fbpx
Wikipedia

Hyperarithmetical theory

In computability theory, hyperarithmetic theory is a generalization of Turing computability. It has close connections with definability in second-order arithmetic and with weak systems of set theory such as Kripke–Platek set theory. It is an important tool in effective descriptive set theory.[1]

The central focus of hyperarithmetic theory is the sets of natural numbers known as hyperarithmetic sets. There are three equivalent ways of defining this class of sets; the study of the relationships between these different definitions is one motivation for the study of hyperarithmetical theory.

Hyperarithmetical sets and definability edit

The first definition of the hyperarithmetic sets uses the analytical hierarchy. A set of natural numbers is classified at level   of this hierarchy if it is definable by a formula of second-order arithmetic with only existential set quantifiers and no other set quantifiers. A set is classified at level   of the analytical hierarchy if it is definable by a formula of second-order arithmetic with only universal set quantifiers and no other set quantifiers. A set is   if it is both   and  . The hyperarithmetical sets are exactly the   sets.

Hyperarithmetical sets and iterated Turing jumps: the hyperarithmetical hierarchy edit

The definition of hyperarithmetical sets as   does not directly depend on computability results. A second, equivalent, definition shows that the hyperarithmetical sets can be defined using infinitely iterated Turing jumps. This second definition also shows that the hyperarithmetical sets can be classified into a hierarchy extending the arithmetical hierarchy; the hyperarithmetical sets are exactly the sets that are assigned a rank in this hierarchy.

Each level of the hyperarithmetical hierarchy is indexed by a countable ordinal number (ordinal), but not all countable ordinals correspond to a level of the hierarchy. The ordinals used by the hierarchy are those with an ordinal notation, which is a concrete, effective description of the ordinal.

An ordinal notation is an effective description of a countable ordinal by a natural number. A system of ordinal notations is required in order to define the hyperarithmetic hierarchy. The fundamental property an ordinal notation must have is that it describes the ordinal in terms of smaller ordinals in an effective way. The following inductive definition is typical; it uses a pairing function  .

  • The number 0 is a notation for the ordinal 0.
  • If n is a notation for an ordinal λ then   is a notation for λ + 1;
  • Suppose that δ is a limit ordinal. A notation for δ is a number of the form  , where e is the index of a total computable function   such that for each n,   is a notation for an ordinal λn less than δ and δ is the sup of the set  .

This may also be defined by taking effective joins at all levels instead of only notations for limit ordinals.[2]

There are only countably many ordinal notations, since each notation is a natural number; thus there is a countable ordinal that is the supremum of all ordinals that have a notation. This ordinal is known as the Church–Kleene ordinal and is denoted  . Note that this ordinal is still countable, the symbol being only an analogy with the first uncountable ordinal,  . The set of all natural numbers that are ordinal notations is denoted   and called Kleene's  .

Ordinal notations are used to define iterated Turing jumps. The sets of natural numbers used to define the hierarchy are   for each  .   is sometimes also denoted  ,[3] or   for a notation   for  .[2] Suppose that δ has notation e. These sets were first defined by Davis (1950) and Mostowski (1951).[2] The set   is defined using e as follows.

  • If δ = 0 then   is the empty set.
  • If δ = λ + 1 then   is the Turing jump of  . The sets   and   are   and  , respectively.
  • If δ is a limit ordinal, let   be the sequence of ordinals less than δ given by the notation e. The set   is given by the rule  . This is the effective join of the sets  .

Although the construction of   depends on having a fixed notation for δ, and each infinite ordinal has many notations, a theorem of Clifford Spector shows that the Turing degree of   depends only on δ, not on the particular notation used, and thus   is well defined up to Turing degree.[2]

The hyperarithmetical hierarchy is defined from these iterated Turing jumps. A set X of natural numbers is classified at level δ of the hyperarithmetical hierarchy, for  , if X is Turing reducible to  . There will always be a least such δ if there is any; it is this least δ that measures the level of uncomputability of X.

Hyperarithmetical sets and constructibility edit

Let   denote the  th level of the constructible hierarchy, and let   be the map from a member of Kleene's O to the ordinal it represents. A subset of   is hyperarithmetical if and only if it is a member of  . A subset of   is definable by a   formula if and only if its image under   is  -definable on  , where   is from the Lévy hierarchy of formulae.[4]

Hyperarithmetical sets and recursion in higher types edit

A third characterization of the hyperarithmetical sets, due to Kleene, uses higher-type computable functionals. The type-2 functional   is defined by the following rules:

  if there is an i such that f(i) > 0,
  if there is no i such that f(i) > 0.

