fbpx
Wikipedia

Monoidal t-norm logic

In mathematical logic, monoidal t-norm based logic (or shortly MTL), the logic of left-continuous t-norms, is one of the t-norm fuzzy logics. It belongs to the broader class of substructural logics, or logics of residuated lattices;[1] it extends the logic of commutative bounded integral residuated lattices (known as Höhle's monoidal logic, Ono's FLew, or intuitionistic logic without contraction) by the axiom of prelinearity.

Motivation edit

In fuzzy logic, rather than regarding statements as being either true or false, we associate each statement with a numerical confidence in that statement. By convention the confidences range over the unit interval  , where the maximal confidence   corresponds to the classical concept of true and the minimal confidence   corresponds to the classical concept of false.

T-norms are binary functions on the real unit interval [0, 1], which in fuzzy logic are often used to represent a conjunction connective; if   are the confidences we ascribe to the statements   and   respectively, then one uses a t-norm   to calculate the confidence   ascribed to the compound statement ‘  and  ’. A t-norm   has to satisfy the properties of

commutativity  ,
associativity  ,
monotonicity — if   and   then  ,
and having 1 as identity element  .

Notably absent from this list is the property of idempotence  ; the closest one gets is that  . It may seem strange to be less confident in ‘  and  ’ than in just  , but we generally do want to allow for letting the confidence   in a combined ‘  and  ’ be less than both the confidence   in   and the confidence   in  , and then the ordering   by monotonicity requires  . Another way of putting it is that the t-norm can only take into account the confidences as numbers, not the reasons that may be behind ascribing those confidences; thus it cannot treat ‘  and  ’ differently from ‘  and  , where we are equally confident in both’.

Because the symbol   via its use in lattice theory is very closely associated with the idempotence property, it can be useful to switch to a different symbol for conjunction that is not necessarily idempotent. In the fuzzy logic tradition one sometimes uses   for this "strong" conjunction, but this article follows the substructural logic tradition of using   for the strong conjunction; thus   is the confidence we ascribe to the statement   (still read ‘  and  ’, perhaps with ‘strong’ or ‘multiplicative’ as qualification of the ‘and’).

Having formalised conjunction  , one wishes to continue with the other connectives. One approach to doing that is to introduce negation as an order-reversing map  , then defining remaining connectives using De Morgan's laws, material implication, and the like. A problem with doing so is that the resulting logics may have undesirable properties: they may be too close to classical logic, or if not conversely not support expected inference rules. An alternative that makes the consequences of different choices more predictable is to instead continue with implication   as the second connective: this is overall the most common connective in axiomatisations of logic, and it has closer ties to the deductive aspects of logic than most other connectives. A confidence counterpart   of the implication connective may in fact be defined directly as the residuum of the t-norm.

The logical link between conjunction and implication is provided by something as fundamental as the inference rule modus ponens  : from   and   follows  . In the fuzzy logic case that is more rigorously written as  , because this makes explicit that our confidence for the premise(s) here is that in  , not those in   and   separately. So if   and   are our confidences in   and   respectively, then   is the sought confidence in  , and   is the combined confidence in  . We require that

 

since our confidence   for   should not be less than our confidence   in the statement   from which   logically follows. This bounds the sought confidence  , and one approach for turning   into a binary operation like   would be to make it as large as possible while respecting this bound:

 .

Taking   gives  , so the supremum is always of a nonempty bounded set and thus well-defined. For a general t-norm there remains the possibility that   has a jump discontinuity at  , in which case   could come out strictly larger than   even though   is defined as the least upper bound of  s satisfying  ; to prevent that and have the construction work as expected, we require that the t-norm   is left-continuous. The residuum of a left-continuous t-norm thus can be characterized as the weakest function that makes the fuzzy modus ponens valid, which makes it a suitable truth function for implication in fuzzy logic.

More algebraically, we say that an operation   is a residuum of a t-norm   if for all  ,  , and   it satisfies

  if and only if  .

This equivalence of numerical comparisons mirrors the equivalence of entailments

  if and only if  

that exists because any proof of   from the premise   can be converted into a proof of   from the premise   by doing an extra implication introduction step, and conversely any proof of   from the premise   can be converted into a proof of   from the premise   by doing an extra implication elimination step. Left-continuity of the t-norm is the necessary and sufficient condition for this relationship between a t-norm conjunction and its residual implication to hold.

