fbpx
Wikipedia

Polarity item

In linguistics, a polarity item is a lexical item that is associated with affirmation or negation. An affirmation is a positive polarity item, abbreviated PPI or AFF. A negation is a negative polarity item, abbreviated NPI or NEG.

The linguistic environment in which a polarity item appears is a licensing context. In the simplest case, an affirmative statement provides a licensing context for a PPI, while negation provides a licensing context for an NPI. However, there are many complications, and not all polarity items of a particular type have the same licensing contexts.

In English

As examples of polarity items, consider the English lexical items somewhat and at all, as used in the following sentences:

  1. I liked the film somewhat.
  2. I didn't like the film at all.
  3. *I liked the film at all.
  4. *I didn't like the film somewhat.

As can be seen, somewhat is licensed by the affirmative environment of sentence (1), but it is forbidden (anti-licensed) by the negative environment of sentence (4).[1] It can therefore be considered to be a positive polarity item (PPI). On the other hand, at all is licensed by the negative environment of sentence (2), but anti-licensed by the positive environment of sentence (3), and is therefore considered a negative polarity item (NPI).

Because standard English does not have negative concord, that is, double negatives are not used to intensify each other, the language makes frequent use of certain NPIs that correspond in meaning to negative items, and can be used in the environment of another negative. For example, anywhere is an NPI corresponding to the negative nowhere, as used in the following sentences:

  1. I was going nowhere. (the negative nowhere is used when not preceded by another negative)
  2. I was not going anywhere. (the NPI anywhere is used in the environment of the preceding negative not)

Note that double-negative constructions like I was not going nowhere take on an opposing meaning in formal usage, but that this is not necessarily the case in colloquial contexts and in various lects, which parallels other languages which have negative concord. Anywhere, like most of the other NPIs listed below, is also used in other senses where it is not an NPI, as in I would go anywhere with you.

  • nobody/no one – anybody/anyone
  • nothing – anything
  • no/none – any
  • never – ever
  • nowhere – anywhere
  • no longer/no more – any longer/any more

See also English grammar § Negation, and Affirmation and negation § Multiple negation.

Determination of licensing contexts

The actual set of contexts that license particular polarity items is not as easily defined as a simple distinction between affirmative and negative sentences. Baker[2] noted that double negation may provide an acceptable context for positive polarity items:

I can't believe you don't fancy her somewhat.
John doesn't have any potatoes
*John has any potatoes.

However, licensing contexts can take many forms besides simple negation/affirmation. To complicate matters, polarity items appear to be highly idiosyncratic, each with its own set of licensing contexts.

Early discussion of polarity items can be found in the work of Otto Jespersen and Edward Klima. Much of the research on polarity items has centered around the question of what creates a negative context. In the late 1970s, William Ladusaw (building on work by Gilles Fauconnier) discovered that most English NPIs are licensed in downward entailing environments. This is known as the Fauconnier–Ladusaw hypothesis. A downward entailing environment, however, is not a necessary condition for an NPI to be licensed—they may be licensed by some non-monotone (and thus not downward entailing) contexts, like "exactly N," as well.

*Some people have ever been on the moon.
Exactly three people have ever been on the moon.

Nor is a downward entailing environment a sufficient condition for all negative polarity items, as first pointed out by Zwarts (1981) for Dutch "ook maar."

Licensing contexts across languages include the scope of n-words (negative particles, negative quantifiers), the antecedent of conditionals, questions, the restrictor of universal quantifiers, non-affirmative verbs (doubt), adversative predicates (be surprised), negative conjunctions (without), comparatives and superlatives, too-phrases, negative predicates (unlikely), some subjunctive complements, some disjunctions, imperatives, and others (finally, only). Given this wide range of mostly non-downward entailing environments, the Fauconnier-Ladusaw Hypothesis has gradually been replaced in favor of theories based on the notion of nonveridicality (proposed by Zwarts and Giannakidou).

Different NPIs may be licensed by different expressions. Thus, while the NPI anything is licensed by the downward entailing expression at most two of the visitors, the idiomatic NPI not lift a finger (known as a minimizer) is not licensed by the same expression.

