fbpx
Wikipedia

The Radicalism of the American Revolution

The Radicalism of the American Revolution is a nonfiction book by historian Gordon S. Wood, published by Vintage Books as a paperback in 1993. The first printing of the hardcover edition notes a publication date of December 1991. In the book, Wood explores the radical character of the American Revolution. The book was awarded the 1993 Pulitzer Prize for History.[1]

The Radicalism of the American Revolution
AuthorGordon S. Wood
CountryUnited States
GenreHistory
PublisherVintage Books
Publication date
1993 (hardcover 1991)
Pages464
AwardsPulitzer Prize for History
ISBN9780679736882

Wood divided the narrative into three parts: monarchy, republicanism, and democracy.

Background edit

Gordon S. Wood ended The Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787, a 1969 book based on a dissertation supervised by Bernard Bailyn, with the "End of Classical Politics." Wood had argued that, after the Constitutional ratification debates, "the stability of government...now depended upon the prevention of the various social interests from incorporating themselves too firmly in the government. Institutional or governmental politics was thus abstracted in a curious way from its former associations with the society...This revolution marked an end of the classical conception of politics." The first section of the book explored how and why "the colonists" appropriated "Whig...ideals" of "liberty", which came to represent the absolute ideal unity of "personal liberty" with "public liberty."[2]

In the final chapter of the book, Wood attempted to demonstrate that the "assumptions" and premises of Federalist No. 10, "different from those of the Whigs in 1776", proliferated among the ratifying framers as an "American science of politics." The "Federalist Persuasion" for " 'the people' " as sovereign rested, in turn, on notional "interests"—and vice-versa. Government further retained Tory urgings from "the early seventies 'to protect citizens in their personal liberty and property.' " Wood declared that "public or political liberty, the right of the people to share in the government—lost its significance for a system in which the people participated throughout." But a potential effect of these premises and "assumptions" was the rise of "factions" in government—fearful representatives catering to " 'popular resentment' ", or delegates invoking the " 'silent awe of a predominant party.' " For Wood's James Madison, "unless individuals and minorities were protected against the power of majorities, no government could truly be free."[3] Still, a faction could be "a minority or majority of the whole."[4] In "such circumstances the aim of government, in James Iredell's words, had become twofold: " 'the security of every individual, as well as a fluctuating majority of the people.' " The emphasis, however, was on the perils of "factious majorities." Factions in a legislature, especially majority factions, could not define the " 'public interest' " because "the liberty that was now emphasized was personal or private, the protection of individual rights against all government encroachments, particularly by the legislature."[5]

Wood's Federalists were certain that the embrace of "personal liberty" by " 'the people' " would remedy its own potential effect, ensuring protections for " 'the rights of individuals' " when a legislative faction aimed to define the distinct " 'interests of society.' " " In that regard, these "men" considered "public and private liberty as antagonistic rather than complementary... Such a total grounding of government in self-interest and consent had made old-fashioned popular revolutions obsolete." Yet this remedy, "the Federalist image of a public good undefinable by factious majorities in small states but somehow capable of formulation by the best men of a large society may have been chimera." Any ulterior "partisan and aristocratic purposes" for such circular reasoning failed to undermine an "intellectual achievement [that] really transcended their particular political and social intentions." In Wood's estimation, the "formulation of this system" as an "intellectual achievement" was neither his proposition, nor ultimately theirs, because the "political theory" that had "been obscured" prior to his study contributed in linear "time to the destruction of the very social world they had sought to maintain." Wood concluded that the "political theory" was "peculiarly the product of a democratic society, without a precise beginning or an ending."[6]

In 1992, as Wood's The Radicalism of the American Revolution first circulated among scholars, historian Daniel T. Rodgers engaged with debates launched by Bailyn's The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution and Creation of the American Republic. Periodization, according to Rodgers, was the source of much controversy between proponents of "Harvard republicanism" and proponents of "St. Louis republicanism." In the context of The Creation of the American Republic, "when Wood turned to the early national period he found a society dancing feverishly to the tune of 'modern American liberalism.' The mark of St. Louis republicanism, by contrast, was a reluctance to date the 'end of classical politics' as early as Wood had put it." As a result of these fractious disputes, "RepublicanismH collapsed all at once in a clatter of constitutional argument. RepublicanismS staggered on to a slower death." His review essay did not include the extended periodization in Radicalism.[7]

