fbpx
Wikipedia

Causal structure

In mathematical physics, the causal structure of a Lorentzian manifold describes the causal relationships between points in the manifold.

Introduction edit

In modern physics (especially general relativity) spacetime is represented by a Lorentzian manifold. The causal relations between points in the manifold are interpreted as describing which events in spacetime can influence which other events.

The causal structure of an arbitrary (possibly curved) Lorentzian manifold is made more complicated by the presence of curvature. Discussions of the causal structure for such manifolds must be phrased in terms of smooth curves joining pairs of points. Conditions on the tangent vectors of the curves then define the causal relationships.

Tangent vectors edit

 
Subdivision of Minkowski spacetime with respect to a point in four disjoint sets. The light cone, the causal future, the causal past, and elsewhere. The terminology is defined in this article.

If   is a Lorentzian manifold (for metric   on manifold  ) then the nonzero tangent vectors at each point in the manifold can be classified into three disjoint types. A tangent vector   is:

  • timelike if  
  • null or lightlike if  
  • spacelike if  

Here we use the   metric signature. We say that a tangent vector is non-spacelike if it is null or timelike.

The canonical Lorentzian manifold is Minkowski spacetime, where   and   is the flat Minkowski metric. The names for the tangent vectors come from the physics of this model. The causal relationships between points in Minkowski spacetime take a particularly simple form because the tangent space is also   and hence the tangent vectors may be identified with points in the space. The four-dimensional vector   is classified according to the sign of  , where   is a Cartesian coordinate in 3-dimensional space,   is the constant representing the universal speed limit, and   is time. The classification of any vector in the space will be the same in all frames of reference that are related by a Lorentz transformation (but not by a general Poincaré transformation because the origin may then be displaced) because of the invariance of the metric.

Time-orientability edit

At each point in   the timelike tangent vectors in the point's tangent space can be divided into two classes. To do this we first define an equivalence relation on pairs of timelike tangent vectors.

If   and   are two timelike tangent vectors at a point we say that   and   are equivalent (written  ) if  .

There are then two equivalence classes which between them contain all timelike tangent vectors at the point. We can (arbitrarily) call one of these equivalence classes future-directed and call the other past-directed. Physically this designation of the two classes of future- and past-directed timelike vectors corresponds to a choice of an arrow of time at the point. The future- and past-directed designations can be extended to null vectors at a point by continuity.

A Lorentzian manifold is time-orientable[1] if a continuous designation of future-directed and past-directed for non-spacelike vectors can be made over the entire manifold.

Curves edit

A path in   is a continuous map   where   is a nondegenerate interval (i.e., a connected set containing more than one point) in  . A smooth path has   differentiable an appropriate number of times (typically  ), and a regular path has nonvanishing derivative.

A curve in   is the image of a path or, more properly, an equivalence class of path-images related by re-parametrisation, i.e. homeomorphisms or diffeomorphisms of  . When   is time-orientable, the curve is oriented if the parameter change is required to be monotonic.

Smooth regular curves (or paths) in   can be classified depending on their tangent vectors. Such a curve is

  • chronological (or timelike) if the tangent vector is timelike at all points in the curve. Also called a world line.[2]
  • null if the tangent vector is null at all points in the curve.
  • spacelike if the tangent vector is spacelike at all points in the curve.
  • causal (or non-spacelike) if the tangent vector is timelike or null at all points in the curve.

The requirements of regularity and nondegeneracy of   ensure that closed causal curves (such as those consisting of a single point) are not automatically admitted by all spacetimes.

If the manifold is time-orientable then the non-spacelike curves can further be classified depending on their orientation with respect to time.

A chronological, null or causal curve in   is

  • future-directed if, for every point in the curve, the tangent vector is future-directed.
  • past-directed if, for every point in the curve, the tangent vector is past-directed.

These definitions only apply to causal (chronological or null) curves because only timelike or null tangent vectors can be assigned an orientation with respect to time.

  • A closed timelike curve is a closed curve which is everywhere future-directed timelike (or everywhere past-directed timelike).
  • A closed null curve is a closed curve which is everywhere future-directed null (or everywhere past-directed null).
  • The holonomy of the ratio of the rate of change of the affine parameter around a closed null geodesic is the redshift factor.