Truth functions of further propositional connectives can be defined by means of the t-norm and its residuum, for instance the residual negation   In this way, the left-continuous t-norm, its residuum, and the truth functions of additional propositional connectives (see the section Standard semantics below) determine the truth values of complex propositional formulae in [0, 1]. Formulae that always evaluate to 1 are then called tautologies with respect to the given left-continuous t-norm   or  tautologies. The set of all  tautologies is called the logic of the t-norm   since these formulae represent the laws of fuzzy logic (determined by the t-norm) that hold (to degree 1) regardless of the truth degrees of atomic formulae. Some formulae are tautologies with respect to all left-continuous t-norms: they represent general laws of propositional fuzzy logic that are independent of the choice of a particular left-continuous t-norm. These formulae form the logic MTL, which can thus be characterized as the logic of left-continuous t-norms.[2]

Syntax edit

Language edit

The language of the propositional logic MTL consists of countably many propositional variables and the following primitive logical connectives:

  • Implication   (binary)
  • Strong conjunction   (binary). The sign & is a more traditional notation for strong conjunction in the literature on fuzzy logic, while the notation   follows the tradition of substructural logics.
  • Weak conjunction   (binary), also called lattice conjunction (as it is always realized by the lattice operation of meet in algebraic semantics). Unlike in BL and stronger fuzzy logics, weak conjunction is not definable in MTL and has to be included among the primitive connectives.
  • Bottom   (nullary — a propositional constant;   or   are common alternative tokens and zero a common alternative name for the propositional constant (as the constants bottom and zero of substructural logics coincide in MTL).

The following are the most common defined logical connectives:

  • Negation   (unary), defined as
 
  • Equivalence   (binary), defined as
 
In MTL, the definition is equivalent to  
  • (Weak) disjunction   (binary), also called lattice disjunction (as it is always realized by the lattice operation of join in algebraic semantics), defined as
 
  • Top   (nullary), also called one and denoted by   or   (as the constants top and zero of substructural logics coincide in MTL), defined as
 

Well-formed formulae of MTL are defined as usual in propositional logics. In order to save parentheses, it is common to use the following order of precedence:

  • Unary connectives (bind most closely)
  • Binary connectives other than implication and equivalence
  • Implication and equivalence (bind most loosely)

Axioms edit

A Hilbert-style deduction system for MTL has been introduced by Esteva and Godo (2001). Its single derivation rule is modus ponens:

from   and   derive  

The following are its axiom schemata:

 

The traditional numbering of axioms, given in the left column, is derived from the numbering of axioms of Hájek's basic fuzzy logic BL.[3] The axioms (MTL4a)–(MTL4c) replace the axiom of divisibility (BL4) of BL. The axioms (MTL5a) and (MTL5b) express the law of residuation and the axiom (MTL6) corresponds to the condition of prelinearity. The axioms (MTL2) and (MTL3) of the original axiomatic system were shown to be redundant (Chvalovský, 2012) and (Cintula, 2005). All the other axioms were shown to be independent (Chvalovský, 2012).

Semantics edit

Like in other propositional t-norm fuzzy logics, algebraic semantics is predominantly used for MTL, with three main classes of algebras with respect to which the logic is complete:

  • General semantics, formed of all MTL-algebras — that is, all algebras for which the logic is sound
  • Linear semantics, formed of all linear MTL-algebras — that is, all MTL-algebras whose lattice order is linear
  • Standard semantics, formed of all standard MTL-algebras — that is, all MTL-algebras whose lattice reduct is the real unit interval [0, 1] with the usual order; they are uniquely determined by the function that interprets strong conjunction, which can be any left-continuous t-norm

General semantics edit

MTL-algebras edit

Algebras for which the logic MTL is sound are called MTL-algebras. They can be characterized as prelinear commutative bounded integral residuated lattices. In more detail, an algebraic structure   is an MTL-algebra if

  •   is a bounded lattice with the top element 0 and bottom element 1
  •   is a commutative monoid
  •   and   form an adjoint pair, that is,   if and only if   where   is the lattice order of   for all x, y, and z in  , (the residuation condition)
  •   holds for all x and y in L (the prelinearity condition)

Important examples of MTL algebras are standard MTL-algebras on the real unit interval [0, 1]. Further examples include all Boolean algebras, all linear Heyting algebras (both with  ), all MV-algebras, all BL-algebras, etc. Since the residuation condition can equivalently be expressed by identities,[4] MTL-algebras form a variety.