Wood clarified the vaunted and maligned "End of Classical Politics" in a new preface to his 1969 study. First, he reminded readers, "it is important to remember that the boxlike categories of 'republicanism' and 'liberalism' are essentially the inventions of us historians." In Wood's estimation, the bifurcation of "Harvard republicanism" and "St. Louis republicanism" had been premised on "the mistaken notion that one set of ideas simply replaced another en bloc...after the debates and discoveries of 1787-88 most Americans (John Adams was a conspicuous exception) more or less ceased talking about politics in the way theorists since Aristotle had—as a maneuvering and mixing of three social entities or forms of government [monarchy, lords, commons]—and began talking about politics in recognizably modern ways—as a competition among interests or parties in the society for control of a quasi-autonomous state...Cultural changes of that magnitude do not take place in such a neat and sudden manner. Republicanism was indeed gradually transformed into something we call liberalism, but in subtle and complicated ways that kept many republican sentiments alive."[8]

Synopsis edit

In The Radicalism of the American Revolution, Wood argued that in the "classical republican tradition our modern distinction between positive and negative liberties was not yet clearly perceived, and the two forms of liberty were still often seen as one." Wood premised this argument with the notion that "public or political liberty—or what we now call positive liberty—meant participation in government. And this political liberty in turn provided the means by which the personal liberty and private rights of the individual—what we today call negative liberty—were protected."[9] If "disinterestedness" in government "was based on liberty and independence, then it followed that only autonomous individuals free from any ties of interest and paid by no master were qualified to be citizens. Jefferson and many other republican idealists hoped that all ordinary yeoman farmers who owned their own land...would be independent and free enough of pecuniary temptations and marketplace interests to be virtuous." Still, for many "republican idealists", who renounced any " 'commonwealth' " shift to " 'absolute Monarchy' ", the "disinterested leadership could only be located among the landed gentry whose income [derived] from the rents of tenants."[10] Yet, most "merchants active in their businesses" sought to attain "wealth and leisure sufficient to avoid any day-to-day involvement in their businesses."[11] Their "world" still seemed "small and intimate...which is why the colonists especially were quick to explain a concatenation of events as caused by conspiracy."[12]

The Revolution also sparked unresolved "ideological" debates over the "commercial nature of real estate." Wood explained that "virtue became identified with decency" and was "soft and feminized." Ideas of "classical virtue had flowed from the citizen's participation in politics...But modern virtue flowed from the citizen's participation in society, not in government, which the liberal-minded increasingly saw as the principal source of the evils of the world." During the American Revolution, "some now argued that even commerce, that traditional enemy of classical virtue, was in fact a source of modern virtue."[13] Wood cast early Federalism as a response to Anti-Federalist questions regarding the very notion of an expansive "[the] United States" and the solecism imperium-in-imperio, sovereignty-within-sovereignty. James Madison and his Federalists offered a last rebuttal: the locus of "power," sovereignty, would be vested in "the people," not in organs of government. In his earlier dissertation, Wood had described the Federalist rebuttal as "disingenuous." He also previously depicted this "mutuality of interests" as generating a crucible for "the alliance of power and liberty."[14]

