fbpx
Wikipedia

Borde–Guth–Vilenkin theorem

The Borde–Guth–Vilenkin (BGV) theorem is a theorem in physical cosmology which deduces that any universe that has, on average, been expanding throughout its history cannot be infinite in the past but must have a past spacetime boundary.[1] It is named after the authors Arvind Borde, Alan Guth and Alexander Vilenkin, who developed its mathematical formulation in 2003.[2][3] The BGV theorem is also popular outside physics, especially in religious and philosophical debates.[3][4][5]

Definition edit

In general relativity, the geodesics represent the paths that free-falling particles or objects follow in curved spacetime. These paths are the equivalent of the shortest path (straight lines) between two points in Euclidean space. In cosmology, a spacetime is said to be geodesically complete if all its geodesics can be extended indefinitely without encountering any singularities or boundaries. On the contrary, a spacetime that is geodesically past-incomplete features geodesics that reach a boundary or a singularity within a finite amount of proper time into the past.

In this context, we can define the average expansion rate as

 

where ti is an initial time (τi is the proper initial time), tf a final time (τf is the proper final time), and H is the expansion parameter, also called the Hubble parameter.

The BGV theorem states that for any spacetime where

 ,

then the spacetime is geodesically past-incomplete.

The theorem only applies to classical spacetime, but it does not assume any specific mass content of the universe and it does not require gravity to be described by Einstein field equations.

Derivation edit

For FLRW metric edit

Here is an example of derivation of the BGV theorem for an expanding homogeneous isotropic flat universe (in units of speed of light c=1).[6] Which is consistent with ΛCDM model, the current model of cosmology. However, this derivation can be generalized to an arbitrary space-time with no appeal to homogeneity or isotropy.[6]

The Friedmann–Lemaître–Robertson–Walker metric is given by

 ,

where t is time, xi (i=1,2,3) are the spatial coordinates and a(t) is the scale factor. Along a timeline geodesic xi = constant, we can consider the universe to be filled with comoving particles. For an observer with proper time τ following the world line xμ(τ), has a 4-momentum  , where   is the energy, m is the mass and p=|p| the magnitude of the 3-momentum.

From the geodesic equation of motion, it follows that   where pf is the final momentum at time tf. Thus

 ,

where   is the Hubble parameter, and

 ,

γ being the Lorentz factor. For any non-comoving observer γ>1 and F(γ)>0.

Assuming   it is follows that

 .

Thereby any non-comoving past-directed timelike geodesic satisfying the condition  , must have a finite proper length, and so must be past-incomplete.

Implications edit

Current astronomical observations, show that the universe is expanding, thus the BGV implies that there must be a boundary or singularity in the history of the universe. This singularity has often been associated to the Big Bang. However the theorem does not tell if it is associated to any other event in the past. The theorem also does not allow to tell when the singularity takes place, or if it is a gravitational singularity or any other kind of boundary condition.[7]

Some physical theories do not discard the possibility of a non-accelerated expansion before a certain moment in time. For example, the expansion rate could be different from   up to the period of inflation.[7]

Limitations and criticism edit

Alternative models, where the average expansion of the universe throughout its history does not hold, have been proposed under the notions of emergent spacetime, eternal inflation, and cyclic models. Vilenkin and Audrey Mithani have argued that none of these models escape the implications of the theorem.[8] In 2017, Vilenkin stated that he does not think there are any viable cosmological models that escape the scenario.[9]

Sean M. Carroll argues that the theorem only applies to classical spacetime, and may not hold under consideration of a complete theory of quantum gravity. He added that Alan Guth, one of the co-authors of the theorem, disagrees with Vilenkin and believes that the universe had no beginning.[10][11] Vilenkin argues that the Carroll-Chen model constructed by Carroll and Jennie Chen, and supported by Guth, to elude the BGV theorem's conclusions persists to indicate a singularity in the history of the universe as it has a reversal of the arrow of time in the past.[12]

Joseph E. Lesnefsky, Damien A. Easson and Paul Davies constructed an uncountable infinite class of classical solutions which have   and are geodesically complete.[13] The authors claim that the geodesic incompleteness of inflationary spacetime is still an open issue. Furthermore, there are examples of infinite cyclic models solving the problem of unbounded entropy growth which are geodesically complete.[14] In both of these studies, the authors argue that the previous investigations often did not use mathematically precise formulations of the BGV theorem and thus reached incomplete conclusions.