Using a precise definition of computability relative to a type-2 functional, Kleene showed that a set of natural numbers is hyperarithmetical if and only if it is computable relative to  .

Example: the truth set of arithmetic edit

Every arithmetical set is hyperarithmetical, but there are many other hyperarithmetical sets. One example of a hyperarithmetical, nonarithmetical set is the set T of Gödel numbers of formulas of Peano arithmetic that are true in the standard natural numbers  . The set T is Turing equivalent to the set  , and so is not high in the hyperarithmetical hierarchy, although it is not arithmetically definable by Tarski's indefinability theorem.

Fundamental results edit

The fundamental results of hyperarithmetic theory show that the three definitions above define the same collection of sets of natural numbers. These equivalences are due to Kleene.

Completeness results are also fundamental to the theory. A set of natural numbers is   complete if it is at level   of the analytical hierarchy and every   set of natural numbers is many-one reducible to it. The definition of a   complete subset of Baire space ( ) is similar. Several sets associated with hyperarithmetic theory are   complete:

  • Kleene's  , the set of natural numbers that are notations for ordinal numbers
  • The set of natural numbers e such that the computable function   computes the characteristic function of a well ordering of the natural numbers. These are the indices of recursive ordinals.
  • The set of elements of Baire space that are the characteristic functions of a well ordering of the natural numbers (using an effective isomorphism  .

Results known as   bounding follow from these completeness results. For any   set S of ordinal notations, there is an   such that every element of S is a notation for an ordinal less than  . For any   subset T of Baire space consisting only of characteristic functions of well orderings, there is an   such that each ordinal represented in T is less than  .

Relativized hyperarithmeticity and hyperdegrees edit

The definition of   can be relativized to a set X of natural numbers: in the definition of an ordinal notation, the clause for limit ordinals is changed so that the computable enumeration of a sequence of ordinal notations is allowed to use X as an oracle. The set of numbers that are ordinal notations relative to X is denoted  . The supremum of ordinals represented in   is denoted  ; this is a countable ordinal no smaller than  .

The definition of   can also be relativized to an arbitrary set   of natural numbers. The only change in the definition is that   is defined to be X rather than the empty set, so that   is the Turing jump of X, and so on. Rather than terminating at   the hierarchy relative to X runs through all ordinals less than  .

The relativized hyperarithmetical hierarchy is used to define hyperarithmetical reducibility. Given sets X and Y, we say   if and only if there is a   such that X is Turing reducible to  . If   and   then the notation   is used to indicate X and Y are hyperarithmetically equivalent. This is a coarser equivalence relation than Turing equivalence; for example, every set of natural numbers is hyperarithmetically equivalent to its Turing jump but not Turing equivalent to its Turing jump. The equivalence classes of hyperarithmetical equivalence are known as hyperdegrees.

The function that takes a set X to   is known as the hyperjump by analogy with the Turing jump. Many properties of the hyperjump and hyperdegrees have been established. In particular, it is known that Post's problem for hyperdegrees has a positive answer: for every set X of natural numbers there is a set Y of natural numbers such that  .

Generalizations edit

Hyperarithmetical theory is generalized by α-recursion theory, which is the study of definable subsets of admissible ordinals. Hyperarithmetical theory is the special case in which α is  .