In an "American science of politics", government harnessed "interests," which transformed "positive liberty" into, for instance, the United States public interest, sustained by "patrician" disinterestedness---a refraction, rather than reflection, of "interests."[15] Wood held that the idea of government officials as "umpires" for "republican liberty" was soon discarded. "By the late 1780s," Wood opined, "many of the younger revolutionary leaders like James Madison were willing to confront the reality of interests in America," exemplified by Madison's Federalist No. 10. The federal government became a " 'disinterested and dispassionate umpire in disputes between different passions and interests in the State.' "[16] Even with plans to expand public education, potential officeholders needed to become "liberally educated and cosmopolitan enough to have the breadth of perspective to comprehend all the different interests in society." Reading law, out of all the "learned professions, would win the electoral day. Anti-Federalists pointed out that attorney profits, even if supplemented by pro bono work, turned "lawyers into tradesmen or artisans" in an interests-based society. Not so, rejoined Wood's Alexander Hamilton: "being a lawyer was not an occupation and different from other profit-making activities." Both Federalists and Anti-Federalists ultimately countenanced a surplus of candidates in extended electoral spheres, which James Madison conjectured increased campaign competition and the likelihood that anxious elected delegates, despite coming from faraway places, would constantly clamor to reflect constituent "interests."[17]

In Federalist No. 10, James Madison held that disinterested representation defined republics, yet attempted to fuse disinterestedness with direct democracy in a system that would later be deemed representative democracy for an "American science of politics."[18] In an oft-quoted passage from Federalist No. 56, Madison propounded that "it is a sound and important principle that the representative ought to be acquainted with the interests and circumstances of his constituents. But this principle can extend no further than to those circumstances and interests to which the authority and care of the representative relate."[19] The crux of the matter was the fulfillment of both "patrician" disinterestedness and representative "authority" over constituent "interests", such as income, vocation, commerce, urban labor, etc.[20] Also, Madison expressed concerns about government by the "few" as well as government by the "many." In writing Federalist No. 62, for instance, Madison grew skeptical of any fiscal " 'regulation' " because, counterintuitively, " 'every new regulation concerning commerce or revenue; or in any manner affecting the value of the different species of property, presents a new harvest to those who watch the change and can trace its consequences' ", rather than sharing this exclusive purview with " 'the great body of their fellow citizens...[these] laws are made for the few not for the many.' "[21]

For Federalists, officeholders could persist as disinterested "umpires" and reflective representatives due to "a notion that has carried into our own time---that lawyers and other professionals are somehow free of the marketplace, are less selfish and interested...than merchants and businessmen." Federalist representatives were indeed "liberally educated and cosmopolitan enough to have the breadth of perspective to comprehend all the different interests in society."[22] Conversely, in Anti-Federalist disquisitions, "the occupations and interests of the society were so diverse and discrete that only individuals sharing a particular occupation or interest could speak for that occupation or interest." The Anti-Federalists who "lost the battle over the Constitution" believed that "only an explicit form of representation that allowed Germans, Baptists, artisans, farmers, and so on each to send delegates of its own kind into the political arena...In these populist Anti-Federalist calls for the most explicit form of representation possible, and not in Madison's Federalist No. 10, lay the real origins of American pluralism and American interest-group politics...Insofar as American politics became localist and dominated by interest groups and calls for extended suffrage, the Anti-Federalists prepared the way."[23]

Conclusion edit

Gordon S. Wood concluded Radicalism with the rise of a fledgling Jacksonian democracy, contending that voters appropriated the "Federalist Persuasion" of an "interests"-based popular sovereignty and "celebration of commerce", much to the chagrin of many, but by no means all, of the former persuaders in their twilight years. The late eighteenth-century idea of the "equality" of sensations and benevolent "feeling" bestowed on a "moral" humanity by the deistic "Creator", gave rise to the idea of "equality" of opportunity.[24] Wood later elaborated on this argument: "...in both the national and international spheres, monarchy and its intrusive institutions and monopolistic ways were what prevented a natural harmony of people's feelings and interests."[25] More recently, historian Carli Conklin added that "the pursuit of happiness" referred to the "unalienable right to then choose to pursue a life of virtue [which may or may not have included "property"] or, in other words, a life lived in harmony with those natural law principles. The result would be eudaimonia or man's own real and substantial happiness."[26]