Causal relations edit

There are several causal relations between points   and   in the manifold  .

  •   chronologically precedes   (often denoted  ) if there exists a future-directed chronological (timelike) curve from   to  .
  •   strictly causally precedes   (often denoted  ) if there exists a future-directed causal (non-spacelike) curve from   to  .
  •   causally precedes   (often denoted   or  ) if   strictly causally precedes   or  .
  •   horismos  [3] (often denoted   or  ) if   or there exists a future-directed null curve from   to  [4] (or equivalently,   and  ).

These relations satisfy the following properties:

  •   implies   (this follows trivially from the definition)[5]
  •  ,   implies  [5]
  •  ,   implies  [5]
  •  ,  ,   are transitive.[5]   is not transitive.[6]
  •  ,   are reflexive[4]

For a point   in the manifold   we define[5]

  • The chronological future of  , denoted  , as the set of all points   in   such that   chronologically precedes  :
 
  • The chronological past of  , denoted  , as the set of all points   in   such that   chronologically precedes  :
 

We similarly define

  • The causal future (also called the absolute future) of  , denoted  , as the set of all points   in   such that   causally precedes  :
 
  • The causal past (also called the absolute past) of  , denoted  , as the set of all points   in   such that   causally precedes  :
 
  • The future null cone of   as the set of all points   in   such that  .
  • The past null cone of   as the set of all points   in   such that  .
  • The light cone of   as the future and past null cones of   together.[7]
  • elsewhere as points not in the light cone, causal future, or causal past.[7]

Points contained in  , for example, can be reached from   by a future-directed timelike curve. The point   can be reached, for example, from points contained in   by a future-directed non-spacelike curve.

In Minkowski spacetime the set   is the interior of the future light cone at  . The set   is the full future light cone at  , including the cone itself.

These sets   defined for all   in  , are collectively called the causal structure of  .

For   a subset of   we define[5]

 
 

For   two subsets of   we define

  • The chronological future of   relative to  ,  , is the chronological future of   considered as a submanifold of  . Note that this is quite a different concept from   which gives the set of points in   which can be reached by future-directed timelike curves starting from  . In the first case the curves must lie in   in the second case they do not. See Hawking and Ellis.
  • The causal future of   relative to  ,  , is the causal future of   considered as a submanifold of  . Note that this is quite a different concept from   which gives the set of points in   which can be reached by future-directed causal curves starting from  . In the first case the curves must lie in   in the second case they do not. See Hawking and Ellis.
  • A future set is a set closed under chronological future.
  • A past set is a set closed under chronological past.
  • An indecomposable past set (IP) is a past set which isn't the union of two different open past proper subsets.
  • An IP which does not coincide with the past of any point in   is called a terminal indecomposable past set (TIP).
  • A proper indecomposable past set (PIP) is an IP which isn't a TIP.   is a proper indecomposable past set (PIP).
  • The future Cauchy development of  ,   is the set of all points   for which every past directed inextendible causal curve through   intersects   at least once. Similarly for the past Cauchy development. The Cauchy development is the union of the future and past Cauchy developments. Cauchy developments are important for the study of determinism.
  • A subset   is achronal if there do not exist   such that  , or equivalently, if   is disjoint from  .

 
Causal diamond
  • A Cauchy surface is a closed achronal set whose Cauchy development is  .
  • A metric is globally hyperbolic if it can be foliated by Cauchy surfaces.
  • The chronology violating set is the set of points through which closed timelike curves pass.
  • The causality violating set is the set of points through which closed causal curves pass.
  • The boundary of the causality violating set is a Cauchy horizon. If the Cauchy horizon is generated by closed null geodesics, then there's a redshift factor associated with each of them.
  • For a causal curve  , the causal diamond is   (here we are using the looser definition of 'curve' whereon it is just a set of points), being the point   in the causal past of  . In words: the causal diamond of a particle's world-line   is the set of all events that lie in both the past of some point in   and the future of some point in  . In the discrete version, the causal diamond is the set of all the causal paths that connect   from  .

