amp John Shook Research Group on Semiotic Epistemology and Mathematics Education late 1990s Institut fur Didaktik der Mathematik Michael Hoffman Michael Otte Universitat Bielefeld Germany See Peirce Project Newsletter v 3 n 1 p 13 Semiotics according to Robert Marty with 76 definitions of the sign by C S Peirce Related pragmatismAssociazione Culturale Pragma with European Journal of Pragmatism and American Philosophy International Pragmatism Society Journal Contemporary Pragmatism Mitchell Aboulafia amp John R Shook Editors Nordic Pragmatism Network Henrik Rydenfelt U of Helsinki coordinator Journal Nordic Studies in Pragmatism Pragmatism Cybrary David Hildebrand amp John R Shook Editors Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Pragmaticism amp oldid 1124697271, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.