In Radicalism, Wood observed that "government officials were no longer to play the role of umpire; they were no longer to stand above the competing interests of the marketplace...Elected officials were to bring the partial, local interests of the society, and sometimes even their own interests, right into the workings of government. Partisanship and parties became legitimate activities in politics. And all adult white males, regardless of their property holdings of their independence, were to have the right to vote...the Revolution was the most radical and most far-reaching event in American history."[27]

Reception edit

References edit

  1. ^ . Writer's Directory 2005.  – via HighBeam Research (subscription required). Archived from the original on April 15, 2016. Retrieved December 7, 2012.
  2. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1969). Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (1 ed.). Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute. pp. 3–45 and 606–618.
  3. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1969). Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (1 ed.). Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute. pp. 3–45 and 606–618.
  4. ^ Federalist No. 10. p. 56 of the Dawson edition at Wikisource.
  5. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1969). Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (1 ed.). Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute. pp. 3–45 and 606–618.
  6. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1969). Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (1 ed.). Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute. pp. 3–45 and 606–618.
  7. ^ Rodgers, Daniel T. (1992). "Republicanism: The Career of a Concept". The Journal of American History. 79 (1): 11–38. doi:10.2307/2078466. JSTOR 2078466.
  8. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1998). Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (2 ed.). Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute. pp. xi–xii.
  9. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. pp. 3 and 109.
  10. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. pp. 99 and 106.
  11. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. p. 107.
  12. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. p. 61.
  13. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. pp. 216–18.
  14. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1969). Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (1 ed.). Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute. pp. 543–546.
  15. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1969). Creation of the American Republic, 1776-1787 (1 ed.). Chapel Hill, NC: University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute. pp. 519–564 and 593–618.
  16. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. p. 253.
  17. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. p. 254.
  18. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. p. 254.
  19. ^ "The Avalon Project : Federalist No 56". avalon.law.yale.edu.
  20. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. p. 254.
  21. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. p. 254.
  22. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. p. 254.
  23. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. pp. 258–259.
  24. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. pp. 8, 243–270, and 325–370.
  25. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (2009). Empire of Liberty: A History of the early Republic, 1789-1815. Oxford, United Kingdom: Oxford University Press. pp. 189–90. ISBN 9780195039146.
  26. ^ Conklin, Carli (2015). "The Origins of the Pursuit of Happiness". Washington University Jurisprudence Review. 7 (2): 198, 202, and 260–62.
  27. ^ Wood, Gordon S. (1991). The Radicalism of the American Revolution. New York, NY: Vintage Books: Random House, Inc. p. 8.

