fbpx
Wikipedia

Large cardinal

In the mathematical field of set theory, a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of transfinite cardinal numbers. Cardinals with such properties are, as the name suggests, generally very "large" (for example, bigger than the least α such that α=ωα). The proposition that such cardinals exist cannot be proved in the most common axiomatization of set theory, namely ZFC, and such propositions can be viewed as ways of measuring how "much", beyond ZFC, one needs to assume to be able to prove certain desired results. In other words, they can be seen, in Dana Scott's phrase, as quantifying the fact "that if you want more you have to assume more".[1]

There is a rough convention that results provable from ZFC alone may be stated without hypotheses, but that if the proof requires other assumptions (such as the existence of large cardinals), these should be stated. Whether this is simply a linguistic convention, or something more, is a controversial point among distinct philosophical schools (see Motivations and epistemic status below).

A large cardinal axiom is an axiom stating that there exists a cardinal (or perhaps many of them) with some specified large cardinal property.

Most working set theorists believe that the large cardinal axioms that are currently being considered are consistent with ZFC.[citation needed] These axioms are strong enough to imply the consistency of ZFC. This has the consequence (via Gödel's second incompleteness theorem) that their consistency with ZFC cannot be proven in ZFC (assuming ZFC is consistent).

There is no generally agreed precise definition of what a large cardinal property is, though essentially everyone agrees that those in the list of large cardinal properties are large cardinal properties.

Partial definition edit

A necessary condition for a property of cardinal numbers to be a large cardinal property is that the existence of such a cardinal is not known to be inconsistent with ZF and that such a cardinal Κ would be an uncountable initial ordinal for which LΚ is a model of ZFC. If ZFC is consistent, then ZFC does not imply that any such large cardinals exist.

Hierarchy of consistency strength edit

A remarkable observation about large cardinal axioms is that they appear to occur in strict linear order by consistency strength. That is, no exception is known to the following: Given two large cardinal axioms A1 and A2, exactly one of three things happens:

  1. Unless ZFC is inconsistent, ZFC+A1 is consistent if and only if ZFC+A2 is consistent;
  2. ZFC+A1 proves that ZFC+A2 is consistent; or
  3. ZFC+A2 proves that ZFC+A1 is consistent.

These are mutually exclusive, unless one of the theories in question is actually inconsistent.

In case 1, we say that A1 and A2 are equiconsistent. In case 2, we say that A1 is consistency-wise stronger than A2 (vice versa for case 3). If A2 is stronger than A1, then ZFC+A1 cannot prove ZFC+A2 is consistent, even with the additional hypothesis that ZFC+A1 is itself consistent (provided of course that it really is). This follows from Gödel's second incompleteness theorem.

The observation that large cardinal axioms are linearly ordered by consistency strength is just that, an observation, not a theorem. (Without an accepted definition of large cardinal property, it is not subject to proof in the ordinary sense.) Also, it is not known in every case which of the three cases holds. Saharon Shelah has asked, "[i]s there some theorem explaining this, or is our vision just more uniform than we realize?" Woodin, however, deduces this from the Ω-conjecture, the main unsolved problem of his Ω-logic. It is also noteworthy that many combinatorial statements are exactly equiconsistent with some large cardinal rather than, say, being intermediate between them.

The order of consistency strength is not necessarily the same as the order of the size of the smallest witness to a large cardinal axiom. For example, the existence of a huge cardinal is much stronger, in terms of consistency strength, than the existence of a supercompact cardinal, but assuming both exist, the first huge is smaller than the first supercompact.

Motivations and epistemic status edit

Large cardinals are understood in the context of the von Neumann universe V, which is built up by transfinitely iterating the powerset operation, which collects together all subsets of a given set. Typically, models in which large cardinal axioms fail can be seen in some natural way as submodels of those in which the axioms hold. For example, if there is an inaccessible cardinal, then "cutting the universe off" at the height of the first such cardinal yields a universe in which there is no inaccessible cardinal. Or if there is a measurable cardinal, then iterating the definable powerset operation rather than the full one yields Gödel's constructible universe, L, which does not satisfy the statement "there is a measurable cardinal" (even though it contains the measurable cardinal as an ordinal).

Thus, from a certain point of view held by many set theorists (especially those inspired by the tradition of the Cabal), large cardinal axioms "say" that we are considering all the sets we're "supposed" to be considering, whereas their negations are "restrictive" and say that we're considering only some of those sets. Moreover the consequences of large cardinal axioms seem to fall into natural patterns (see Maddy, "Believing the Axioms, II"). For these reasons, such set theorists tend to consider large cardinal axioms to have a preferred status among extensions of ZFC, one not shared by axioms of less clear motivation (such as Martin's axiom) or others that they consider intuitively unlikely (such as V = L). The hardcore realists in this group would state, more simply, that large cardinal axioms are true.