Interpretation of the logic MTL in MTL-algebras edit

The connectives of MTL are interpreted in MTL-algebras as follows:

  • Strong conjunction by the monoidal operation  
  • Implication by the operation   (which is called the residuum of  )
  • Weak conjunction and weak disjunction by the lattice operations   and   respectively (usually denoted by the same symbols as the connectives, if no confusion can arise)
  • The truth constants zero (top) and one (bottom) by the constants 0 and 1
  • The equivalence connective is interpreted by the operation   defined as
 
Due to the prelinearity condition, this definition is equivalent to one that uses   instead of   thus
 
  • Negation is interpreted by the definable operation  

With this interpretation of connectives, any evaluation ev of propositional variables in L uniquely extends to an evaluation e of all well-formed formulae of MTL, by the following inductive definition (which generalizes Tarski's truth conditions), for any formulae A, B, and any propositional variable p:

 

Informally, the truth value 1 represents full truth and the truth value 0 represents full falsity; intermediate truth values represent intermediate degrees of truth. Thus a formula is considered fully true under an evaluation e if e(A) = 1. A formula A is said to be valid in an MTL-algebra L if it is fully true under all evaluations in L, that is, if e(A) = 1 for all evaluations e in L. Some formulae (for instance, pp) are valid in any MTL-algebra; these are called tautologies of MTL.

The notion of global entailment (or: global consequence) is defined for MTL as follows: a set of formulae Γ entails a formula A (or: A is a global consequence of Γ), in symbols   if for any evaluation e in any MTL-algebra, whenever e(B) = 1 for all formulae B in Γ, then also e(A) = 1. Informally, the global consequence relation represents the transmission of full truth in any MTL-algebra of truth values.

General soundness and completeness theorems edit

The logic MTL is sound and complete with respect to the class of all MTL-algebras (Esteva & Godo, 2001):

A formula is provable in MTL if and only if it is valid in all MTL-algebras.

The notion of MTL-algebra is in fact so defined that MTL-algebras form the class of all algebras for which the logic MTL is sound. Furthermore, the strong completeness theorem holds:[5]

A formula A is a global consequence in MTL of a set of formulae Γ if and only if A is derivable from Γ in MTL.

Linear semantics edit

Like algebras for other fuzzy logics,[6] MTL-algebras enjoy the following linear subdirect decomposition property:

Every MTL-algebra is a subdirect product of linearly ordered MTL-algebras.

(A subdirect product is a subalgebra of the direct product such that all projection maps are surjective. An MTL-algebra is linearly ordered if its lattice order is linear.)

In consequence of the linear subdirect decomposition property of all MTL-algebras, the completeness theorem with respect to linear MTL-algebras (Esteva & Godo, 2001) holds:

  • A formula is provable in MTL if and only if it is valid in all linear MTL-algebras.
  • A formula A is derivable in MTL from a set of formulae Γ if and only if A is a global consequence in all linear MTL-algebras of Γ.

Standard semantics edit

Standard are called those MTL-algebras whose lattice reduct is the real unit interval [0, 1]. They are uniquely determined by the real-valued function that interprets strong conjunction, which can be any left-continuous t-norm  . The standard MTL-algebra determined by a left-continuous t-norm   is usually denoted by   In   implication is represented by the residuum of   weak conjunction and disjunction respectively by the minimum and maximum, and the truth constants zero and one respectively by the real numbers 0 and 1.

The logic MTL is complete with respect to standard MTL-algebras; this fact is expressed by the standard completeness theorem (Jenei & Montagna, 2002):

A formula is provable in MTL if and only if it is valid in all standard MTL-algebras.

Since MTL is complete with respect to standard MTL-algebras, which are determined by left-continuous t-norms, MTL is often referred to as the logic of left-continuous t-norms (similarly as BL is the logic of continuous t-norms).