radicalism, american, revolution, nonfiction, book, historian, gordon, wood, published, vintage, books, paperback, 1993, first, printing, hardcover, edition, notes, publication, date, december, 1991, book, wood, explores, radical, character, american, revoluti. The Radicalism of the American Revolution is a nonfiction book by historian Gordon S Wood published by Vintage Books as a paperback in 1993 The first printing of the hardcover edition notes a publication date of December 1991 In the book Wood explores the radical character of the American Revolution The book was awarded the 1993 Pulitzer Prize for History 1 The Radicalism of the American RevolutionAuthorGordon S WoodCountryUnited StatesGenreHistoryPublisherVintage BooksPublication date1993 hardcover 1991 Pages464AwardsPulitzer Prize for HistoryISBN9780679736882Wood divided the narrative into three parts monarchy republicanism and democracy Contents 1 Background 2 Synopsis 2 1 Conclusion 3 Reception 4 ReferencesBackground editGordon S Wood ended The Creation of the American Republic 1776 1787 a 1969 book based on a dissertation supervised by Bernard Bailyn with the End of Classical Politics Wood had argued that after the Constitutional ratification debates the stability of government now depended upon the prevention of the various social interests from incorporating themselves too firmly in the government Institutional or governmental politics was thus abstracted in a curious way from its former associations with the society This revolution marked an end of the classical conception of politics The first section of the book explored how and why the colonists appropriated Whig ideals of liberty which came to represent the absolute ideal unity of personal liberty with public liberty 2 In the final chapter of the book Wood attempted to demonstrate that the assumptions and premises of Federalist No 10 different from those of the Whigs in 1776 proliferated among the ratifying framers as an American science of politics The Federalist Persuasion for the people as sovereign rested in turn on notional interests and vice versa Government further retained Tory urgings from the early seventies to protect citizens in their personal liberty and property Wood declared that public or political liberty the right of the people to share in the government lost its significance for a system in which the people participated throughout But a potential effect of these premises and assumptions was the rise of factions in government fearful representatives catering to popular resentment or delegates invoking the silent awe of a predominant party For Wood s James Madison unless individuals and minorities were protected against the power of majorities no government could truly be free 3 Still a faction could be a minority or majority of the whole 4 In such circumstances the aim of government in James Iredell s words had become twofold the security of every individual as well as a fluctuating majority of the people The emphasis however was on the perils of factious majorities Factions in a legislature especially majority factions could not define the public interest because the liberty that was now emphasized was personal or private the protection of individual rights against all government encroachments particularly by the legislature 5 Wood s Federalists were certain that the embrace of personal liberty by the people would remedy its own potential effect ensuring protections for the rights of individuals when a legislative faction aimed to define the distinct interests of society In that regard these men considered public and private liberty as antagonistic rather than complementary Such a total grounding of government in self interest and consent had made old fashioned popular revolutions obsolete Yet this remedy the Federalist image of a public good undefinable by factious majorities in small states but somehow capable of formulation by the best men of a large society may have been chimera Any ulterior partisan and aristocratic purposes for such circular reasoning failed to undermine an intellectual achievement that really transcended their particular political and social intentions In Wood s estimation the formulation of this system as an intellectual achievement was neither his proposition nor ultimately theirs because the political theory that had been obscured prior to his study contributed in linear time to the destruction of the very social world they had sought to maintain Wood concluded that the political theory was peculiarly the product of a democratic society without a precise beginning or an ending 6 In 1992 as Wood s The Radicalism of the American Revolution first circulated among scholars historian Daniel T Rodgers engaged with debates launched by Bailyn s The Ideological Origins of the American Revolution and Creation of the American Republic Periodization according to Rodgers was the source of much controversy between proponents of Harvard republicanism and proponents of St Louis republicanism In the context of The Creation of the American Republic when Wood turned to the early national period he found a society dancing feverishly to the tune of modern American liberalism The mark of St Louis republicanism by contrast was a reluctance to date the end of classical politics as early as Wood had put it As a result of these fractious disputes RepublicanismH collapsed all at once in a clatter of constitutional argument RepublicanismS staggered on to a slower death His review essay did not include the extended periodization in Radicalism 7 Wood clarified the vaunted and maligned End of Classical Politics in a new preface to his 1969 study First he reminded readers it is important to remember that the boxlike categories of republicanism and liberalism are essentially the inventions of us historians In Wood s estimation the bifurcation of Harvard republicanism and St Louis republicanism had been premised on the mistaken notion that one set of ideas simply replaced another en bloc after the debates and discoveries of 1787 88 most Americans John Adams was a conspicuous exception