This point of view is by no means universal among set theorists. Some formalists would assert that standard set theory is by definition the study of the consequences of ZFC, and while they might not be opposed in principle to studying the consequences of other systems, they see no reason to single out large cardinals as preferred. There are also realists who deny that ontological maximalism is a proper motivation, and even believe that large cardinal axioms are false. And finally, there are some who deny that the negations of large cardinal axioms are restrictive, pointing out that (for example) there can be a transitive set model in L that believes there exists a measurable cardinal, even though L itself does not satisfy that proposition.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Bell, J. L. (1985). Boolean-Valued Models and Independence Proofs in Set Theory. Oxford University Press. viii. ISBN 0-19-853241-5.

References edit

  • Drake, F. R. (1974). Set Theory: An Introduction to Large Cardinals (Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics ; V. 76). Elsevier Science Ltd. ISBN 0-444-10535-2.
  • Jech, Thomas (2002). Set theory, third millennium edition (revised and expanded). Springer. ISBN 3-540-44085-2.
  • Kanamori, Akihiro (2003). The Higher Infinite : Large Cardinals in Set Theory from Their Beginnings (2nd ed.). Springer. ISBN 3-540-00384-3.
  • Kanamori, Akihiro; Magidor, M. (1978), "The evolution of large cardinal axioms in set theory" (PDF), Higher Set Theory, Lecture Notes in Mathematics, vol. 669, Springer Berlin / Heidelberg, pp. 99–275, doi:10.1007/BFb0103104, ISBN 978-3-540-08926-1, retrieved September 25, 2022
  • Maddy, Penelope (1988). "Believing the Axioms, I". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 53 (2): 481–511. doi:10.2307/2274520. JSTOR 2274520.
  • Maddy, Penelope (1988). "Believing the Axioms, II". Journal of Symbolic Logic. 53 (3): 736–764. doi:10.2307/2274569. JSTOR 2274569. S2CID 16544090.
  • Shelah, Saharon (2002). "The Future of Set Theory". arXiv:math/0211397.
  • Solovay, Robert M.; William N. Reinhardt; Akihiro Kanamori (1978). "Strong axioms of infinity and elementary embeddings" (PDF). Annals of Mathematical Logic. 13 (1): 73–116. doi:10.1016/0003-4843(78)90031-1.
  • Woodin, W. Hugh (2001). "The continuum hypothesis, part II". Notices of the American Mathematical Society. 48 (7): 681–690.