Bibliography edit

  • Hájek P., 1998, Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic. Dordrecht: Kluwer.
  • Esteva F. & Godo L., 2001, "Monoidal t-norm based logic: Towards a logic of left-continuous t-norms". Fuzzy Sets and Systems 124: 271–288.
  • Jenei S. & Montagna F., 2002, "A proof of standard completeness of Esteva and Godo's monoidal logic MTL". Studia Logica 70: 184–192.
  • Ono, H., 2003, "Substructural logics and residuated lattices — an introduction". In F.V. Hendricks, J. Malinowski (eds.): Trends in Logic: 50 Years of Studia Logica, Trends in Logic 20: 177–212.
  • Cintula P., 2005, "Short note: On the redundancy of axiom (A3) in BL and MTL". Soft Computing 9: 942.
  • Cintula P., 2006, "Weakly implicative (fuzzy) logics I: Basic properties". Archive for Mathematical Logic 45: 673–704.
  • Chvalovský K., 2012, "On the Independence of Axioms in BL and MTL". Fuzzy Sets and Systems 197: 123–129, doi:10.1016/j.fss.2011.10.018.

References edit

  1. ^ Ono (2003).
  2. ^ Conjectured by Esteva and Godo who introduced the logic (2001), proved by Jenei and Montagna (2002).
  3. ^ Hájek (1998), Definition 2.2.4.
  4. ^ The proof of Lemma 2.3.10 in Hájek (1998) for BL-algebras can easily be adapted to work for MTL-algebras, too.
  5. ^ A general proof of the strong completeness with respect to all L-algebras for any weakly implicative logic L (which includes MTL) can be found in Cintula (2006).
  6. ^ Cintula (2006).