Relation to other hierarchies edit

Lightface Boldface
Σ0
0
= Π0
0
= Δ0
0
(sometimes the same as Δ0
1
)
Σ0
0
= Π0
0
= Δ0
0
(if defined)
Δ0
1
= recursive
Δ0
1
= clopen
Σ0
1
= recursively enumerable
Π0
1
= co-recursively enumerable
Σ0
1
= G = open
Π0
1
= F = closed
Δ0
2
Δ0
2
Σ0
2
Π0
2
Σ0
2
= Fσ
Π0
2
= Gδ
Δ0
3
Δ0
3
Σ0
3
Π0
3
Σ0
3
= Gδσ
Π0
3
= Fσδ
Σ0
= Π0
= Δ0
= Σ1
0
= Π1
0
= Δ1
0
= arithmetical
Σ0
= Π0
= Δ0
= Σ1
0
= Π1
0
= Δ1
0
= boldface arithmetical
Δ0
α
recursive)
Δ0
α
countable)
Σ0
α
Π0
α
Σ0
α
Π0
α
Σ0
ωCK
1
= Π0
ωCK
1
= Δ0
ωCK
1
= Δ1
1
= hyperarithmetical
Σ0
ω1
= Π0
ω1
= Δ0
ω1
= Δ1
1
= B = Borel
Σ1
1
= lightface analytic
Π1
1
= lightface coanalytic
Σ1
1
= A = analytic
Π1
1
= CA = coanalytic
Δ1
2
Δ1
2
Σ1
2
Π1
2
Σ1
2
= PCA
Π1
2
= CPCA
Δ1
3
Δ1
3
Σ1
3
Π1
3
Σ1
3
= PCPCA
Π1
3
= CPCPCA
Σ1
= Π1
= Δ1
= Σ2
0
= Π2
0
= Δ2
0
= analytical
Σ1
= Π1
= Δ1
= Σ2
0
= Π2
0
= Δ2
0
= P = projective


References edit

  • H. Rogers, Jr., 1967. The Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability, second edition 1987, MIT Press. ISBN 0-262-68052-1 (paperback), ISBN 0-07-053522-1
  • G. Sacks, 1990. Higher Recursion Theory, Springer-Verlag. ISBN 3-540-19305-7
  • S. Simpson, 1999. Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic, Springer-Verlag.
  • C. J. Ash, J. F. Knight, 2000. Computable Structures and the Hyperarithmetical Hierarchy, Elsevier. ISBN 0-444-50072-3

Citations edit

  1. ^ Computability Theory of Hyperarithmetical Sets
  2. ^ a b c d S. G. Simpson, The Hierarchy Based on the Jump Operator, pp.268--269. The Kleene Symposium (North-Holland, 1980)
  3. ^ C. J. Ash, J. Knight, Computable Structures and the Hyperarithmetical Hierarchy (Studies in Logic and the Foundation of Mathematics, 2000), ch. 5
  4. ^ D. Natingga, Embedding Theorem for the automorphism group of the α-enumeration degrees (p.27), PhD thesis, University of Leeds, 2019.

External links edit

  • Descriptive set theory. Notes by David Marker, University of Illinois at Chicago. 2002.
  • Mathematical Logic II. Notes by Dag Normann, The University of Oslo. 2005.
  • Antonio Montalbán: University of California, Berkeley and YouTube content creator