Properties edit

See Penrose (1972), p13.

  • A point   is in   if and only if   is in  .
  •  
  •  
  •  
  •  
  • The horismos is generated by null geodesic congruences.

Topological properties:

  •   is open for all points   in  .
  •   is open for all subsets  .
  •   for all subsets  . Here   is the closure of a subset  .
  •  

Conformal geometry edit

Two metrics   and   are conformally related[8] if   for some real function   called the conformal factor. (See conformal map).

Looking at the definitions of which tangent vectors are timelike, null and spacelike we see they remain unchanged if we use   or  . As an example suppose   is a timelike tangent vector with respect to the   metric. This means that  . We then have that   so   is a timelike tangent vector with respect to the   too.

It follows from this that the causal structure of a Lorentzian manifold is unaffected by a conformal transformation.

A null geodesic remains a null geodesic under a conformal rescaling.

Conformal infinity edit

An infinite metric admits geodesics of infinite length/proper time. However, we can sometimes make a conformal rescaling of the metric with a conformal factor which falls off sufficiently fast to 0 as we approach infinity to get the conformal boundary of the manifold. The topological structure of the conformal boundary depends upon the causal structure.

  • Future-directed timelike geodesics end up on  , the future timelike infinity.
  • Past-directed timelike geodesics end up on  , the past timelike infinity.
  • Future-directed null geodesics end up on ℐ+, the future null infinity.
  • Past-directed null geodesics end up on ℐ, the past null infinity.
  • Spacelike geodesics end up on spacelike infinity.

In various spaces:

  • Minkowski space:   are points, ℐ± are null sheets, and spacelike infinity has codimension 2.
  • Anti-de Sitter space: there's no timelike or null infinity, and spacelike infinity has codimension 1.
  • de Sitter space: the future and past timelike infinity has codimension 1.

Gravitational singularity edit

If a geodesic terminates after a finite affine parameter, and it is not possible to extend the manifold to extend the geodesic, then we have a singularity.

  • For black holes, the future timelike boundary ends on a singularity in some places.
  • For the Big Bang, the past timelike boundary is also a singularity.

The absolute event horizon is the past null cone of the future timelike infinity. It is generated by null geodesics which obey the Raychaudhuri optical equation.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ Hawking & Israel 1979, p. 255
  2. ^ Galloway, Gregory J. "Notes on Lorentzian causality" (PDF). ESI-EMS-IAMP Summer School on Mathematical Relativity. University of Miami. p. 4. Retrieved 2 July 2021.
  3. ^ Penrose 1972, p. 15
  4. ^ a b Papadopoulos, Kyriakos; Acharjee, Santanu; Papadopoulos, Basil K. (May 2018). "The order on the light cone and its induced topology". International Journal of Geometric Methods in Modern Physics. 15 (5): 1850069–1851572. arXiv:1710.05177. Bibcode:2018IJGMM..1550069P. doi:10.1142/S021988781850069X. S2CID 119120311.
  5. ^ a b c d e f Penrose 1972, p. 12
  6. ^ Stoica, O. C. (25 May 2016). "Spacetime Causal Structure and Dimension from Horismotic Relation". Journal of Gravity. 2016: 1–6. arXiv:1504.03265. doi:10.1155/2016/6151726.
  7. ^ a b Sard 1970, p. 78
  8. ^ Hawking & Ellis 1973, p. 42

