fbpx
Wikipedia

Mertens-stable equilibrium

In game theory, Mertens stability is a solution concept used to predict the outcome of a non-cooperative game. A tentative definition of stability was proposed by Elon Kohlberg and Jean-François Mertens[1] for games with finite numbers of players and strategies. Later, Mertens[2][3] proposed a stronger definition that was elaborated further by Srihari Govindan and Mertens.[4] This solution concept is now called Mertens stability, or just stability.

Like other refinements of Nash equilibrium[5] used in game theory stability selects subsets of the set of Nash equilibria that have desirable properties. Stability invokes stronger criteria than other refinements, and thereby ensures that more desirable properties are satisfied.

Desirable Properties of a Refinement edit

Refinements have often been motivated by arguments for admissibility, backward induction, and forward induction. In a two-player game, an admissible decision rule for a player is one that does not use any strategy that is weakly dominated by another (see Strategic dominance). Backward induction posits that a player's optimal action in any event anticipates that his and others' subsequent actions are optimal. The refinement called subgame perfect equilibrium implements a weak version of backward induction, and increasingly stronger versions are sequential equilibrium, perfect equilibrium, quasi-perfect equilibrium, and proper equilibrium. Forward induction posits that a player's optimal action in any event presumes the optimality of others' past actions whenever that is consistent with his observations. Forward induction[6] is satisfied by a sequential equilibrium for which a player's belief at an information set assigns probability only to others' optimal strategies that enable that information to be reached.

Kohlberg and Mertens emphasized further that a solution concept should satisfy the invariance principle that it not depend on which among the many equivalent representations of the strategic situation as an extensive-form game is used. Thus it should depend only on the reduced normal-form game obtained after elimination of pure strategies that are redundant because their payoffs for all players can be replicated by a mixture of other pure strategies. Mertens[7][8] emphasized also the importance of the small worlds principle that a solution concept should depend only on the ordinal properties of players' preferences, and should not depend on whether the game includes extraneous players whose actions have no effect on the original players' feasible strategies and payoffs.

Kohlberg and Mertens demonstrated via examples that not all of these properties can be obtained from a solution concept that selects single Nash equilibria. Therefore, they proposed that a solution concept should select closed connected subsets of the set of Nash equilibria.[9]

Properties of Stable Sets edit

  • Admissibility and Perfection: Each equilibrium in a stable set is perfect, and therefore admissible.
  • Backward Induction and Forward Induction: A stable set includes a proper equilibrium of the normal form of the game that induces a quasi-perfect and therefore a sequential equilibrium in every extensive-form game with perfect recall that has the same normal form. A subset of a stable set survives iterative elimination of weakly dominated strategies and strategies that are inferior replies at every equilibrium in the set.
  • Invariance and Small Worlds: The stable sets of a game are the projections of the stable sets of any larger game in which it is embedded while preserving the original players' feasible strategies and payoffs.[10]
  • Decomposition and Player Splitting. The stable sets of the product of two independent games are the products of their stable sets. Stable sets are not affected by splitting a player into agents such that no path through the game tree includes actions of two agents.

For two-player games with perfect recall and generic payoffs, stability is equivalent to just three of these properties: a stable set uses only undominated strategies, includes a quasi-perfect equilibrium, and is immune to embedding in a larger game.[11]

Definition of a Stable Set edit

A stable set is defined mathematically by essentiality of the projection map from a closed connected neighborhood in the graph of the Nash equilibria over the space of perturbed games obtained by perturbing players' strategies toward completely mixed strategies. This definition requires more than every nearby game having a nearby equilibrium. Essentiality requires further that no deformation of the projection maps to the boundary, which ensures that perturbations of the fixed point problem defining Nash equilibria have nearby solutions. This is apparently necessary to obtain all the desirable properties listed above.

Mertens provided several formal definitions depending on the coefficient module used for homology or cohomology.

A formal definition requires some notation. For a given game   let   be product of the simplices of the players' of mixed strategies. For each  , let   and let   be its topological boundary. For   let   be the minimum probability of any pure strategy. For any   define the perturbed game   as the game where the strategy set of each player   is the same as in  , but where the payoff from a strategy profile   is the payoff in   from the profile  . Say that   is a perturbed equilibrium of   if   is an equilibrium of  . Let   be the graph of the perturbed equilibrium correspondence over  , viz., the graph   is the set of those pairs   such that   is a perturbed equilibrium of  . For  ,   is the corresponding equilibrium of  . Denote by   the natural projection map from   to  . For  , let  , and for   let  . Finally,   refers to Čech cohomology with integer coefficients.