At most two of the visitors had seen anything.
*At most two of the visitors lifted a finger to help.

While NPIs have been discovered in many languages, their distribution is subject to substantial cross-linguistic variation; this aspect of NPIs is currently the subject of ongoing research in cross-linguistic semantics.[3]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ See Baker (1970).
  2. ^ See Baker (1970).
  3. ^ Giannakidou, Anastasia. "Negative and positive polarity items: licensing, compositionality and variation". 2017-01-18 at the Wayback Machine Prepared for Maienborn, Claudia, Klaus von Heusinger, and Paul Portner (eds). Semantics: An International Handbook of Natural Language Meaning. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter. (January 2008).

References

  • Baker, C. Lee (1970). "Double Negatives". Linguistic Inquiry. 1 (2): 169–186. JSTOR 4177551.
  • Klima, Edward (1964). "Negation in English". In Jerry A. Fodor & Jerrold J. Katz (ed.). The structure of language. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall, 246-323.
  • Fauconnier, Gilles (1975). "Polarity and the scale principle". Chicago Linguistic Society. Vol. 11. pp. 188–199.
  • Giannakidou, Anastasia (2001). "The Meaning of Free Choice". Linguistics and Philosophy. 24 (6): 659–735. doi:10.1023/A:1012758115458. S2CID 10533949.
  • Ladusaw, William A. (1979). Polarity Sensitivity as Inherent Scope Relations. Ph.D. Dissertation, University of Texas, Austin.
  • Zwarts, Frans (1981). "Negatief Polaire Uitdrukkingen I". GLOT. 4: 35–102.

External links

  • The Polarity Items Bibliography (Tübingen University)
  • Isac, Daniela; Charles Reiss (2013). I-language: An Introduction to Linguistics as Cognitive Science, 2nd edition. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-953420-3. In the book, there is an introductory discussion of negative polarity items spanning several chapters, covering syntax, semantics, sociolinguistic aspects.
  • The Collection of Distributionally Idiosyncratic Items, containing German and Rumanian NPIs (Tübingen University)