monoidal, norm, logic, mathematical, logic, monoidal, norm, based, logic, shortly, logic, left, continuous, norms, norm, fuzzy, logics, belongs, broader, class, substructural, logics, logics, residuated, lattices, extends, logic, commutative, bounded, integral. In mathematical logic monoidal t norm based logic or shortly MTL the logic of left continuous t norms is one of the t norm fuzzy logics It belongs to the broader class of substructural logics or logics of residuated lattices 1 it extends the logic of commutative bounded integral residuated lattices known as Hohle s monoidal logic Ono s FLew or intuitionistic logic without contraction by the axiom of prelinearity Contents 1 Motivation 2 Syntax 2 1 Language 2 2 Axioms 3 Semantics 3 1 General semantics 3 1 1 MTL algebras 3 1 2 Interpretation of the logic MTL in MTL algebras 3 1 3 General soundness and completeness theorems 3 2 Linear semantics 3 3 Standard semantics 4 Bibliography 5 ReferencesMotivation editIn fuzzy logic rather than regarding statements as being either true or false we associate each statement with a numerical confidence in that statement By convention the confidences range over the unit interval 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 nbsp where the maximal confidence 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp corresponds to the classical concept of true and the minimal confidence 0 displaystyle 0 nbsp corresponds to the classical concept of false T norms are binary functions on the real unit interval 0 1 which in fuzzy logic are often used to represent a conjunction connective if a b 0 1 displaystyle a b in 0 1 nbsp are the confidences we ascribe to the statements A displaystyle A nbsp and B displaystyle B nbsp respectively then one uses a t norm displaystyle nbsp to calculate the confidence a b displaystyle a b nbsp ascribed to the compound statement A displaystyle A nbsp and B displaystyle B nbsp A t norm displaystyle nbsp has to satisfy the properties of commutativity a b b a displaystyle a b b a nbsp associativity a b c a b c displaystyle a b c a b c nbsp monotonicity if a b displaystyle a leqslant b nbsp and c d displaystyle c leqslant d nbsp then a c b d displaystyle a c leqslant b d nbsp and having 1 as identity element 1 a a displaystyle 1 a a nbsp Notably absent from this list is the property of idempotence a a a displaystyle a a a nbsp the closest one gets is that a a 1 a a displaystyle a a leqslant 1 a a nbsp It may seem strange to be less confident in A displaystyle A nbsp and A displaystyle A nbsp than in just A displaystyle A nbsp but we generally do want to allow for letting the confidence a b displaystyle a b nbsp in a combined A displaystyle A nbsp and B displaystyle B nbsp be less than both the confidence a displaystyle a nbsp in A displaystyle A nbsp and the confidence b displaystyle b nbsp in B displaystyle B nbsp and then the ordering a b lt a b displaystyle a b lt a leqslant b nbsp by monotonicity requires a a a b lt a displaystyle a a leqslant a b lt a nbsp Another way of putting it is that the t norm can only take into account the confidences as numbers not the reasons that may be behind ascribing those confidences thus it cannot treat A displaystyle A nbsp and A displaystyle A nbsp differently from A displaystyle A nbsp and B displaystyle B nbsp where we are equally confident in both Because the symbol displaystyle wedge nbsp via its use in lattice theory is very closely associated with the idempotence property it can be useful to switch to a different symbol for conjunction that is not necessarily idempotent In the fuzzy logic tradition one sometimes uses amp displaystyle amp nbsp for this strong conjunction but this article follows the substructural logic tradition of using displaystyle otimes nbsp for the strong conjunction thus a b displaystyle a b nbsp is the confidence we ascribe to the statement A B displaystyle A otimes B nbsp still read A displaystyle A nbsp and B displaystyle B nbsp perhaps with strong or multiplicative as qualification of the and Having formalised conjunction displaystyle otimes nbsp one wishes to continue with the other connectives One approach to doing that is to introduce negation as an order reversing map 0 1 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 longrightarrow 0 1 nbsp then defining remaining connectives using De Morgan s laws material implication and the like A problem with doing so is that the resulting logics may have undesirable properties they may be too close to classical logic or if not conversely not support expected inference rules An alternative that makes the consequences of different choices more predictable is to instead continue with implication displaystyle to nbsp as the second connective this is overall the most common connective in axiomatisations of logic and it has closer ties to the deductive aspects of logic than most other connectives A confidence counterpart displaystyle Rightarrow nbsp of the implication connective may in fact be defined directly as the residuum of the t norm The logical link between conjunction and implication is provided by something as fundamental as the inference rule modus ponens A A B B displaystyle A A to B vdash B nbsp from A displaystyle A nbsp and A B displaystyle A to B nbsp follows B displaystyle B nbsp In the fuzzy logic case that is more rigorously written as A A B B displaystyle A otimes A to B vdash B nbsp because this makes explicit that our confidence for the premise s here is that in A A B displaystyle A otimes A to B nbsp not those in A displaystyle A nbsp and A B