more or less ceased talking about politics in the way theorists since Aristotle had as a maneuvering and mixing of three social entities or forms of government monarchy lords commons and began talking about politics in recognizably modern ways as a competition among interests or parties in the society for control of a quasi autonomous state Cultural changes of that magnitude do not take place in such a neat and sudden manner Republicanism was indeed gradually transformed into something we call liberalism but in subtle and complicated ways that kept many republican sentiments alive 8 Synopsis editIn The Radicalism of the American Revolution Wood argued that in the classical republican tradition our modern distinction between positive and negative liberties was not yet clearly perceived and the two forms of liberty were still often seen as one Wood premised this argument with the notion that public or political liberty or what we now call positive liberty meant participation in government And this political liberty in turn provided the means by which the personal liberty and private rights of the individual what we today call negative liberty were protected 9 If disinterestedness in government was based on liberty and independence then it followed that only autonomous individuals free from any ties of interest and paid by no master were qualified to be citizens Jefferson and many other republican idealists hoped that all ordinary yeoman farmers who owned their own land would be independent and free enough of pecuniary temptations and marketplace interests to be virtuous Still for many republican idealists who renounced any commonwealth shift to absolute Monarchy the disinterested leadership could only be located among the landed gentry whose income derived from the rents of tenants 10 Yet most merchants active in their businesses sought to attain wealth and leisure sufficient to avoid any day to day involvement in their businesses 11 Their world still seemed small and intimate which is why the colonists especially were quick to explain a concatenation of events as caused by conspiracy 12 The Revolution also sparked unresolved ideological debates over the commercial nature of real estate Wood explained that virtue became identified with decency and was soft and feminized Ideas of classical virtue had flowed from the citizen s participation in politics But modern virtue flowed from the citizen s participation in society not in government which the liberal minded increasingly saw as the principal source of the evils of the world During the American Revolution some now argued that even commerce that traditional enemy of classical virtue was in fact a source of modern virtue 13 Wood cast early Federalism as a response to Anti Federalist questions regarding the very notion of an expansive the United States and the solecism imperium in imperio sovereignty within sovereignty James Madison and his Federalists offered a last rebuttal the locus of power sovereignty would be vested in the people not in organs of government In his earlier dissertation Wood had described the Federalist rebuttal as disingenuous He also previously depicted this mutuality of interests as generating a crucible for the alliance of power and liberty 14 In an American science of politics government harnessed interests which transformed positive liberty into for instance the United States public interest sustained by patrician disinterestedness a refraction rather than reflection of interests 15 Wood held that the idea of government officials as umpires for republican liberty was soon discarded By the late 1780s Wood opined many of the younger revolutionary leaders like James Madison were willing to confront the reality of interests in America exemplified by Madison s Federalist No 10 The federal government became a disinterested and dispassionate umpire in disputes between different passions and interests in the State 16 Even with plans to expand public education potential officeholders needed to become liberally educated and cosmopolitan enough to have the breadth of perspective to comprehend all the different interests in society Reading law out of all the learned professions would win the electoral day Anti Federalists pointed out that attorney profits even if supplemented by pro bono work turned lawyers into tradesmen or artisans in an interests based society Not so rejoined Wood s Alexander Hamilton being a lawyer was not an occupation and different from other profit making activities Both Federalists and Anti Federalists ultimately countenanced a surplus of candidates in extended electoral spheres which James Madison conjectured increased campaign competition and the likelihood that anxious elected delegates despite coming from faraway places would constantly clamor to reflect constituent interests 17 In Federalist No 10 James Madison held that disinterested representation defined republics yet attempted to fuse disinterestedness with direct democracy in a system that would later be deemed representative democracy for an American science of politics 18 In an oft quoted passage from Federalist No 56 Madison propounded that it is a sound and important principle that the representative ought to be acquainted with the interests and circumstances of his constituents But this principle can extend no further than to those circumstances and interests to which the authority and care of the representative relate 19 The crux of the matter was the fulfillment of both patrician disinterestedness and representative authority over constituent interests such as income vocation commerce urban labor etc 20 Also Madison expressed concerns about government by the few as well as government by the many In writing Federalist No 62 for instance Madison grew skeptical of any fiscal regulation because counterintuitively every new regulation concerning commerce or revenue or in any manner affecting the value of the different species of property presents a new harvest to those who watch the change and can trace its consequences rather than sharing this exclusive purview with the