References edit

Further reading edit

  • G. W. Gibbons, S. N. Solodukhin; The Geometry of Small Causal Diamonds arXiv:hep-th/0703098 (Causal intervals)
  • S.W. Hawking, A.R. King, P.J. McCarthy; A new topology for curved space–time which incorporates the causal, differential, and conformal structures; J. Math. Phys. 17 2:174-181 (1976); (Geometry, Causal Structure)
  • A.V. Levichev; Prescribing the conformal geometry of a lorentz manifold by means of its causal structure; Soviet Math. Dokl. 35:452-455, (1987); (Geometry, Causal Structure)
  • D. Malament; The class of continuous timelike curves determines the topology of spacetime; J. Math. Phys. 18 7:1399-1404 (1977); (Geometry, Causal Structure)
  • A.A. Robb; A theory of time and space; Cambridge University Press, 1914; (Geometry, Causal Structure)
  • A.A. Robb; The absolute relations of time and space; Cambridge University Press, 1921; (Geometry, Causal Structure)
  • A.A. Robb; Geometry of Time and Space; Cambridge University Press, 1936; (Geometry, Causal Structure)
  • R.D. Sorkin, E. Woolgar; A Causal Order for Spacetimes with C^0 Lorentzian Metrics: Proof of Compactness of the Space of Causal Curves; Classical & Quantum Gravity 13: 1971-1994 (1996); arXiv:gr-qc/9508018 (Causal Structure)