Use in theology edit

Vilenkin has also written about the religious significance of the BGV theorem. In October 2015, Vilenkin responded to arguments made by theist William Lane Craig and the New Atheism movement regarding the existence of God. Vilenkin stated "What causes the universe to pop out of nothing? No cause is needed."[6]

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ Perlov, Delia; Vilenkin, Alexander (7 August 2017). Cosmology for the Curious. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. pp. 330–31. ISBN 978-3319570402.
  2. ^ Borde, Arvind; Guth, Alan H.; Vilenkin, Alexander (15 April 2003). "Inflationary space-times are incomplete in past directions". Physical Review Letters. 90 (15): 151301. arXiv:gr-qc/0110012. Bibcode:2003PhRvL..90o1301B. doi:10.1103/PhysRevLett.90.151301. PMID 12732026. S2CID 46902994.
  3. ^ a b Perlov, Delia; Vilenkin, Alexander (7 August 2017). Cosmology for the Curious. Cham, Switzerland: Springer. pp. 330–31. ISBN 978-3319570402.
  4. ^ Copan, Paul; Craig, William Lane (2017-11-16). The Kalam Cosmological Argument, Volume 2: Scientific Evidence for the Beginning of the Universe. Bloomsbury Publishing USA. ISBN 9781501335891.
  5. ^ Nagasawa, Y. (2012-07-25). Scientific Approaches to the Philosophy of Religion. Springer. ISBN 9781137026019.
  6. ^ a b c Vilenkin, Alexander (2015-10-23). . Inference. 1 (4). Archived from the original on 27 December 2023.
  7. ^ a b Calcagni, Gianluca (2017-01-06). Classical and Quantum Cosmology. Springer. ISBN 978-3-319-41127-9.
  8. ^ Mithani, Audrey; Vilenkin, Alexander (20 April 2012). "Did the universe have a beginning?". arXiv:1204.4658 [hep-th].
  9. ^ Alexander Vilenkin, "The Beginning of the Universe" in The Kalam Cosmological Argument: Volume 2, Bloomsbury, 2017, pp. 150–158
  10. ^ Carroll, Sean (2014-02-24). "Post-Debate Reflections". Sean Carroll Blog. from the original on 2014-02-25. Retrieved 2019-11-19.
  11. ^ Carroll, Sean M. (2018-06-04). "Why Is There Something, Rather Than Nothing?". arXiv:1802.02231 [physics.hist-ph].
  12. ^ Vilenkin, Alexander (2013). "Arrows of time and the beginning of the universe". Physical Review D. 88 (4): 043516. arXiv:1305.3836. Bibcode:2013PhRvD..88d3516V. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.88.043516. S2CID 119213877.
  13. ^ Lesnefsky, J. E.; Easson, D. A.; Davies, P. C. W. (2023). "Past-completeness of inflationary spacetimes". Physical Review D. 107 (4): 044024. arXiv:2207.00955. doi:10.1103/PhysRevD.107.044024.
  14. ^ Pavlović, Petar; Sossich, Marko (2024). "Geodesically complete cyclic cosmologies and entropy". European Physical Journal C. 84 (3) 242. arXiv:2305.06719. doi:10.1140/epjc/s10052-024-12621-z.

Further reading edit

  • Calcagni, Gianluca (2017-01-06). Classical and Quantum Cosmology. Springer. ISBN 9783319411279.