External links edit

large, cardinal, mathematical, field, theory, large, cardinal, property, certain, kind, property, transfinite, cardinal, numbers, cardinals, with, such, properties, name, suggests, generally, very, large, example, bigger, than, least, such, that, ωα, propositi. In the mathematical field of set theory a large cardinal property is a certain kind of property of transfinite cardinal numbers Cardinals with such properties are as the name suggests generally very large for example bigger than the least a such that a wa The proposition that such cardinals exist cannot be proved in the most common axiomatization of set theory namely ZFC and such propositions can be viewed as ways of measuring how much beyond ZFC one needs to assume to be able to prove certain desired results In other words they can be seen in Dana Scott s phrase as quantifying the fact that if you want more you have to assume more 1 There is a rough convention that results provable from ZFC alone may be stated without hypotheses but that if the proof requires other assumptions such as the existence of large cardinals these should be stated Whether this is simply a linguistic convention or something more is a controversial point among distinct philosophical schools see Motivations and epistemic status below A large cardinal axiom is an axiom stating that there exists a cardinal or perhaps many of them with some specified large cardinal property Most working set theorists believe that the large cardinal axioms that are currently being considered are consistent with ZFC citation needed These axioms are strong enough to imply the consistency of ZFC This has the consequence via Godel s second incompleteness theorem that their consistency with ZFC cannot be proven in ZFC assuming ZFC is consistent There is no generally agreed precise definition of what a large cardinal property is though essentially everyone agrees that those in the list of large cardinal properties are large cardinal properties Contents 1 Partial definition 2 Hierarchy of consistency strength 3 Motivations and epistemic status 4 See also 5 Notes 6 References 7 External linksPartial definition editA necessary condition for a property of cardinal numbers to be a large cardinal property is that the existence of such a cardinal is not known to be inconsistent with ZF and that such a cardinal K would be an uncountable initial ordinal for which LK is a model of ZFC If ZFC is consistent then ZFC does not imply that any such large cardinals exist Hierarchy of consistency strength editA remarkable observation about large cardinal axioms is that they appear to occur in strict linear order by consistency strength That is no exception is known to the following Given two large cardinal axioms A1 and A2 exactly one of three things happens Unless ZFC is inconsistent ZFC A1 is consistent if and only if ZFC A2 is consistent ZFC A1 proves that ZFC A2 is consistent or ZFC A2 proves that ZFC A1 is consistent These are mutually exclusive unless one of the theories in question is actually inconsistent In case 1 we say that A1 and A2 are equiconsistent In case 2 we say that A1 is consistency wise stronger than A2 vice versa for case 3 If A2 is stronger than A1 then ZFC A1 cannot prove ZFC A2 is consistent even with the additional hypothesis that ZFC A1 is itself consistent provided of course that it really is This follows from Godel s second incompleteness theorem The observation that large cardinal axioms are linearly ordered by consistency strength is just that an observation not a theorem Without an accepted definition of large cardinal property it is not subject to proof in the ordinary sense Also it is not known in every case which of the three cases holds Saharon Shelah has asked i s there some theorem explaining this or is our vision just more uniform than we realize Woodin however deduces this from the W conjecture the main unsolved problem of his W logic It is also noteworthy that many combinatorial statements are exactly equiconsistent with some large cardinal rather than say being intermediate between them The order of consistency strength is not necessarily the same as the order of the size of the smallest witness to a large cardinal axiom For example the existence of a huge cardinal is much stronger in terms of consistency strength than the existence of a supercompact cardinal but assuming both exist the first huge is smaller than the first supercompact Motivations and epistemic status editLarge cardinals are understood in the context of the von Neumann universe V which is built up by transfinitely iterating the powerset operation which collects together all subsets of a given set Typically models in which large cardinal axioms fail can be seen in some natural way as submodels of those in which the axioms hold For example if there is an inaccessible cardinal then cutting the universe off at the height of the first such cardinal yields a universe in which there is no inaccessible cardinal Or if there is a measurable cardinal then iterating the definable powerset operation rather than the full one yields Godel s constructible universe L which does not satisfy the statement there is a measurable cardinal even though it contains the measurable cardinal as an ordinal Thus from a certain point of view held by many set theorists especially those inspired by the tradition of the Cabal large cardinal axioms say that we are considering all the sets we re supposed to be considering whereas their negations are restrictive and say that we re considering only some of those sets Moreover the consequences of large cardinal axioms seem to fall into natural patterns see Maddy Believing the Axioms II For these reasons such set theorists tend to consider large cardinal axioms to have a preferred status among extensions of ZFC one not shared by axioms of less clear motivation such as Martin s axiom or others that they consider intuitively unlikely such as V L The hardcore realists in this group would state more simply that large cardinal axioms are true This point of view is by no means universal among set theorists Some formalists would assert that standard set theory is by definition the study of the consequences of ZFC and while they might not be opposed in principle to studying the consequences of other systems they see no reason to single out large cardinals as preferred There are also realists who deny that ontological maximalism is a proper motivation and even believe that large cardinal axioms are false And finally there are some who deny that the negations of large cardinal axioms are restrictive pointing out that for example there can be a transitive set model in L that believes there exists a measurable cardinal even though L itself does not satisfy that proposition See also editList of large cardinal propertiesNotes edit Bell J L 1985 Boolean Valued Models and Independence Proofs in Set Theory Oxford University Press viii ISBN 0 19 853241 5 References editDrake F R 1974 Set Theory An Introduction to Large Cardinals Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics V 76 Elsevier Science Ltd ISBN 0 444 10535 2 Jech Thomas 2002 Set theory third millennium edition revised and expanded Springer ISBN 3 540 44085 2 Kanamori Akihiro 2003 The Higher Infinite Large Cardinals in Set Theory from Their Beginnings 2nd ed Springer ISBN 3 540 00384 3 Kanamori Akihiro Magidor M 1978 The evolution of large cardinal axioms in set theory PDF Higher Set Theory Lecture Notes in Mathematics vol 669 Springer Berlin Heidelberg pp 99 275 doi 10 1007 BFb0103104 ISBN 978 3 540 08926 1 retrieved September 25 2022 Maddy Penelope 1988 Believing the Axioms I Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 2 481 511 doi 10 2307 2274520 JSTOR 2274520 Maddy Penelope 1988 Believing the Axioms II Journal of Symbolic Logic 53 3 736 764 doi 10 2307 2274569 JSTOR 2274569 S2CID 16544090 Shelah Saharon 2002 The Future of Set Theory arXiv math 0211397 Solovay Robert M William N Reinhardt Akihiro Kanamori 1978 Strong axioms of infinity and elementary embeddings PDF Annals of Mathematical Logic 13 1 73 116 doi 10 1016 0003 4843 78 90031 1 Woodin W Hugh 2001 The continuum hypothesis part II Notices of the American Mathematical Society 48 7 681 690 External links edit Large Cardinals and Determinacy at the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Large cardinal amp oldid 1187450968, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.