fbpx
Wikipedia

Cauchy's theorem (group theory)

In mathematics, specifically group theory, Cauchy's theorem states that if G is a finite group and p is a prime number dividing the order of G (the number of elements in G), then G contains an element of order p. That is, there is x in G such that p is the smallest positive integer with xp = e, where e is the identity element of G. It is named after Augustin-Louis Cauchy, who discovered it in 1845.[1][2]

The theorem is related to Lagrange's theorem, which states that the order of any subgroup of a finite group G divides the order of G. Cauchy's theorem implies that for any prime divisor p of the order of G, there is a subgroup of G whose order is p—the cyclic group generated by the element in Cauchy's theorem.

Cauchy's theorem is generalized by Sylow's first theorem, which implies that if pn is the maximal power of p dividing the order of G, then G has a subgroup of order pn (and using the fact that a p-group is solvable, one can show that G has subgroups of order pr for any r less than or equal to n).

Statement and proof

Many texts prove the theorem with the use of strong induction and the class equation, though considerably less machinery is required to prove the theorem in the abelian case. One can also invoke group actions for the proof.[3]

Cauchy's theorem — Let G be a finite group and p be a prime. If p divides the order of G, then G has an element of order p.

Proof 1

We first prove the special case that where G is abelian, and then the general case; both proofs are by induction on n = |G|, and have as starting case n = p which is trivial because any non-identity element now has order p. Suppose first that G is abelian. Take any non-identity element a, and let H be the cyclic group it generates. If p divides |H|, then a|H|/p is an element of order p. If p does not divide |H|, then it divides the order [G:H] of the quotient group G/H, which therefore contains an element of order p by the inductive hypothesis. That element is a class xH for some x in G, and if m is the order of x in G, then xm = e in G gives (xH)m = eH in G/H, so p divides m; as before xm/p is now an element of order p in G, completing the proof for the abelian case.

In the general case, let Z be the center of G, which is an abelian subgroup. If p divides |Z|, then Z contains an element of order p by the case of abelian groups, and this element works for G as well. So we may assume that p does not divide the order of Z. Since p does divide |G|, and G is the disjoint union of Z and of the conjugacy classes of non-central elements, there exists a conjugacy class of a non-central element a whose size is not divisible by p. But the class equation shows that size is [G : CG(a)], so p divides the order of the centralizer CG(a) of a in G, which is a proper subgroup because a is not central. This subgroup contains an element of order p by the inductive hypothesis, and we are done.

Proof 2

This proof uses the fact that for any action of a (cyclic) group of prime order p, the only possible orbit sizes are 1 and p, which is immediate from the orbit stabilizer theorem.

The set that our cyclic group shall act on is the set

 

of p-tuples of elements of G whose product (in order) gives the identity. Such a p-tuple is uniquely determined by all its components except the last one, as the last element must be the inverse of the product of those preceding elements. One also sees that those p − 1 elements can be chosen freely, so X has |G|p−1 elements, which is divisible by p.

Now from the fact that in a group if ab = e then also ba = e, it follows that any cyclic permutation of the components of an element of X again gives an element of X. Therefore one can define an action of the cyclic group Cp of order p on X by cyclic permutations of components, in other words in which a chosen generator of Cp sends

 .

As remarked, orbits in X under this action either have size 1 or size p. The former happens precisely for those tuples   for which  . Counting the elements of X by orbits, and reducing modulo p, one sees that the number of elements satisfying   is divisible by p. But x = e is one such element, so there must be at least p − 1 other solutions for x, and these solutions are elements of order p. This completes the proof.

Uses

A practically immediate consequence of Cauchy's theorem is a useful characterization of finite p-groups, where p is a prime. In particular, a finite group G is a p-group (i.e. all of its elements have order pk for some natural number k) if and only if G has order pn for some natural number n. One may use the abelian case of Cauchy's Theorem in an inductive proof[4] of the first of Sylow's theorems, similar to the first proof above, although there are also proofs that avoid doing this special case separately.

Example 1

Let G be a finite group where x2 = e for all elements x of G. Then G has the order 2n for some non negative integer n. Let |G| equal m. In the case of m is 1, then G = {e}. In the case of m ≥ 2, if m has the odd prime factor p, G has the element x where xp = e from Cauchy's theorem. It conflicts with the assumption. Therefore m must be 2n.[5] G is an abelian group, and G is called an elementary abelian 2-group or Boolean group. The well-known example is Klein four-group.