borde, guth, vilenkin, theorem, this, article, relies, excessively, references, primary, sources, please, improve, this, article, adding, secondary, tertiary, sources, find, sources, news, newspapers, books, scholar, jstor, march, 2021, learn, when, remove, th. This article relies excessively on references to primary sources Please improve this article by adding secondary or tertiary sources Find sources Borde Guth Vilenkin theorem news newspapers books scholar JSTOR March 2021 Learn how and when to remove this message The Borde Guth Vilenkin BGV theorem is a theorem in physical cosmology which deduces that any universe that has on average been expanding throughout its history cannot be infinite in the past but must have a past spacetime boundary 1 It is named after the authors Arvind Borde Alan Guth and Alexander Vilenkin who developed its mathematical formulation in 2003 2 3 The BGV theorem is also popular outside physics especially in religious and philosophical debates 3 4 5 Contents 1 Definition 2 Derivation 2 1 For FLRW metric 3 Implications 4 Limitations and criticism 5 Use in theology 6 See also 7 References 8 Further readingDefinition editIn general relativity the geodesics represent the paths that free falling particles or objects follow in curved spacetime These paths are the equivalent of the shortest path straight lines between two points in Euclidean space In cosmology a spacetime is said to be geodesically complete if all its geodesics can be extended indefinitely without encountering any singularities or boundaries On the contrary a spacetime that is geodesically past incomplete features geodesics that reach a boundary or a singularity within a finite amount of proper time into the past In this context we can define the average expansion rate as H a v 1 t f t i t i t f H t d t displaystyle H rm av frac 1 tau rm f tau rm i int t rm i t rm f H tau d tau nbsp where ti is an initial time ti is the proper initial time tf a final time tf is the proper final time and H is the expansion parameter also called the Hubble parameter The BGV theorem states that for any spacetime whereH a v gt 0 displaystyle H rm av gt 0 nbsp then the spacetime is geodesically past incomplete The theorem only applies to classical spacetime but it does not assume any specific mass content of the universe and it does not require gravity to be described by Einstein field equations Derivation editFor FLRW metric edit Here is an example of derivation of the BGV theorem for an expanding homogeneous isotropic flat universe in units of speed of light c 1 6 Which is consistent with LCDM model the current model of cosmology However this derivation can be generalized to an arbitrary space time with no appeal to homogeneity or isotropy 6 The Friedmann Lemaitre Robertson Walker metric is given by d s d t 2 a 2 t d x i d x i displaystyle ds dt 2 a 2 t dx i dx i nbsp where t is time xi i 1 2 3 are the spatial coordinates and a t is the scale factor Along a timeline geodesic xi constant we can consider the universe to be filled with comoving particles For an observer with proper time t following the world line xm t has a 4 momentum P m m d x m d t E p displaystyle P mu mdx mu d tau E mathbf p nbsp where E p 2 m 2 displaystyle E sqrt p 2 m 2 nbsp is the energy m is the mass and p p the magnitude of the 3 momentum From the geodesic equation of motion it follows that p t p f a t f a t displaystyle p t p rm f a t rm f a t nbsp where pf is the final momentum at time tf Thus t i t f H t d t a t i a t f m d a m 2 a 2 p 2 a t f F g f F g i F g f displaystyle int t rm i t rm f H tau d tau int a t rm i a t rm f frac mda sqrt m 2 a 2 p 2 a t rm f F gamma rm f F gamma rm i leq F gamma rm f nbsp where H a a displaystyle H dot a a nbsp is the Hubble parameter and F g 1 2 ln g 1 g 1 displaystyle F gamma frac 1 2 ln left frac gamma 1 gamma 1 right nbsp g being the Lorentz factor For any non comoving observer g gt 1 and F g gt 0 Assuming H a v gt 0 displaystyle H rm av gt 0 nbsp it is follows that t f t i F g f H a v displaystyle tau rm f tau rm i leq frac F gamma rm f H rm av nbsp Thereby any non comoving past directed timelike geodesic satisfying the condition H a v gt 0 displaystyle H rm av gt 0 nbsp must have a finite proper length and so must be past incomplete Implications editCurrent astronomical observations show that the universe is expanding thus the BGV implies that there must be a boundary or singularity in the history of the universe This singularity has often been associated to the Big Bang However the theorem does not tell if it is associated to any other event in the past The theorem also does not allow to tell when the singularity takes place or if it is