hyperarithmetical, theory, computability, theory, hyperarithmetic, theory, generalization, turing, computability, close, connections, with, definability, second, order, arithmetic, with, weak, systems, theory, such, kripke, platek, theory, important, tool, eff. In computability theory hyperarithmetic theory is a generalization of Turing computability It has close connections with definability in second order arithmetic and with weak systems of set theory such as Kripke Platek set theory It is an important tool in effective descriptive set theory 1 The central focus of hyperarithmetic theory is the sets of natural numbers known as hyperarithmetic sets There are three equivalent ways of defining this class of sets the study of the relationships between these different definitions is one motivation for the study of hyperarithmetical theory Contents 1 Hyperarithmetical sets and definability 2 Hyperarithmetical sets and iterated Turing jumps the hyperarithmetical hierarchy 3 Hyperarithmetical sets and constructibility 4 Hyperarithmetical sets and recursion in higher types 5 Example the truth set of arithmetic 6 Fundamental results 7 Relativized hyperarithmeticity and hyperdegrees 8 Generalizations 9 Relation to other hierarchies 10 References 11 Citations 12 External linksHyperarithmetical sets and definability editThe first definition of the hyperarithmetic sets uses the analytical hierarchy A set of natural numbers is classified at level S 1 1 displaystyle Sigma 1 1 nbsp of this hierarchy if it is definable by a formula of second order arithmetic with only existential set quantifiers and no other set quantifiers A set is classified at level P 1 1 displaystyle Pi 1 1 nbsp of the analytical hierarchy if it is definable by a formula of second order arithmetic with only universal set quantifiers and no other set quantifiers A set is D 1 1 displaystyle Delta 1 1 nbsp if it is both S 1 1 displaystyle Sigma 1 1 nbsp and P 1 1 displaystyle Pi 1 1 nbsp The hyperarithmetical sets are exactly the D 1 1 displaystyle Delta 1 1 nbsp sets Hyperarithmetical sets and iterated Turing jumps the hyperarithmetical hierarchy editThe definition of hyperarithmetical sets as D 1 1 displaystyle Delta 1 1 nbsp does not directly depend on computability results A second equivalent definition shows that the hyperarithmetical sets can be defined using infinitely iterated Turing jumps This second definition also shows that the hyperarithmetical sets can be classified into a hierarchy extending the arithmetical hierarchy the hyperarithmetical sets are exactly the sets that are assigned a rank in this hierarchy Each level of the hyperarithmetical hierarchy is indexed by a countable ordinal number ordinal but not all countable ordinals correspond to a level of the hierarchy The ordinals used by the hierarchy are those with an ordinal notation which is a concrete effective description of the ordinal An ordinal notation is an effective description of a countable ordinal by a natural number A system of ordinal notations is required in order to define the hyperarithmetic hierarchy The fundamental property an ordinal notation must have is that it describes the ordinal in terms of smaller ordinals in an effective way The following inductive definition is typical it uses a pairing function displaystyle langle cdot cdot rangle nbsp The number 0 is a notation for the ordinal 0 If n is a notation for an ordinal l then 1 n displaystyle langle 1 n rangle nbsp is a notation for l 1 Suppose that d is a limit ordinal A notation for d is a number of the form 2 e displaystyle langle 2 e rangle nbsp where e is the index of a total computable function ϕ e displaystyle phi e nbsp such that for each n ϕ e n displaystyle phi e n nbsp is a notation for an ordinal ln less than d and d is the sup of the set l n n N displaystyle lambda n mid n in mathbb N nbsp This may also be defined by taking effective joins at all levels instead of only notations for limit ordinals 2 There are only countably many ordinal notations since each notation is a natural number thus there is a countable ordinal that is the supremum of all ordinals that have a notation This ordinal is known as the Church Kleene ordinal and is denoted w 1 C K displaystyle omega 1 CK nbsp Note that this ordinal is still countable the symbol being only an analogy with the first uncountable ordinal w 1 displaystyle omega 1 nbsp The set of all natural numbers that are ordinal notations is denoted O displaystyle mathcal O nbsp and called Kleene s O displaystyle mathcal O nbsp Ordinal notations are used to define iterated Turing jumps The sets of natural numbers used to define the hierarchy are 0 d displaystyle 0 delta nbsp for each d lt w 1 C K displaystyle delta lt omega 1 CK nbsp 0 d displaystyle 0 delta nbsp is sometimes also denoted H d displaystyle H delta nbsp 3 or H e displaystyle H e nbsp for a notation e displaystyle e nbsp for d displaystyle delta nbsp 2 Suppose that d has notation e These sets were first defined by Davis 1950 and Mostowski 1951 2 The set 0 d