External links edit

causal, structure, this, article, about, possible, causal, relationships, among, points, lorentzian, manifold, classification, lorentzian, manifolds, according, types, causal, structures, they, admit, causality, conditions, mathematical, physics, causal, struc. This article is about the possible causal relationships among points in a Lorentzian manifold For classification of Lorentzian manifolds according to the types of causal structures they admit see Causality conditions In mathematical physics the causal structure of a Lorentzian manifold describes the causal relationships between points in the manifold Contents 1 Introduction 1 1 Tangent vectors 1 2 Time orientability 1 3 Curves 1 4 Causal relations 1 5 Properties 2 Conformal geometry 3 Conformal infinity 4 Gravitational singularity 5 See also 6 Notes 7 References 8 Further reading 9 External linksIntroduction editIn modern physics especially general relativity spacetime is represented by a Lorentzian manifold The causal relations between points in the manifold are interpreted as describing which events in spacetime can influence which other events The causal structure of an arbitrary possibly curved Lorentzian manifold is made more complicated by the presence of curvature Discussions of the causal structure for such manifolds must be phrased in terms of smooth curves joining pairs of points Conditions on the tangent vectors of the curves then define the causal relationships Tangent vectors edit nbsp Subdivision of Minkowski spacetime with respect to a point in four disjoint sets The light cone the causal future the causal past and elsewhere The terminology is defined in this article If M g displaystyle M g nbsp is a Lorentzian manifold for metric g displaystyle g nbsp on manifold M displaystyle M nbsp then the nonzero tangent vectors at each point in the manifold can be classified into three disjoint types A tangent vector X displaystyle X nbsp is timelike if g X X lt 0 displaystyle g X X lt 0 nbsp null or lightlike if g X X 0 displaystyle g X X 0 nbsp spacelike if g X X gt 0 displaystyle g X X gt 0 nbsp Here we use the displaystyle cdots nbsp metric signature We say that a tangent vector is non spacelike if it is null or timelike The canonical Lorentzian manifold is Minkowski spacetime where M R 4 displaystyle M mathbb R 4 nbsp and g displaystyle g nbsp is the flat Minkowski metric The names for the tangent vectors come from the physics of this model The causal relationships between points in Minkowski spacetime take a particularly simple form because the tangent space is also R 4 displaystyle mathbb R 4 nbsp and hence the tangent vectors may be identified with points in the space The four dimensional vector X t r displaystyle X t r nbsp is classified according to the sign of g X X c 2 t 2 r 2 displaystyle g X X c 2 t 2 r 2 nbsp where r R 3 displaystyle r in mathbb R 3 nbsp is a Cartesian coordinate in 3 dimensional space c displaystyle c nbsp is the constant representing the universal speed limit and t displaystyle t nbsp is time The classification of any vector in the space will be the same in all frames of reference that are related by a Lorentz transformation but not by a general Poincare transformation because the origin may then be displaced because of the invariance of the metric Time orientability edit At each point in M displaystyle M nbsp the timelike tangent vectors in the point s tangent space can be divided into two classes To do this we first define an equivalence relation on pairs of timelike tangent vectors If X displaystyle X nbsp and Y displaystyle Y nbsp are two timelike tangent vectors at a point we say that X displaystyle X nbsp and Y displaystyle Y nbsp are equivalent written X Y displaystyle X sim Y nbsp if g X Y lt 0 displaystyle g X Y lt 0 nbsp There are then two equivalence classes which between them contain all timelike tangent vectors at the point We can arbitrarily call one of these equivalence classes future directed and call the other past directed Physically this designation of the two classes of future and past directed timelike vectors corresponds to a choice of an arrow of time at the point The future and past directed designations can be extended to null vectors at a point by continuity A Lorentzian manifold is time orientable 1 if a continuous designation of future directed and past directed for non spacelike vectors can be made over the entire manifold Curves edit A path in M displaystyle M nbsp is a continuous map m S M displaystyle mu Sigma to M nbsp where S displaystyle Sigma nbsp is a nondegenerate interval i e a connected set containing more than one point in R displaystyle mathbb R nbsp A smooth path has m displaystyle mu nbsp differentiable an appropriate number of times typically C displaystyle C infty nbsp and a regular path has nonvanishing derivative A curve in M displaystyle M nbsp is the image of a path or more properly an equivalence class of path images related by re parametrisation i e homeomorphisms or diffeomorphisms of S displaystyle Sigma nbsp When M displaystyle M nbsp is time orientable the curve is oriented if the parameter change is required to be monotonic Smooth regular curves or paths in M displaystyle M nbsp can be classified depending on their tangent vectors Such a curve