a gravitational singularity or any other kind of boundary condition 7 Some physical theories do not discard the possibility of a non accelerated expansion before a certain moment in time For example the expansion rate could be different from H a v gt 0 displaystyle H rm av gt 0 nbsp up to the period of inflation 7 Limitations and criticism editAlternative models where the average expansion of the universe throughout its history does not hold have been proposed under the notions of emergent spacetime eternal inflation and cyclic models Vilenkin and Audrey Mithani have argued that none of these models escape the implications of the theorem 8 In 2017 Vilenkin stated that he does not think there are any viable cosmological models that escape the scenario 9 Sean M Carroll argues that the theorem only applies to classical spacetime and may not hold under consideration of a complete theory of quantum gravity He added that Alan Guth one of the co authors of the theorem disagrees with Vilenkin and believes that the universe had no beginning 10 11 Vilenkin argues that the Carroll Chen model constructed by Carroll and Jennie Chen and supported by Guth to elude the BGV theorem s conclusions persists to indicate a singularity in the history of the universe as it has a reversal of the arrow of time in the past 12 Joseph E Lesnefsky Damien A Easson and Paul Davies constructed an uncountable infinite class of classical solutions which have H a v 0 displaystyle H rm av geq 0 nbsp and are geodesically complete 13 The authors claim that the geodesic incompleteness of inflationary spacetime is still an open issue Furthermore there are examples of infinite cyclic models solving the problem of unbounded entropy growth which are geodesically complete 14 In both of these studies the authors argue that the previous investigations often did not use mathematically precise formulations of the BGV theorem and thus reached incomplete conclusions Use in theology editVilenkin has also written about the religious significance of the BGV theorem In October 2015 Vilenkin responded to arguments made by theist William Lane Craig and the New Atheism movement regarding the existence of God Vilenkin stated What causes the universe to pop out of nothing No cause is needed 6 See also editKalam cosmological argument Gibbons Hawking York boundary term Gibbons Hawking effect Penrose Hawking singularity theoremsReferences edit Perlov Delia Vilenkin Alexander 7 August 2017 Cosmology for the Curious Cham Switzerland Springer pp 330 31 ISBN 978 3319570402 Borde Arvind Guth Alan H Vilenkin Alexander 15 April 2003 Inflationary space times are incomplete in past directions Physical Review Letters 90 15 151301 arXiv gr qc 0110012 Bibcode 2003PhRvL 90o1301B doi 10 1103 PhysRevLett 90 151301 PMID 12732026 S2CID 46902994 a b Perlov Delia Vilenkin Alexander 7 August 2017 Cosmology for the Curious Cham Switzerland Springer pp 330 31 ISBN 978 3319570402 Copan Paul Craig William Lane 2017 11 16 The Kalam Cosmological Argument Volume 2 Scientific Evidence for the Beginning of the Universe Bloomsbury Publishing USA ISBN 9781501335891 Nagasawa Y 2012 07 25 Scientific Approaches to the Philosophy of Religion Springer ISBN 9781137026019 a b c Vilenkin Alexander 2015 10 23 The Beginning of the Universe Inference 1 4 Archived from the original on 27 December 2023 a b Calcagni Gianluca 2017 01 06 Classical and Quantum Cosmology Springer ISBN 978 3 319 41127 9 Mithani Audrey Vilenkin Alexander 20 April 2012 Did the universe have a beginning arXiv 1204 4658 hep th Alexander Vilenkin The Beginning of the Universe in The Kalam Cosmological Argument Volume 2 Bloomsbury 2017 pp 150 158 Carroll Sean 2014 02 24 Post Debate Reflections Sean Carroll Blog Archived from the original on 2014 02 25 Retrieved 2019 11 19 Carroll Sean M 2018 06 04 Why Is There Something Rather Than Nothing arXiv 1802 02231 physics hist ph Vilenkin Alexander 2013 Arrows of time and the beginning of the universe Physical Review D 88 4 043516 arXiv 1305 3836 Bibcode 2013PhRvD 88d3516V doi 10 1103 PhysRevD 88 043516 S2CID 119213877 Lesnefsky J E Easson D A Davies P C W 2023 Past completeness of inflationary spacetimes Physical Review D 107 4 044024 arXiv 2207 00955 doi 10 1103 PhysRevD 107 044024 Pavlovic Petar Sossich Marko 2024 Geodesically complete cyclic cosmologies and entropy European Physical Journal C 84 3 242 arXiv 2305 06719 doi 10 1140 epjc s10052 024 12621 z Further reading editCalcagni Gianluca 2017 01 06 Classical and Quantum Cosmology Springer ISBN 9783319411279 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Borde Guth Vilenkin theorem amp oldid 1216620235, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.