displaystyle A to B nbsp separately So if a displaystyle a nbsp and b displaystyle b nbsp are our confidences in A displaystyle A nbsp and B displaystyle B nbsp respectively then a b displaystyle a Rightarrow b nbsp is the sought confidence in A B displaystyle A to B nbsp and a a b displaystyle a a Rightarrow b nbsp is the combined confidence in A A B displaystyle A otimes A to B nbsp We require that a a b b displaystyle a a mathbin Rightarrow b leqslant b nbsp since our confidence b displaystyle b nbsp for B displaystyle B nbsp should not be less than our confidence a a b displaystyle a a Rightarrow b nbsp in the statement A A B displaystyle A otimes A to B nbsp from which B displaystyle B nbsp logically follows This bounds the sought confidence a b displaystyle a Rightarrow b nbsp and one approach for turning displaystyle Rightarrow nbsp into a binary operation like displaystyle nbsp would be to make it as large as possible while respecting this bound a b sup x 0 1 a x b displaystyle a mathbin Rightarrow b equiv sup left x in 0 1 big a x leqslant b right nbsp Taking x 0 displaystyle x 0 nbsp gives a x a 0 1 0 0 b displaystyle a x a 0 leqslant 1 0 0 leqslant b nbsp so the supremum is always of a nonempty bounded set and thus well defined For a general t norm there remains the possibility that f a x a x displaystyle f a x a x nbsp has a jump discontinuity at x a b displaystyle x a mathbin Rightarrow b nbsp in which case a a b displaystyle a a mathbin Rightarrow b nbsp could come out strictly larger than b displaystyle b nbsp even though a b displaystyle a mathbin Rightarrow b nbsp is defined as the least upper bound of x displaystyle x nbsp s satisfying a x b displaystyle a x leqslant b nbsp to prevent that and have the construction work as expected we require that the t norm displaystyle nbsp is left continuous The residuum of a left continuous t norm thus can be characterized as the weakest function that makes the fuzzy modus ponens valid which makes it a suitable truth function for implication in fuzzy logic More algebraically we say that an operation displaystyle Rightarrow nbsp is a residuum of a t norm displaystyle nbsp if for all a displaystyle a nbsp b displaystyle b nbsp and c displaystyle c nbsp it satisfies a b c displaystyle a b leq c nbsp if and only if a b c displaystyle a leq b mathbin Rightarrow c nbsp This equivalence of numerical comparisons mirrors the equivalence of entailments A B C displaystyle A otimes B vdash C nbsp if and only if A B C displaystyle A vdash B to C nbsp that exists because any proof of C displaystyle C nbsp from the premise A B displaystyle A otimes B nbsp can be converted into a proof of B C displaystyle B to C nbsp from the premise A displaystyle A nbsp by doing an extra implication introduction step and conversely any proof of B C displaystyle B to C nbsp from the premise A displaystyle A nbsp can be converted into a proof of C displaystyle C nbsp from the premise A B displaystyle A otimes B nbsp by doing an extra implication elimination step Left continuity of the t norm is the necessary and sufficient condition for this relationship between a t norm conjunction and its residual implication to hold Truth functions of further propositional connectives can be defined by means of the t norm and its residuum for instance the residual negation x x 0 displaystyle neg x x mathbin Rightarrow 0 nbsp In this way the left continuous t norm its residuum and the truth functions of additional propositional connectives see the section Standard semantics below determine the truth values of complex propositional formulae in 0 1 Formulae that always evaluate to 1 are then called tautologies with respect to the given left continuous t norm displaystyle nbsp or displaystyle mbox nbsp tautologies The set of all displaystyle mbox nbsp tautologies is called the logic of the t norm displaystyle nbsp since these formulae represent the laws of fuzzy logic determined by the t norm that hold to degree 1 regardless of the truth degrees of atomic formulae Some formulae are tautologies with respect to all left continuous t norms they represent general laws of propositional fuzzy logic that are independent of the choice of a particular left continuous t norm These formulae form the logic MTL which can thus be characterized as the logic of left continuous t norms 2 Syntax editLanguage edit The language of the propositional logic MTL consists of countably many propositional variables and the following primitive logical connectives Implication displaystyle rightarrow nbsp binary Strong conjunction displaystyle otimes nbsp binary The sign amp is a more traditional notation for strong conjunction in the literature on fuzzy logic while the notation displaystyle otimes nbsp follows the tradition of substructural logics Weak conjunction displaystyle wedge nbsp binary also called lattice conjunction as it is always realized by the lattice operation of meet in algebraic semantics Unlike in BL and stronger fuzzy logics weak conjunction is not definable in MTL and has to be included among the primitive connectives Bottom displaystyle bot nbsp nullary a propositional constant 0 displaystyle 0 nbsp or 0 displaystyle overline 0 nbsp are common alternative tokens and zero a common alternative name for the propositional constant as the constants bottom and zero of substructural logics coincide in MTL The following are the most common defined logical connectives Negation displaystyle neg nbsp unary defined as A A displaystyle neg A equiv A rightarrow bot nbsp dd Equivalence displaystyle leftrightarrow