is chronological or timelike if the tangent vector is timelike at all points in the curve Also called a world line 2 null if the tangent vector is null at all points in the curve spacelike if the tangent vector is spacelike at all points in the curve causal or non spacelike if the tangent vector is timelike or null at all points in the curve The requirements of regularity and nondegeneracy of S displaystyle Sigma nbsp ensure that closed causal curves such as those consisting of a single point are not automatically admitted by all spacetimes If the manifold is time orientable then the non spacelike curves can further be classified depending on their orientation with respect to time A chronological null or causal curve in M displaystyle M nbsp is future directed if for every point in the curve the tangent vector is future directed past directed if for every point in the curve the tangent vector is past directed These definitions only apply to causal chronological or null curves because only timelike or null tangent vectors can be assigned an orientation with respect to time A closed timelike curve is a closed curve which is everywhere future directed timelike or everywhere past directed timelike A closed null curve is a closed curve which is everywhere future directed null or everywhere past directed null The holonomy of the ratio of the rate of change of the affine parameter around a closed null geodesic is the redshift factor Causal relations edit There are several causal relations between points x displaystyle x nbsp and y displaystyle y nbsp in the manifold M displaystyle M nbsp x displaystyle x nbsp chronologically precedes y displaystyle y nbsp often denoted x y displaystyle x ll y nbsp if there exists a future directed chronological timelike curve from x displaystyle x nbsp to y displaystyle y nbsp x displaystyle x nbsp strictly causally precedes y displaystyle y nbsp often denoted x lt y displaystyle x lt y nbsp if there exists a future directed causal non spacelike curve from x displaystyle x nbsp to y displaystyle y nbsp x displaystyle x nbsp causally precedes y displaystyle y nbsp often denoted x y displaystyle x prec y nbsp or x y displaystyle x leq y nbsp if x displaystyle x nbsp strictly causally precedes y displaystyle y nbsp or x y displaystyle x y nbsp x displaystyle x nbsp horismos y displaystyle y nbsp 3 often denoted x y displaystyle x to y nbsp or x y displaystyle x nearrow y nbsp if x y displaystyle x y nbsp or there exists a future directed null curve from x displaystyle x nbsp to y displaystyle y nbsp 4 or equivalently x y displaystyle x prec y nbsp and x y displaystyle x not ll y nbsp These relations satisfy the following properties x y displaystyle x ll y nbsp implies x y displaystyle x prec y nbsp this follows trivially from the definition 5 x y displaystyle x ll y nbsp y z displaystyle y prec z nbsp implies x z displaystyle x ll z nbsp 5 x y displaystyle x prec y nbsp y z displaystyle y ll z nbsp implies x z displaystyle x ll z nbsp 5 displaystyle ll nbsp lt displaystyle lt nbsp displaystyle prec nbsp are transitive 5 displaystyle to nbsp is not transitive 6 displaystyle prec nbsp displaystyle to nbsp are reflexive 4 For a point x displaystyle x nbsp in the manifold M displaystyle M nbsp we define 5 The chronological future of x displaystyle x nbsp denoted I x displaystyle I x nbsp as the set of all points y displaystyle y nbsp in M displaystyle M nbsp such that x displaystyle x nbsp chronologically precedes y displaystyle y nbsp I x y M x y displaystyle I x y in M x ll y nbsp The chronological past of x displaystyle x nbsp denoted I x displaystyle I x nbsp as the set of all points y displaystyle y nbsp in M displaystyle M nbsp such that y displaystyle y nbsp chronologically precedes x displaystyle x nbsp I x y M y x displaystyle I x y in M y ll x nbsp We similarly define The causal future also called the absolute future of x displaystyle x nbsp denoted J x displaystyle J x nbsp as the set of all points y displaystyle y nbsp in M displaystyle M nbsp such that x displaystyle x nbsp causally precedes y displaystyle y nbsp J x y M x y displaystyle J x y in M x prec y nbsp The causal past also called the absolute past of x displaystyle x nbsp denoted J x displaystyle J x nbsp as the set of all points y displaystyle y nbsp in M displaystyle M nbsp such that y displaystyle y nbsp causally precedes x displaystyle x nbsp J x y M y x displaystyle J x y in M y prec x nbsp The future null cone of x displaystyle x nbsp as the set of all points y displaystyle y nbsp in M displaystyle M nbsp such that x y displaystyle x to y nbsp The past null cone of x displaystyle x nbsp as the set of all points y displaystyle y nbsp in M displaystyle M nbsp such that y x displaystyle y to x nbsp The light cone of x displaystyle x nbsp as the future and past null cones of x displaystyle x nbsp together 7 elsewhere as points not in the light cone causal future or causal past 7 Points contained in I x displaystyle I x nbsp for example can be reached from x displaystyle x nbsp by a future directed timelike curve The point x displaystyle x nbsp can be reached for example from points contained in J x displaystyle J x nbsp by a future directed non spacelike curve In Minkowski spacetime the set I x displaystyle I x nbsp is