displaystyle 0 delta nbsp is defined using e as follows If d 0 then 0 d 0 displaystyle 0 delta 0 nbsp is the empty set If d l 1 then 0 d displaystyle 0 delta nbsp is the Turing jump of 0 l displaystyle 0 lambda nbsp The sets 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 nbsp and 0 2 displaystyle 0 2 nbsp are 0 displaystyle 0 nbsp and 0 displaystyle 0 nbsp respectively If d is a limit ordinal let l n n N displaystyle langle lambda n mid n in mathbb N rangle nbsp be the sequence of ordinals less than d given by the notation e The set 0 d displaystyle 0 delta nbsp is given by the rule 0 d n i i 0 l n displaystyle 0 delta langle n i rangle mid i in 0 lambda n nbsp This is the effective join of the sets 0 l n displaystyle 0 lambda n nbsp Although the construction of 0 d displaystyle 0 delta nbsp depends on having a fixed notation for d and each infinite ordinal has many notations a theorem of Clifford Spector shows that the Turing degree of 0 d displaystyle 0 delta nbsp depends only on d not on the particular notation used and thus 0 d displaystyle 0 delta nbsp is well defined up to Turing degree 2 The hyperarithmetical hierarchy is defined from these iterated Turing jumps A set X of natural numbers is classified at level d of the hyperarithmetical hierarchy for d lt w 1 C K displaystyle delta lt omega 1 CK nbsp if X is Turing reducible to 0 d displaystyle 0 delta nbsp There will always be a least such d if there is any it is this least d that measures the level of uncomputability of X Hyperarithmetical sets and constructibility editLet L a displaystyle L alpha nbsp denote the a displaystyle alpha nbsp th level of the constructible hierarchy and let n O w 1 C K displaystyle n mathcal O to omega 1 CK nbsp be the map from a member of Kleene s O to the ordinal it represents A subset of N displaystyle mathbb N nbsp is hyperarithmetical if and only if it is a member of L w 1 C K displaystyle L omega 1 CK nbsp A subset of N displaystyle mathbb N nbsp is definable by a P 1 1 displaystyle Pi 1 1 nbsp formula if and only if its image under n displaystyle n nbsp is S 1 displaystyle Sigma 1 nbsp definable on L w 1 C K displaystyle L omega 1 CK nbsp where S 1 displaystyle Sigma 1 nbsp is from the Levy hierarchy of formulae 4 Hyperarithmetical sets and recursion in higher types editA third characterization of the hyperarithmetical sets due to Kleene uses higher type computable functionals The type 2 functional 2 E N N N displaystyle 2 E colon mathbb N mathbb N to mathbb N nbsp is defined by the following rules 2 E f 1 displaystyle 2 E f 1 quad nbsp if there is an i such that f i gt 0 2 E f 0 displaystyle 2 E f 0 quad nbsp if there is no i such that f i gt 0 Using a precise definition of computability relative to a type 2 functional Kleene showed that a set of natural numbers is hyperarithmetical if and only if it is computable relative to 2 E displaystyle 2 E nbsp Example the truth set of arithmetic editEvery arithmetical set is hyperarithmetical but there are many other hyperarithmetical sets One example of a hyperarithmetical nonarithmetical set is the set T of Godel numbers of formulas of Peano arithmetic that are true in the standard natural numbers N displaystyle mathbb N nbsp The set T is Turing equivalent to the set 0 w displaystyle 0 omega nbsp and so is not high in the hyperarithmetical hierarchy although it is not arithmetically definable by Tarski s indefinability theorem Fundamental results editThis section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2023 Learn how and when to remove this message The fundamental results of hyperarithmetic theory show that the three definitions above define the same collection of sets of natural numbers These equivalences are due to Kleene Completeness results are also fundamental to the theory A set of natural numbers is P 1 1 displaystyle Pi 1 1 nbsp complete if it is at level P 1 1 displaystyle Pi 1 1 nbsp of the analytical hierarchy and every P 1 1 displaystyle Pi 1 1 nbsp set of natural numbers is many one reducible to it The definition of a P 1 1 displaystyle Pi 1 1 nbsp complete subset of Baire space N N displaystyle mathbb N mathbb N nbsp is similar Several sets associated with hyperarithmetic theory are P 1 1 displaystyle Pi 1 1 nbsp complete Kleene s O displaystyle mathcal O nbsp the set of natural numbers that are notations for ordinal numbers The set of natural numbers e such that the computable function ϕ e x y displaystyle phi e x y nbsp computes the characteristic function of a well ordering of the natural numbers These are the indices of recursive ordinals The set of elements of Baire space that are the characteristic functions of a well ordering of the natural numbers using an effective isomorphism N N N N N displaystyle mathbb N mathbb N cong mathbb N mathbb N times mathbb N nbsp Results known as S 1 1 displaystyle Sigma 1 1 nbsp bounding follow from these completeness results For any S 1 1 displaystyle Sigma 1 1 nbsp set S of ordinal notations there is an a lt w 1 C K displaystyle alpha lt omega 1 CK nbsp