Example 2

An abelian simple group is either {e} or cyclic group Cp whose order is a prime number p. Let G is an abelian group, then all subgroups of G are normal subgroups. So, if G is a simple group, G has only normal subgroup that is either {e} or G. If |G| = 1, then G is {e}. It is suitable. If |G| ≥ 2, let aG is not e, the cyclic group   is subgroup of G and   is not {e}, then   Let n is the order of  . If n is infinite, then

 

So in this case, it is not suitable. Then n is finite. If n is composite, n is divisible by prime q which is less than n. From Cauchy's theorem, the subgroup H will be exist whose order is q, it is not suitable. Therefore, n must be a prime number.

Notes

  1. ^ Cauchy 1845.
  2. ^ Cauchy 1932.
  3. ^ McKay 1959.
  4. ^ Jacobson 2009, p. 80.
  5. ^ Finite groups where x2=e has order 2n, Stack Exchange, 2015-09-23

References

  • Cauchy, Augustin-Louis (1845), "Mémoire sur les arrangements que l'on peut former avec des lettres données, et sur les permutations ou substitutions à l'aide desquelles on passe d'un arrangement à un autre", Exercises d'analyse et de physique mathématique, Paris, 3: 151–252
  • Cauchy, Augustin-Louis (1932), "Oeuvres complètes" (PDF), Lilliad - Université de Lille - Sciences et Technologies, second series (reprinted ed.), Paris: Gauthier-Villars, 13: 171–282
  • Jacobson, Nathan (2009) [1985], Basic Algebra, Dover Books on Mathematics, vol. I (Second ed.), Dover Publications, p. 80, ISBN 978-0-486-47189-1
  • McKay, James H. (1959), "Another proof of Cauchy's group theorem", American Mathematical Monthly, 66 (2): 119, CiteSeerX 10.1.1.434.3544, doi:10.2307/2310010, JSTOR 2310010, MR 0098777, Zbl 0082.02601
  • Meo, M. (2004), "The mathematical life of Cauchy's group theorem", Historia Mathematica, 31 (2): 196–221, doi:10.1016/S0315-0860(03)00003-X