the interior of the future light cone at x displaystyle x nbsp The set J x displaystyle J x nbsp is the full future light cone at x displaystyle x nbsp including the cone itself These sets I x I x J x J x displaystyle I x I x J x J x nbsp defined for all x displaystyle x nbsp in M displaystyle M nbsp are collectively called the causal structure of M displaystyle M nbsp For S displaystyle S nbsp a subset of M displaystyle M nbsp we define 5 I S x S I x displaystyle I pm S bigcup x in S I pm x nbsp J S x S J x displaystyle J pm S bigcup x in S J pm x nbsp For S T displaystyle S T nbsp two subsets of M displaystyle M nbsp we define The chronological future of S displaystyle S nbsp relative to T displaystyle T nbsp I S T displaystyle I S T nbsp is the chronological future of S displaystyle S nbsp considered as a submanifold of T displaystyle T nbsp Note that this is quite a different concept from I S T displaystyle I S cap T nbsp which gives the set of points in T displaystyle T nbsp which can be reached by future directed timelike curves starting from S displaystyle S nbsp In the first case the curves must lie in T displaystyle T nbsp in the second case they do not See Hawking and Ellis The causal future of S displaystyle S nbsp relative to T displaystyle T nbsp J S T displaystyle J S T nbsp is the causal future of S displaystyle S nbsp considered as a submanifold of T displaystyle T nbsp Note that this is quite a different concept from J S T displaystyle J S cap T nbsp which gives the set of points in T displaystyle T nbsp which can be reached by future directed causal curves starting from S displaystyle S nbsp In the first case the curves must lie in T displaystyle T nbsp in the second case they do not See Hawking and Ellis A future set is a set closed under chronological future A past set is a set closed under chronological past An indecomposable past set IP is a past set which isn t the union of two different open past proper subsets An IP which does not coincide with the past of any point in M displaystyle M nbsp is called a terminal indecomposable past set TIP A proper indecomposable past set PIP is an IP which isn t a TIP I x displaystyle I x nbsp is a proper indecomposable past set PIP The future Cauchy development of S displaystyle S nbsp D S displaystyle D S nbsp is the set of all points x displaystyle x nbsp for which every past directed inextendible causal curve through x displaystyle x nbsp intersects S displaystyle S nbsp at least once Similarly for the past Cauchy development The Cauchy development is the union of the future and past Cauchy developments Cauchy developments are important for the study of determinism A subset S M displaystyle S subset M nbsp is achronal if there do not exist q r S displaystyle q r in S nbsp such that r I q displaystyle r in I q nbsp or equivalently if S displaystyle S nbsp is disjoint from I S displaystyle I S nbsp nbsp Causal diamond A Cauchy surface is a closed achronal set whose Cauchy development is M displaystyle M nbsp A metric is globally hyperbolic if it can be foliated by Cauchy surfaces The chronology violating set is the set of points through which closed timelike curves pass The causality violating set is the set of points through which closed causal curves pass The boundary of the causality violating set is a Cauchy horizon If the Cauchy horizon is generated by closed null geodesics then there s a redshift factor associated with each of them For a causal curve g displaystyle gamma nbsp the causal diamond is J g t 1 J g t 2 displaystyle J gamma t 1 cap J gamma t 2 nbsp here we are using the looser definition of curve whereon it is just a set of points being the point g t 1 displaystyle gamma t 1 nbsp in the causal past of g t 2 displaystyle gamma t 2 nbsp In words the causal diamond of a particle s world line g displaystyle gamma nbsp is the set of all events that lie in both the past of some point in g displaystyle gamma nbsp and the future of some point in g displaystyle gamma nbsp In the discrete version the causal diamond is the set of all the causal paths that connect g t 2 displaystyle gamma t 2 nbsp from g t 1 displaystyle gamma t 1 nbsp Properties edit See Penrose 1972 p13 A point x displaystyle x nbsp is in I y displaystyle I y nbsp if and only if y displaystyle y nbsp is in I x displaystyle I x nbsp x y I x I y displaystyle x prec y implies I x subset I y nbsp x y I y I x displaystyle x prec y implies I y subset I x nbsp I S I I S J S J J S displaystyle I S I I S subset J S J J S nbsp I S I I S J S J J S displaystyle I S I I S subset J S J J S nbsp The horismos is generated by null geodesic congruences Topological properties I x displaystyle I pm x nbsp is open for all points x displaystyle x nbsp in M displaystyle M nbsp I S displaystyle I pm S nbsp is open for all subsets S M displaystyle S subset M nbsp I S I S displaystyle I pm S I pm overline S nbsp for all subsets S M displaystyle S subset M nbsp Here S displaystyle overline S nbsp is the closure of a subset S displaystyle S nbsp I S J S displaystyle I pm S subset overline J pm S nbsp Conformal geometry editTwo metrics g displaystyle g nbsp and g displaystyle hat g nbsp are conformally related 8 if g W 2 g displaystyle hat g Omega 2 g nbsp for some real function W displaystyle Omega nbsp called