great body of their fellow citizens these laws are made for the few not for the many 21 For Federalists officeholders could persist as disinterested umpires and reflective representatives due to a notion that has carried into our own time that lawyers and other professionals are somehow free of the marketplace are less selfish and interested than merchants and businessmen Federalist representatives were indeed liberally educated and cosmopolitan enough to have the breadth of perspective to comprehend all the different interests in society 22 Conversely in Anti Federalist disquisitions the occupations and interests of the society were so diverse and discrete that only individuals sharing a particular occupation or interest could speak for that occupation or interest The Anti Federalists who lost the battle over the Constitution believed that only an explicit form of representation that allowed Germans Baptists artisans farmers and so on each to send delegates of its own kind into the political arena In these populist Anti Federalist calls for the most explicit form of representation possible and not in Madison s Federalist No 10 lay the real origins of American pluralism and American interest group politics Insofar as American politics became localist and dominated by interest groups and calls for extended suffrage the Anti Federalists prepared the way 23 Conclusion edit Gordon S Wood concluded Radicalism with the rise of a fledgling Jacksonian democracy contending that voters appropriated the Federalist Persuasion of an interests based popular sovereignty and celebration of commerce much to the chagrin of many but by no means all of the former persuaders in their twilight years The late eighteenth century idea of the equality of sensations and benevolent feeling bestowed on a moral humanity by the deistic Creator gave rise to the idea of equality of opportunity 24 Wood later elaborated on this argument in both the national and international spheres monarchy and its intrusive institutions and monopolistic ways were what prevented a natural harmony of people s feelings and interests 25 More recently historian Carli Conklin added that the pursuit of happiness referred to the unalienable right to then choose to pursue a life of virtue which may or may not have included property or in other words a life lived in harmony with those natural law principles The result would be eudaimonia or man s own real and substantial happiness 26 In Radicalism Wood observed that government officials were no longer to play the role of umpire they were no longer to stand above the competing interests of the marketplace Elected officials were to bring the partial local interests of the society and sometimes even their own interests right into the workings of government Partisanship and parties became legitimate activities in politics And all adult white males regardless of their property holdings of their independence were to have the right to vote the Revolution was the most radical and most far reaching event in American history 27 Reception editThis section is empty You can help by adding to it August 2023 References edit Wood Gordon S tewart Writer s Directory 2005 via HighBeam Research subscription required Archived from the original on April 15 2016 Retrieved December 7 2012 Wood Gordon S 1969 Creation of the American Republic 1776 1787 1 ed Chapel Hill NC University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute pp 3 45 and 606 618 Wood Gordon S 1969 Creation of the American Republic 1776 1787 1 ed Chapel Hill NC University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute pp 3 45 and 606 618 Federalist No 10 p 56 of the Dawson edition at Wikisource Wood Gordon S 1969 Creation of the American Republic 1776 1787 1 ed Chapel Hill NC University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute pp 3 45 and 606 618 Wood Gordon S 1969 Creation of the American Republic 1776 1787 1 ed Chapel Hill NC University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute pp 3 45 and 606 618 Rodgers Daniel T 1992 Republicanism The Career of a Concept The Journal of American History 79 1 11 38 doi 10 2307 2078466 JSTOR 2078466 Wood Gordon S 1998 Creation of the American Republic 1776 1787 2 ed Chapel Hill NC University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute pp xi xii Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc pp 3 and 109 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc pp 99 and 106 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc p 107 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc p 61 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc pp 216 18 Wood Gordon S 1969 Creation of the American Republic 1776 1787 1 ed Chapel Hill NC University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute pp 543 546 Wood Gordon S 1969 Creation of the American Republic 1776 1787 1 ed Chapel Hill NC University of North Carolina Press for the Omohundro Institute pp 519 564 and 593 618 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc p 253 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc p 254 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc p 254 The Avalon Project Federalist No 56 avalon law yale edu Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc p 254 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc p 254 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc p 254 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc pp 258 259 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc pp 8 243 270 and 325 370 Wood Gordon S 2009 Empire of Liberty A History of the early Republic 1789 1815 Oxford United Kingdom Oxford University Press pp 189 90 ISBN 9780195039146 Conklin Carli 2015 The Origins of the Pursuit of Happiness Washington University Jurisprudence Review 7 2 198 202 and 260 62 Wood Gordon S 1991 The Radicalism of the American Revolution New York NY Vintage Books Random House Inc p 8 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title The Radicalism of the American Revolution amp oldid 1178542509, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.