External links

cauchy, theorem, group, theory, other, theorems, attributed, augustin, louis, cauchy, cauchy, theorem, disambiguation, mathematics, specifically, group, theory, cauchy, theorem, states, that, finite, group, prime, number, dividing, order, number, elements, the. For other theorems attributed to Augustin Louis Cauchy see Cauchy theorem disambiguation In mathematics specifically group theory Cauchy s theorem states that if G is a finite group and p is a prime number dividing the order of G the number of elements in G then G contains an element of order p That is there is x in G such that p is the smallest positive integer with x p e where e is the identity element of G It is named after Augustin Louis Cauchy who discovered it in 1845 1 2 The theorem is related to Lagrange s theorem which states that the order of any subgroup of a finite group G divides the order of G Cauchy s theorem implies that for any prime divisor p of the order of G there is a subgroup of G whose order is p the cyclic group generated by the element in Cauchy s theorem Cauchy s theorem is generalized by Sylow s first theorem which implies that if p n is the maximal power of p dividing the order of G then G has a subgroup of order p n and using the fact that a p group is solvable one can show that G has subgroups of order p r for any r less than or equal to n Contents 1 Statement and proof 1 1 Proof 1 1 2 Proof 2 2 Uses 2 1 Example 1 2 2 Example 2 3 Notes 4 References 5 External linksStatement and proof EditMany texts prove the theorem with the use of strong induction and the class equation though considerably less machinery is required to prove the theorem in the abelian case One can also invoke group actions for the proof 3 Cauchy s theorem Let G be a finite group and p be a prime If p divides the order of G then G has an element of order p Proof 1 Edit We first prove the special case that where G is abelian and then the general case both proofs are by induction on n G and have as starting case n p which is trivial because any non identity element now has order p Suppose first that G is abelian Take any non identity element a and let H be the cyclic group it generates If p divides H then a H p is an element of order p If p does not divide H then it divides the order G H of the quotient group G H which therefore contains an element of order p by the inductive hypothesis That element is a class xH for some x in G and if m is the order of x in G then x m e in G gives xH m eH in G H so p divides m as before x m p is now an element of order p in G completing the proof for the abelian case In the general case let Z be the center of G which is an abelian subgroup If p divides Z then Z contains an element of order p by the case of abelian groups and this element works for G as well So we may assume that p does not divide the order of Z Since p does divide G and G is the disjoint union of Z and of the conjugacy classes of non central elements there exists a conjugacy class of a non central element a whose size is not divisible by p But the class equation shows that size is G C G a so p divides the order of the centralizer C G a of a in G which is a proper subgroup because a is not central This subgroup contains an element of order p by the inductive hypothesis and we are done Proof 2 Edit This proof uses the fact that for any action of a cyclic group of prime order p the only possible orbit sizes are 1 and p which is immediate from the orbit stabilizer theorem The set that our cyclic group shall act on is the set X x 1 x p G p x 1 x 2 x p e displaystyle X x 1 ldots x p in G p x 1 x 2 cdots x p e of p tuples of elements of G whose product in order gives the identity Such a p tuple is uniquely determined by all its components except the last one as the last element must be the inverse of the product of those preceding elements One also sees that those p 1 elements can be chosen freely so X has G p 1 elements which is divisible by p Now from the fact that in a group if ab e then also ba e it follows that any cyclic permutation of the components of an element of X again gives an element of X Therefore one can define an action of the cyclic group C p of order p on X by cyclic permutations of components in other words in which a chosen generator of C p sends x 1 x 2 x p x 2 x p x 1 displaystyle x 1 x 2 ldots x p mapsto x 2 ldots x p x 1 As remarked orbits in X under this action either have size 1 or size p The former happens precisely for those tuples x x x displaystyle x x ldots x for which x p e displaystyle x p e Counting the elements of X by orbits and reducing modulo p one sees that the number of elements satisfying x p e displaystyle x p e is divisible by p But x e is one such element so there must be at least p 1 other solutions for x and these solutions are elements of order p This completes the proof Uses EditA practically immediate consequence of Cauchy s theorem is a useful characterization of finite p groups where p is a prime In particular a finite group G is a p group i e all of its elements have order p k for some natural number k if and only if G has order p n for some natural number n One may use the abelian case of Cauchy s Theorem in an inductive proof 4 of the first of Sylow s theorems similar to the first proof above although there are also proofs that avoid doing this special case separately Example 1 Edit Some of this section s listed sources may not be reliable Please help this article by looking for better more reliable sources Unreliable citations may be challenged or deleted February 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message Let G be a finite group where x 2 e for all elements x of G Then G has the order 2n for some non negative integer n Let G equal m In the case of m is 1 then G e In the case of m 2 if m has the odd prime factor p G has the element x where xp e from Cauchy s theorem It conflicts with the assumption Therefore m must be 2n 5 G is an abelian group and G is called an elementary abelian 2 group or Boolean group The well known example is Klein four group Example 2 Edit This section does not cite any sources Please help improve this section by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed February 2021 Learn how and when to remove this template message An abelian simple group is either e or cyclic group Cp whose order is a prime number p Let G is an abelian group then all subgroups of G are normal subgroups So if G is a simple group G has only normal subgroup that is either e or G If G 1 then G is e It is suitable If G 2 let a G is not e the cyclic group a displaystyle langle a rangle is subgroup of G and a displaystyle langle a rangle is not e then G a displaystyle G langle a rangle Let n is the order of a displaystyle langle a rangle If n is infinite then G a a 2 e displaystyle G langle a rangle supsetneqq langle a 2 rangle supsetneqq e So in this case it is not suitable Then n is finite If n is composite n is divisible by prime q which is less than n From Cauchy s theorem the subgroup H will be exist whose order is q it is not suitable Therefore n must be a prime number Notes Edit Cauchy 1845 Cauchy 1932 McKay 1959 Jacobson 2009 p 80 Finite groups where x 2 e has order 2n Stack Exchange 2015 09 23References EditCauchy Augustin Louis 1845 Memoire sur les arrangements que l on peut former avec des lettres donnees et sur les permutations ou substitutions a l aide desquelles on passe d un arrangement a un autre Exercises d analyse et de physique mathematique Paris 3 151 252 Cauchy Augustin Louis 1932 Oeuvres completes PDF Lilliad Universite de Lille Sciences et Technologies second series reprinted ed Paris Gauthier Villars 13 171 282 Jacobson Nathan 2009 1985 Basic Algebra Dover Books on Mathematics vol I Second ed Dover Publications p 80 ISBN 978 0 486 47189 1 McKay James H 1959 Another proof of Cauchy s group theorem American Mathematical Monthly 66 2 119 CiteSeerX 10 1 1 434 3544 doi 10 2307 2310010 JSTOR 2310010 MR 0098777 Zbl 0082 02601 Meo M 2004 The mathematical life of Cauchy s group theorem Historia Mathematica 31 2 196 221 doi 10 1016 S0315 0860 03 00003 XExternal links Edit Cauchy s theorem PlanetMath Proof of Cauchy s theorem PlanetMath Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Cauchy 27s theorem group theory amp oldid 1136440384, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.