nbsp binary defined asA B A B B A displaystyle A leftrightarrow B equiv A rightarrow B wedge B rightarrow A nbsp dd In MTL the definition is equivalent to A B B A displaystyle A rightarrow B otimes B rightarrow A nbsp Weak disjunction displaystyle vee nbsp binary also called lattice disjunction as it is always realized by the lattice operation of join in algebraic semantics defined asA B A B B B A A displaystyle A vee B equiv A rightarrow B rightarrow B wedge B rightarrow A rightarrow A nbsp dd Top displaystyle top nbsp nullary also called one and denoted by 1 displaystyle 1 nbsp or 1 displaystyle overline 1 nbsp as the constants top and zero of substructural logics coincide in MTL defined as displaystyle top equiv bot rightarrow bot nbsp dd Well formed formulae of MTL are defined as usual in propositional logics In order to save parentheses it is common to use the following order of precedence Unary connectives bind most closely Binary connectives other than implication and equivalence Implication and equivalence bind most loosely Axioms edit A Hilbert style deduction system for MTL has been introduced by Esteva and Godo 2001 Its single derivation rule is modus ponens from A displaystyle A nbsp and A B displaystyle A rightarrow B nbsp derive B displaystyle B nbsp The following are its axiom schemata M T L 1 A B B C A C M T L 2 A B A M T L 3 A B B A M T L 4 a A B A M T L 4 b A B B A M T L 4 c A A B A B M T L 5 a A B C A B C M T L 5 b A B C A B C M T L 6 A B C B A C C M T L 7 A displaystyle begin array ll rm MTL1 colon amp A rightarrow B rightarrow B rightarrow C rightarrow A rightarrow C rm MTL2 colon amp A otimes B rightarrow A rm MTL3 colon amp A otimes B rightarrow B otimes A rm MTL4a colon amp A wedge B rightarrow A rm MTL4b colon amp A wedge B rightarrow B wedge A rm MTL4c colon amp A otimes A rightarrow B rightarrow A wedge B rm MTL5a colon amp A rightarrow B rightarrow C rightarrow A otimes B rightarrow C rm MTL5b colon amp A otimes B rightarrow C rightarrow A rightarrow B rightarrow C rm MTL6 colon amp A rightarrow B rightarrow C rightarrow B rightarrow A rightarrow C rightarrow C rm MTL7 colon amp bot rightarrow A end array nbsp The traditional numbering of axioms given in the left column is derived from the numbering of axioms of Hajek s basic fuzzy logic BL 3 The axioms MTL4a MTL4c replace the axiom of divisibility BL4 of BL The axioms MTL5a and MTL5b express the law of residuation and the axiom MTL6 corresponds to the condition of prelinearity The axioms MTL2 and MTL3 of the original axiomatic system were shown to be redundant Chvalovsky 2012 and Cintula 2005 All the other axioms were shown to be independent Chvalovsky 2012 Semantics editLike in other propositional t norm fuzzy logics algebraic semantics is predominantly used for MTL with three main classes of algebras with respect to which the logic is complete General semantics formed of all MTL algebras that is all algebras for which the logic is sound Linear semantics formed of all linear MTL algebras that is all MTL algebras whose lattice order is linear Standard semantics formed of all standard MTL algebras that is all MTL algebras whose lattice reduct is the real unit interval 0 1 with the usual order they are uniquely determined by the function that interprets strong conjunction which can be any left continuous t normGeneral semantics edit MTL algebras edit Algebras for which the logic MTL is sound are called MTL algebras They can be characterized as prelinear commutative bounded integral residuated lattices In more detail an algebraic structure L 0 1 displaystyle L wedge vee ast Rightarrow 0 1 nbsp is an MTL algebra if L 0 1 displaystyle L wedge vee 0 1 nbsp is a bounded lattice with the top element 0 and bottom element 1 L 1 displaystyle L ast 1 nbsp is a commutative monoid displaystyle ast nbsp and displaystyle Rightarrow nbsp form an adjoint pair that is z x y displaystyle z x leq y nbsp if and only if z x y displaystyle z leq x Rightarrow y nbsp where displaystyle leq nbsp is the lattice order of L displaystyle L wedge vee nbsp for all x y and z in L displaystyle L nbsp the residuation condition x y y x 1 displaystyle x Rightarrow y vee y Rightarrow x 1 nbsp holds for all x and y in L the prelinearity condition Important examples of MTL algebras are standard MTL algebras on the real unit interval 0 1 Further examples include all Boolean algebras all linear Heyting algebras both with displaystyle ast wedge nbsp all MV algebras all BL algebras etc Since the residuation condition can equivalently be expressed by identities 4 MTL algebras form a variety Interpretation of the logic MTL in MTL algebras edit The connectives of MTL are interpreted in MTL algebras as follows Strong conjunction by the monoidal operation displaystyle ast nbsp Implication by the operation displaystyle Rightarrow nbsp which is called the residuum of displaystyle ast nbsp Weak conjunction and weak disjunction by the lattice operations displaystyle wedge nbsp and displaystyle vee nbsp respectively usually denoted by the same symbols as the connectives if no confusion can arise The truth constants zero top and one bottom by the constants 0 and 1 The equivalence connective is interpreted by the operation displaystyle Leftrightarrow nbsp defined asx y x y y x displaystyle x Leftrightarrow y equiv x Rightarrow y wedge y Rightarrow x nbsp dd Due to the prelinearity condition this definition is equivalent to one that uses displaystyle ast nbsp instead of displaystyle wedge nbsp thusx y x y y x displaystyle x Leftrightarrow y equiv x Rightarrow y ast y Rightarrow