The following is a version of the most inclusive of Mertens' definitions, called *-stability.

Definition of a *-stable set:   is a *-stable set if for some closed subset   of   with   it has the following two properties:

  • Connectedness: For every neighborhood   of   in  , the set   has a connected component whose closure is a neighborhood of   in  .
  • Cohomological Essentiality:   is nonzero for some  .

If essentiality in cohomology or homology is relaxed to homotopy, then a weaker definition is obtained, which differs chiefly in a weaker form of the decomposition property.[12]

References edit

  1. ^ Kohlberg, Elon; Mertens, Jean-François (1986). "On the Strategic Stability of Equilibria" (PDF). Econometrica. 54 (5): 1003–1037. CiteSeerX 10.1.1.295.4592. doi:10.2307/1912320. JSTOR 1912320.
  2. ^ Mertens, Jean-François (1989). "Stable Equilibria—A Reformulation Part I. Definition and basic properties". Mathematics of Operations Research. 14 (4): 575–625. doi:10.1287/moor.14.4.575. JSTOR 3689732.
  3. ^ Mertens, Jean-François (1991). "Stable Equilibria—A Reformulation Part II. Discussion of the definition, and further results". Mathematics of Operations Research. 16 (4): 694–753. doi:10.1287/moor.16.4.694. JSTOR 3689907.
  4. ^ Govindan, Srihari; Mertens, Jean-François (2004). "An Equivalent Definition of Stable Equilibria". International Journal of Game Theory. 32 (3): 339–357. doi:10.1007/s001820400165. hdl:10.1007/s001820400165.
  5. ^ Govindan, Srihari & Robert Wilson, 2008. "Refinements of Nash Equilibrium," The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics, 2nd edition. (PDF). Archived from the original (PDF) on 2010-06-20. Retrieved 2012-02-12.{{cite web}}: CS1 maint: archived copy as title (link)
  6. ^ Govindan, Srihari; Wilson, Robert (2009). "On Forward Induction". Econometrica. 77 (1): 1–28. doi:10.3982/ECTA6956.
  7. ^ Mertens, Jean-François (2003). "Ordinality in Non Cooperative Games". International Journal of Game Theory. 32: 387–430. doi:10.1007/s001820400166.
  8. ^ Mertens, Jean-François (1992). "The Small Worlds Axiom for Stable Equilibria". Games and Economic Behavior. 4 (4): 553–564. doi:10.1016/0899-8256(92)90036-R.
  9. ^ The requirement that the set is connected excludes the trivial refinement that selects all equilibria. If only a single (possibly unconnected) subset is selected then only the trivial refinement satisfies the conditions invoked by Norde, Henk; Potters, Jos; Reijnierse, Hans; Vermeulen, Dries (1996). "Equilibrium Selection and Consistency". Games and Economic Behavior. 12 (2): 219–225. doi:10.1006/game.1996.0014. hdl:2066/27895.
  10. ^ See Appendix D of Govindan & Wilson (2012)
  11. ^ Govindan, Srihari; Wilson, Robert (2012). "Axiomatic Theory of Equilibrium Selection for Generic Two-Player Games" (PDF). Econometrica. 80 (4): 1639–1699. doi:10.3982/ECTA9579.
  12. ^ Govindan, Srihari; Wilson, Robert (2008). "Metastable Equilibria". Mathematics of Operations Research. 33 (4): 787–820. doi:10.1287/moor.1080.0336.