polarity, item, linguistics, polarity, item, lexical, item, that, associated, with, affirmation, negation, affirmation, positive, polarity, item, abbreviated, negation, negative, polarity, item, abbreviated, linguistic, environment, which, polarity, item, appe. In linguistics a polarity item is a lexical item that is associated with affirmation or negation An affirmation is a positive polarity item abbreviated PPI or AFF A negation is a negative polarity item abbreviated NPI or NEG The linguistic environment in which a polarity item appears is a licensing context In the simplest case an affirmative statement provides a licensing context for a PPI while negation provides a licensing context for an NPI However there are many complications and not all polarity items of a particular type have the same licensing contexts Contents 1 In English 2 Determination of licensing contexts 3 See also 4 Notes 5 References 6 External linksIn English EditAs examples of polarity items consider the English lexical items somewhat and at all as used in the following sentences I liked the film somewhat I didn t like the film at all I liked the film at all I didn t like the film somewhat As can be seen somewhat is licensed by the affirmative environment of sentence 1 but it is forbidden anti licensed by the negative environment of sentence 4 1 It can therefore be considered to be a positive polarity item PPI On the other hand at all is licensed by the negative environment of sentence 2 but anti licensed by the positive environment of sentence 3 and is therefore considered a negative polarity item NPI Because standard English does not have negative concord that is double negatives are not used to intensify each other the language makes frequent use of certain NPIs that correspond in meaning to negative items and can be used in the environment of another negative For example anywhere is an NPI corresponding to the negative nowhere as used in the following sentences I was going nowhere the negative nowhere is used when not preceded by another negative I was not going anywhere the NPI anywhere is used in the environment of the preceding negative not Note that double negative constructions like I was not going nowhere take on an opposing meaning in formal usage but that this is not necessarily the case in colloquial contexts and in various lects which parallels other languages which have negative concord Anywhere like most of the other NPIs listed below is also used in other senses where it is not an NPI as in I would go anywhere with you nobody no one anybody anyone nothing anything no none any never ever nowhere anywhere no longer no more any longer any moreSee also English grammar Negation and Affirmation and negation Multiple negation Determination of licensing contexts EditThe actual set of contexts that license particular polarity items is not as easily defined as a simple distinction between affirmative and negative sentences Baker 2 noted that double negation may provide an acceptable context for positive polarity items I can t believe you don t fancy her somewhat John doesn t have any potatoes John has any potatoes However licensing contexts can take many forms besides simple negation affirmation To complicate matters polarity items appear to be highly idiosyncratic each with its own set of licensing contexts Early discussion of polarity items can be found in the work of Otto Jespersen and Edward Klima Much of the research on polarity items has centered around the question of what creates a negative context In the late 1970s William Ladusaw building on work by Gilles Fauconnier discovered that most English NPIs are licensed in downward entailing environments This is known as the Fauconnier Ladusaw hypothesis A downward entailing environment however is not a necessary condition for an NPI to be licensed they may be licensed by some non monotone and thus not downward entailing contexts like exactly N as well Some people have ever been on the moon Exactly three people have ever been on the moon Nor is a downward entailing environment a sufficient condition for all negative polarity items as first pointed out by Zwarts 1981 for Dutch ook maar Licensing contexts across languages include the scope of n words negative particles negative quantifiers the antecedent of conditionals questions the restrictor of universal quantifiers non affirmative verbs doubt adversative predicates be surprised negative conjunctions without comparatives and superlatives too phrases negative predicates unlikely some subjunctive complements some disjunctions imperatives and others finally only Given this wide range of mostly non downward entailing environments the Fauconnier Ladusaw Hypothesis has gradually been replaced in favor of theories based on the notion of nonveridicality proposed by Zwarts and Giannakidou Different NPIs may be licensed by different expressions Thus while the NPI anything is licensed by the downward entailing expression at most two of the visitors the idiomatic NPI not lift a finger known as a minimizer is not licensed by the same expression At most two of the visitors had seen anything At most two of the visitors lifted a finger to help While NPIs have been discovered in many languages their distribution is subject to substantial cross linguistic variation this aspect of NPIs is currently the subject of ongoing research in cross linguistic semantics 3 See also EditDownward entailing Generalized quantifier Grammatical polarity Subtrigging VeridicalityNotes Edit See Baker 1970 See Baker 1970 Giannakidou Anastasia Negative and positive polarity items licensing compositionality and variation Archived 2017 01 18 at the Wayback Machine Prepared for Maienborn Claudia Klaus von Heusinger and Paul Portner eds Semantics An International Handbook of Natural Language Meaning Berlin Mouton de Gruyter January 2008 References EditBaker C Lee 1970 Double Negatives Linguistic Inquiry 1 2 169 186 JSTOR 4177551 Klima Edward 1964 Negation in English In Jerry A Fodor amp Jerrold J Katz ed The structure of language Englewood Cliffs Prentice Hall 246 323 Fauconnier Gilles 1975 Polarity and the scale principle Chicago Linguistic Society Vol 11 pp 188 199 Giannakidou Anastasia 2001 The Meaning of Free Choice Linguistics and Philosophy 24 6 659 735 doi 10 1023 A 1012758115458 S2CID 10533949 Ladusaw William A 1979 Polarity Sensitivity as Inherent Scope Relations Ph D Dissertation University of Texas Austin Zwarts Frans 1981 Negatief Polaire Uitdrukkingen I GLOT 4 35 102 External links EditThe Polarity Items Bibliography Tubingen University Isac Daniela Charles Reiss 2013 I language An Introduction to Linguistics as Cognitive Science 2nd edition Oxford University Press ISBN 978 0 19 953420 3 In the book there is an introductory discussion of negative polarity items spanning several chapters covering syntax semantics sociolinguistic aspects The Collection of Distributionally Idiosyncratic Items containing German and Rumanian NPIs Tubingen University Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Polarity item amp oldid 1154410787, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.