x nbsp dd Negation is interpreted by the definable operation x x 0 displaystyle x equiv x Rightarrow 0 nbsp With this interpretation of connectives any evaluation ev of propositional variables in L uniquely extends to an evaluation e of all well formed formulae of MTL by the following inductive definition which generalizes Tarski s truth conditions for any formulae A B and any propositional variable p e p e v p e 0 e 1 e A B e A e B e A B e A e B e A B e A e B e A B e A e B e A B e A e B e A e A 0 displaystyle begin array rcl e p amp amp e mathrm v p e bot amp amp 0 e top amp amp 1 e A otimes B amp amp e A ast e B e A rightarrow B amp amp e A Rightarrow e B e A wedge B amp amp e A wedge e B e A vee B amp amp e A vee e B e A leftrightarrow B amp amp e A Leftrightarrow e B e neg A amp amp e A Rightarrow 0 end array nbsp Informally the truth value 1 represents full truth and the truth value 0 represents full falsity intermediate truth values represent intermediate degrees of truth Thus a formula is considered fully true under an evaluation e if e A 1 A formula A is said to be valid in an MTL algebra L if it is fully true under all evaluations in L that is if e A 1 for all evaluations e in L Some formulae for instance p p are valid in any MTL algebra these are called tautologies of MTL The notion of global entailment or global consequence is defined for MTL as follows a set of formulae G entails a formula A or A is a global consequence of G in symbols G A displaystyle Gamma models A nbsp if for any evaluation e in any MTL algebra whenever e B 1 for all formulae B in G then also e A 1 Informally the global consequence relation represents the transmission of full truth in any MTL algebra of truth values General soundness and completeness theorems edit The logic MTL is sound and complete with respect to the class of all MTL algebras Esteva amp Godo 2001 A formula is provable in MTL if and only if it is valid in all MTL algebras The notion of MTL algebra is in fact so defined that MTL algebras form the class of all algebras for which the logic MTL is sound Furthermore the strong completeness theorem holds 5 A formula A is a global consequence in MTL of a set of formulae G if and only if A is derivable from G in MTL Linear semantics edit Like algebras for other fuzzy logics 6 MTL algebras enjoy the following linear subdirect decomposition property Every MTL algebra is a subdirect product of linearly ordered MTL algebras A subdirect product is a subalgebra of the direct product such that all projection maps are surjective An MTL algebra is linearly ordered if its lattice order is linear In consequence of the linear subdirect decomposition property of all MTL algebras the completeness theorem with respect to linear MTL algebras Esteva amp Godo 2001 holds A formula is provable in MTL if and only if it is valid in all linear MTL algebras A formula A is derivable in MTL from a set of formulae G if and only if A is a global consequence in all linear MTL algebras of G Standard semantics edit Standard are called those MTL algebras whose lattice reduct is the real unit interval 0 1 They are uniquely determined by the real valued function that interprets strong conjunction which can be any left continuous t norm displaystyle ast nbsp The standard MTL algebra determined by a left continuous t norm displaystyle ast nbsp is usually denoted by 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 ast nbsp In 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 ast nbsp implication is represented by the residuum of displaystyle ast nbsp weak conjunction and disjunction respectively by the minimum and maximum and the truth constants zero and one respectively by the real numbers 0 and 1 The logic MTL is complete with respect to standard MTL algebras this fact is expressed by the standard completeness theorem Jenei amp Montagna 2002 A formula is provable in MTL if and only if it is valid in all standard MTL algebras Since MTL is complete with respect to standard MTL algebras which are determined by left continuous t norms MTL is often referred to as the logic of left continuous t norms similarly as BL is the logic of continuous t norms Bibliography editHajek P 1998 Metamathematics of Fuzzy Logic Dordrecht Kluwer Esteva F amp Godo L 2001 Monoidal t norm based logic Towards a logic of left continuous t norms Fuzzy Sets and Systems 124 271 288 Jenei S amp Montagna F 2002 A proof of standard completeness of Esteva and Godo s monoidal logic MTL Studia Logica 70 184 192 Ono H 2003 Substructural logics and residuated lattices an introduction In F V Hendricks J Malinowski eds Trends in Logic 50 Years of Studia Logica Trends in Logic 20 177 212 Cintula P 2005 Short note On the redundancy of axiom A3 in BL and MTL Soft Computing 9 942 Cintula P 2006 Weakly implicative fuzzy logics I Basic properties Archive for Mathematical Logic 45 673 704 Chvalovsky K 2012 On the Independence of Axioms in BL and MTL Fuzzy Sets and Systems 197 123 129 doi 10 1016 j fss 2011 10 018 References edit Ono 2003 Conjectured by Esteva and Godo who introduced the logic 2001 proved by Jenei and Montagna 2002 Hajek 1998 Definition 2 2 4 The proof of Lemma 2 3 10 in Hajek 1998 for BL algebras can easily be adapted to work for MTL algebras too A general proof of the strong completeness with respect to all L algebras for any weakly implicative logic L which includes MTL can be found in Cintula 2006 Cintula 2006 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Monoidal t norm logic amp oldid 1148062469, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.