mertens, stable, equilibrium, game, theory, mertens, stability, solution, concept, used, predict, outcome, cooperative, game, tentative, definition, stability, proposed, elon, kohlberg, jean, françois, mertens, games, with, finite, numbers, players, strategies. In game theory Mertens stability is a solution concept used to predict the outcome of a non cooperative game A tentative definition of stability was proposed by Elon Kohlberg and Jean Francois Mertens 1 for games with finite numbers of players and strategies Later Mertens 2 3 proposed a stronger definition that was elaborated further by Srihari Govindan and Mertens 4 This solution concept is now called Mertens stability or just stability Like other refinements of Nash equilibrium 5 used in game theory stability selects subsets of the set of Nash equilibria that have desirable properties Stability invokes stronger criteria than other refinements and thereby ensures that more desirable properties are satisfied Contents 1 Desirable Properties of a Refinement 2 Properties of Stable Sets 3 Definition of a Stable Set 4 ReferencesDesirable Properties of a Refinement editRefinements have often been motivated by arguments for admissibility backward induction and forward induction In a two player game an admissible decision rule for a player is one that does not use any strategy that is weakly dominated by another see Strategic dominance Backward induction posits that a player s optimal action in any event anticipates that his and others subsequent actions are optimal The refinement called subgame perfect equilibrium implements a weak version of backward induction and increasingly stronger versions are sequential equilibrium perfect equilibrium quasi perfect equilibrium and proper equilibrium Forward induction posits that a player s optimal action in any event presumes the optimality of others past actions whenever that is consistent with his observations Forward induction 6 is satisfied by a sequential equilibrium for which a player s belief at an information set assigns probability only to others optimal strategies that enable that information to be reached Kohlberg and Mertens emphasized further that a solution concept should satisfy the invariance principle that it not depend on which among the many equivalent representations of the strategic situation as an extensive form game is used Thus it should depend only on the reduced normal form game obtained after elimination of pure strategies that are redundant because their payoffs for all players can be replicated by a mixture of other pure strategies Mertens 7 8 emphasized also the importance of the small worlds principle that a solution concept should depend only on the ordinal properties of players preferences and should not depend on whether the game includes extraneous players whose actions have no effect on the original players feasible strategies and payoffs Kohlberg and Mertens demonstrated via examples that not all of these properties can be obtained from a solution concept that selects single Nash equilibria Therefore they proposed that a solution concept should select closed connected subsets of the set of Nash equilibria 9 Properties of Stable Sets editAdmissibility and Perfection Each equilibrium in a stable set is perfect and therefore admissible Backward Induction and Forward Induction A stable set includes a proper equilibrium of the normal form of the game that induces a quasi perfect and therefore a sequential equilibrium in every extensive form game with perfect recall that has the same normal form A subset of a stable set survives iterative elimination of weakly dominated strategies and strategies that are inferior replies at every equilibrium in the set Invariance and Small Worlds The stable sets of a game are the projections of the stable sets of any larger game in which it is embedded while preserving the original players feasible strategies and payoffs 10 Decomposition and Player Splitting The stable sets of the product of two independent games are the products of their stable sets Stable sets are not affected by splitting a player into agents such that no path through the game tree includes actions of two agents For two player games with perfect recall and generic payoffs stability is equivalent to just three of these properties a stable set uses only undominated strategies includes a quasi perfect equilibrium and is immune to embedding in a larger game 11 Definition of a Stable Set editA stable set is defined mathematically by essentiality of the projection map from a closed connected neighborhood in the graph of the Nash equilibria over the space of perturbed games obtained by perturbing players strategies toward completely mixed strategies This definition requires more than every nearby game having a nearby equilibrium Essentiality requires further that no deformation of the projection maps to the boundary which ensures that perturbations of the fixed point problem defining Nash equilibria have nearby solutions This is apparently necessary to obtain all the desirable properties listed above Mertens provided several formal definitions depending on the coefficient module used for homology or cohomology A formal definition requires some notation For a given game G displaystyle G nbsp let S displaystyle Sigma nbsp be product of the