the conformal factor See conformal map Looking at the definitions of which tangent vectors are timelike null and spacelike we see they remain unchanged if we use g displaystyle g nbsp or g displaystyle hat g nbsp As an example suppose X displaystyle X nbsp is a timelike tangent vector with respect to the g displaystyle g nbsp metric This means that g X X lt 0 displaystyle g X X lt 0 nbsp We then have that g X X W 2 g X X lt 0 displaystyle hat g X X Omega 2 g X X lt 0 nbsp so X displaystyle X nbsp is a timelike tangent vector with respect to the g displaystyle hat g nbsp too It follows from this that the causal structure of a Lorentzian manifold is unaffected by a conformal transformation A null geodesic remains a null geodesic under a conformal rescaling Conformal infinity editMain article Conformal infinity An infinite metric admits geodesics of infinite length proper time However we can sometimes make a conformal rescaling of the metric with a conformal factor which falls off sufficiently fast to 0 as we approach infinity to get the conformal boundary of the manifold The topological structure of the conformal boundary depends upon the causal structure Future directed timelike geodesics end up on i displaystyle i nbsp the future timelike infinity Past directed timelike geodesics end up on i displaystyle i nbsp the past timelike infinity Future directed null geodesics end up on ℐ the future null infinity Past directed null geodesics end up on ℐ the past null infinity Spacelike geodesics end up on spacelike infinity In various spaces Minkowski space i displaystyle i pm nbsp are points ℐ are null sheets and spacelike infinity has codimension 2 Anti de Sitter space there s no timelike or null infinity and spacelike infinity has codimension 1 de Sitter space the future and past timelike infinity has codimension 1 Gravitational singularity editMain article Gravitational singularity If a geodesic terminates after a finite affine parameter and it is not possible to extend the manifold to extend the geodesic then we have a singularity For black holes the future timelike boundary ends on a singularity in some places For the Big Bang the past timelike boundary is also a singularity The absolute event horizon is the past null cone of the future timelike infinity It is generated by null geodesics which obey the Raychaudhuri optical equation See also editCausal dynamical triangulation CDT Causality conditions Causal sets Cauchy surface Closed timelike curve Cosmic censorship hypothesis Globally hyperbolic manifold Malament Hogarth spacetime Null infinity Penrose diagram Penrose Hawking singularity theorems SpacetimeNotes edit Hawking amp Israel 1979 p 255 Galloway Gregory J Notes on Lorentzian causality PDF ESI EMS IAMP Summer School on Mathematical Relativity University of Miami p 4 Retrieved 2 July 2021 Penrose 1972 p 15 a b Papadopoulos Kyriakos Acharjee Santanu Papadopoulos Basil K May 2018 The order on the light cone and its induced topology International Journal of Geometric Methods in Modern Physics 15 5 1850069 1851572 arXiv 1710 05177 Bibcode 2018IJGMM 1550069P doi 10 1142 S021988781850069X S2CID 119120311 a b c d e f Penrose 1972 p 12 Stoica O C 25 May 2016 Spacetime Causal Structure and Dimension from Horismotic Relation Journal of Gravity 2016 1 6 arXiv 1504 03265 doi 10 1155 2016 6151726 a b Sard 1970 p 78 Hawking amp Ellis 1973 p 42References editHawking S W Ellis G F R 1973 The Large Scale Structure of Space Time Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 20016 4 Hawking S W Israel W 1979 General Relativity an Einstein Centenary Survey Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 22285 0 Penrose R 1972 Techniques of Differential Topology in Relativity SIAM ISBN 0898710057 Sard R D 1970 Relativistic Mechanics Special Relativity and Classical Particle Dynamics New York W A Benjamin ISBN 978 0805384918 Further reading editG W Gibbons S N Solodukhin The Geometry of Small Causal Diamonds arXiv hep th 0703098 Causal intervals S W Hawking A R King P J McCarthy A new topology for curved space time which incorporates the causal differential and conformal structures J Math Phys 17 2 174 181 1976 Geometry Causal Structure A V Levichev Prescribing the conformal geometry of a lorentz manifold by means of its causal structure Soviet Math Dokl 35 452 455 1987 Geometry Causal Structure D Malament The class of continuous timelike curves determines the topology of spacetime J Math Phys 18 7 1399 1404 1977 Geometry Causal Structure A A Robb A theory of time and space Cambridge University Press 1914 Geometry Causal Structure A A Robb The absolute relations of time and space Cambridge University Press 1921 Geometry Causal Structure A A Robb Geometry of Time and Space Cambridge University Press 1936 Geometry Causal Structure R D Sorkin E Woolgar A Causal Order for Spacetimes with C 0 Lorentzian Metrics Proof of Compactness of the Space of Causal Curves Classical amp Quantum Gravity 13 1971 1994 1996 arXiv gr qc 9508018 Causal Structure External links editTuring Machine Causal Networks by Enrique Zeleny the Wolfram Demonstrations Project Weisstein Eric W Causal Network MathWorld Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Causal structure amp oldid 1217667613, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.