such that every element of S is a notation for an ordinal less than a displaystyle alpha nbsp For any S 1 1 displaystyle Sigma 1 1 nbsp subset T of Baire space consisting only of characteristic functions of well orderings there is an a lt w 1 C K displaystyle alpha lt omega 1 CK nbsp such that each ordinal represented in T is less than a displaystyle alpha nbsp Relativized hyperarithmeticity and hyperdegrees editThe definition of O displaystyle mathcal O nbsp can be relativized to a set X of natural numbers in the definition of an ordinal notation the clause for limit ordinals is changed so that the computable enumeration of a sequence of ordinal notations is allowed to use X as an oracle The set of numbers that are ordinal notations relative to X is denoted O X displaystyle mathcal O X nbsp The supremum of ordinals represented in O X displaystyle mathcal O X nbsp is denoted w 1 X displaystyle omega 1 X nbsp this is a countable ordinal no smaller than w 1 C K displaystyle omega 1 CK nbsp The definition of 0 d displaystyle 0 delta nbsp can also be relativized to an arbitrary set X displaystyle X nbsp of natural numbers The only change in the definition is that X 0 displaystyle X 0 nbsp is defined to be X rather than the empty set so that X 1 X displaystyle X 1 X nbsp is the Turing jump of X and so on Rather than terminating at w 1 C K displaystyle omega 1 CK nbsp the hierarchy relative to X runs through all ordinals less than w 1 X displaystyle omega 1 X nbsp The relativized hyperarithmetical hierarchy is used to define hyperarithmetical reducibility Given sets X and Y we say X HYP Y displaystyle X leq text HYP Y nbsp if and only if there is a d lt w 1 Y displaystyle delta lt omega 1 Y nbsp such that X is Turing reducible to Y d displaystyle Y delta nbsp If X HYP Y displaystyle X leq text HYP Y nbsp and Y HYP X displaystyle Y leq text HYP X nbsp then the notation X HYP Y displaystyle X equiv text HYP Y nbsp is used to indicate X and Y are hyperarithmetically equivalent This is a coarser equivalence relation than Turing equivalence for example every set of natural numbers is hyperarithmetically equivalent to its Turing jump but not Turing equivalent to its Turing jump The equivalence classes of hyperarithmetical equivalence are known as hyperdegrees The function that takes a set X to O X displaystyle mathcal O X nbsp is known as the hyperjump by analogy with the Turing jump Many properties of the hyperjump and hyperdegrees have been established In particular it is known that Post s problem for hyperdegrees has a positive answer for every set X of natural numbers there is a set Y of natural numbers such that X lt HYP Y lt HYP O X displaystyle X lt text HYP Y lt text HYP mathcal O X nbsp Generalizations editHyperarithmetical theory is generalized by a recursion theory which is the study of definable subsets of admissible ordinals Hyperarithmetical theory is the special case in which a is w 1 C K displaystyle omega 1 CK nbsp Relation to other hierarchies editThis box viewtalkedit Lightface Boldface S00 P00 D00 sometimes the same as D01 S00 P00 D00 if defined D01 recursive D01 clopen S01 recursively enumerable P01 co recursively enumerable S01 G open P01 F closed D02 D02 S02 P02 S02 Fs P02 Gd D03 D03 S03 P03 S03 Gds P03 Fsd S0 lt w P0 lt w D0 lt w S10 P10 D10 arithmetical S0 lt w P0 lt w D0 lt w S10 P10 D10 boldface arithmetical D0a a recursive D0a a countable S0a P0a S0a P0a S0wCK1 P0wCK1 D0wCK1 D11 hyperarithmetical S0w1 P0w1 D0w1 D11 B Borel S11 lightface analytic P11 lightface coanalytic S11 A analytic P11 CA coanalytic D12 D12 S12 P12 S12 PCA P12 CPCA D13 D13 S13 P13 S13 PCPCA P13 CPCPCA S1 lt w P1 lt w D1 lt w S20 P20 D20 analytical S1 lt w P1 lt w D1 lt w S20 P20 D20 P projective References editH Rogers Jr 1967 The Theory of Recursive Functions and Effective Computability second edition 1987 MIT Press ISBN 0 262 68052 1 paperback ISBN 0 07 053522 1 G Sacks 1990 Higher Recursion Theory Springer Verlag ISBN 3 540 19305 7 S Simpson 1999 Subsystems of Second Order Arithmetic Springer Verlag C J Ash J F Knight 2000 Computable Structures and the Hyperarithmetical Hierarchy Elsevier ISBN 0 444 50072 3Citations edit Computability Theory of Hyperarithmetical Sets a b c d S G Simpson The Hierarchy Based on the Jump Operator pp 268 269 The Kleene Symposium North Holland 1980 C J Ash J Knight Computable Structures and the Hyperarithmetical Hierarchy Studies in Logic and the Foundation of Mathematics 2000 ch 5 D Natingga Embedding Theorem for the automorphism group of the a enumeration degrees p 27 PhD thesis University of Leeds 2019 External links editDescriptive set theory Notes by David Marker University of Illinois at Chicago 2002 Mathematical Logic II Notes by Dag Normann The University of Oslo 2005 Antonio Montalban University of California Berkeley and YouTube content creator Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Hyperarithmetical theory amp oldid 1216882341 Relativized hyperarithmeticity and hyperdegrees, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.