simplices of the players of mixed strategies For each 0 lt d 1 displaystyle 0 lt delta leq 1 nbsp let P d ϵ t 0 ϵ d t S displaystyle P delta epsilon tau mid 0 leq epsilon leq delta tau in Sigma nbsp and let P d displaystyle partial P delta nbsp be its topological boundary For h P 1 displaystyle eta in P 1 nbsp let h displaystyle bar eta nbsp be the minimum probability of any pure strategy For any h P 1 displaystyle eta in P 1 nbsp define the perturbed game G h displaystyle G eta nbsp as the game where the strategy set of each player n displaystyle n nbsp is the same as in G displaystyle G nbsp but where the payoff from a strategy profile t displaystyle tau nbsp is the payoff in G displaystyle G nbsp from the profile s 1 h t h displaystyle sigma 1 bar eta tau eta nbsp Say that s displaystyle sigma nbsp is a perturbed equilibrium of G h displaystyle G eta nbsp if t displaystyle tau nbsp is an equilibrium of G h displaystyle G eta nbsp Let E displaystyle mathcal E nbsp be the graph of the perturbed equilibrium correspondence over P 1 displaystyle P 1 nbsp viz the graph E displaystyle mathcal E nbsp is the set of those pairs h s P 1 S displaystyle eta sigma in P 1 times Sigma nbsp such that s displaystyle sigma nbsp is a perturbed equilibrium of G h displaystyle G eta nbsp For h s E displaystyle eta sigma in mathcal E nbsp t h s s h 1 h displaystyle tau eta sigma equiv sigma eta 1 bar eta nbsp is the corresponding equilibrium of G h displaystyle G eta nbsp Denote by p displaystyle p nbsp the natural projection map from E displaystyle mathcal E nbsp to P 1 displaystyle P 1 nbsp For E E displaystyle E subseteq mathcal E nbsp let E 0 0 s E displaystyle E 0 0 sigma in E nbsp and for 0 lt d 1 displaystyle 0 lt delta leq 1 nbsp let E d E d p 1 P d P d E displaystyle E delta partial E delta p 1 P delta partial P delta cap E nbsp Finally H ˇ displaystyle check H nbsp refers to Cech cohomology with integer coefficients The following is a version of the most inclusive of Mertens definitions called stability Definition of a stable set S S displaystyle S subseteq Sigma nbsp is a stable set if for some closed subset E displaystyle E nbsp of E displaystyle mathcal E nbsp with E 0 0 S displaystyle E 0 0 times S nbsp it has the following two properties Connectedness For every neighborhood V displaystyle V nbsp of E 0 displaystyle E 0 nbsp in E displaystyle E nbsp the set V E 1 displaystyle V setminus partial E 1 nbsp has a connected component whose closure is a neighborhood of E 0 displaystyle E 0 nbsp in E displaystyle E nbsp Cohomological Essentiality p H ˇ P d P d H ˇ E d E d displaystyle p check H P delta partial P delta to check H E delta partial E delta nbsp is nonzero for some d gt 0 displaystyle delta gt 0 nbsp If essentiality in cohomology or homology is relaxed to homotopy then a weaker definition is obtained which differs chiefly in a weaker form of the decomposition property 12 References edit Kohlberg Elon Mertens Jean Francois 1986 On the Strategic Stability of Equilibria PDF Econometrica 54 5 1003 1037 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 295 4592 doi 10 2307 1912320 JSTOR 1912320 Mertens Jean Francois 1989 Stable Equilibria A Reformulation Part I Definition and basic properties Mathematics of Operations Research 14 4 575 625 doi 10 1287 moor 14 4 575 JSTOR 3689732 Mertens Jean Francois 1991 Stable Equilibria A Reformulation Part II Discussion of the definition and further results Mathematics of Operations Research 16 4 694 753 doi 10 1287 moor 16 4 694 JSTOR 3689907 Govindan Srihari Mertens Jean Francois 2004 An Equivalent Definition of Stable Equilibria International Journal of Game Theory 32 3 339 357 doi 10 1007 s001820400165 hdl 10 1007 s001820400165 Govindan Srihari amp Robert Wilson 2008 Refinements of Nash Equilibrium The New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics 2nd edition Archived copy PDF Archived from the original PDF on 2010 06 20 Retrieved 2012 02 12 a href Template Cite web html title Template Cite web cite web a CS1 maint archived copy as title link Govindan Srihari Wilson Robert 2009 On Forward Induction Econometrica 77 1 1 28 doi 10 3982 ECTA6956 Mertens Jean Francois 2003 Ordinality in Non Cooperative Games International Journal of Game Theory 32 387 430 doi 10 1007 s001820400166 Mertens Jean Francois 1992 The Small Worlds Axiom for Stable Equilibria Games and Economic Behavior 4 4 553 564 doi 10 1016 0899 8256 92 90036 R The requirement that the set is connected excludes the trivial refinement that selects all equilibria If only a single possibly unconnected subset is selected then only the trivial refinement satisfies the conditions invoked by Norde Henk Potters Jos Reijnierse Hans Vermeulen Dries 1996 Equilibrium Selection and Consistency Games and Economic Behavior 12 2 219 225 doi 10 1006 game 1996 0014 hdl 2066 27895 See Appendix D of Govindan amp Wilson 2012 Govindan Srihari Wilson Robert 2012 Axiomatic Theory of Equilibrium Selection for Generic Two Player Games PDF Econometrica 80 4 1639 1699 doi 10 3982 ECTA9579 Govindan Srihari Wilson Robert 2008 Metastable Equilibria Mathematics of Operations Research 33 4 787 820 doi 10 1287 moor 1080 0336 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Mertens stable equilibrium amp oldid 1193723216, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.