fbpx
Wikipedia

Bayes' theorem

In probability theory and statistics, Bayes' theorem (/bz/ BAYZ or /bzɪz/ BAY-ziz; alternatively Bayes' law or Bayes' rule)[1][2], named after Thomas Bayes, describes the probability of an event, based on prior knowledge of conditions that might be related to the event.[3] For example, if the risk of developing health problems is known to increase with age, Bayes' theorem allows the risk to an individual of a known age to be assessed more accurately by conditioning it relative to their age, rather than simply assuming that the individual is typical of the population as a whole.

One of the many applications of Bayes' theorem is Bayesian inference, a particular approach to statistical inference. When applied, the probabilities involved in the theorem may have different probability interpretations. With Bayesian probability interpretation, the theorem expresses how a degree of belief, expressed as a probability, should rationally change to account for the availability of related evidence. Bayesian inference is fundamental to Bayesian statistics, being considered by one authority as; "to the theory of probability what Pythagoras's theorem is to geometry."[4]

History

Bayes' theorem is named after the Reverend Thomas Bayes (/bz/), also a statistician and philosopher. Bayes used conditional probability to provide an algorithm (his Proposition 9) that uses evidence to calculate limits on an unknown parameter. His work was published in 1763 as An Essay towards solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances. Bayes studied how to compute a distribution for the probability parameter of a binomial distribution (in modern terminology). On Bayes's death his family transferred his papers to a friend, the minister, philosopher, and mathematician Richard Price.

Over two years, Richard Price significantly edited the unpublished manuscript, before sending it to a friend who read it aloud at the Royal Society on 23 December 1763.[5] Price edited[6] Bayes's major work "An Essay towards solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances" (1763), which appeared in Philosophical Transactions,[7] and contains Bayes' theorem. Price wrote an introduction to the paper which provides some of the philosophical basis of Bayesian statistics and chose one of the two solutions offered by Bayes. In 1765, Price was elected a Fellow of the Royal Society in recognition of his work on the legacy of Bayes.[8][9] On 27 April a letter sent to his friend Benjamin Franklin was read out at the Royal Society, and later published, where Price applies this work to population and computing 'life-annuities'.[10]

Independently of Bayes, Pierre-Simon Laplace in 1774, and later in his 1812 Théorie analytique des probabilités, used conditional probability to formulate the relation of an updated posterior probability from a prior probability, given evidence. He reproduced and extended Bayes's results in 1774, apparently unaware of Bayes's work.[note 1][11] The Bayesian interpretation of probability was developed mainly by Laplace.[12]

About 200 years later, Sir Harold Jeffreys put Bayes's algorithm and Laplace's formulation on an axiomatic basis, writing in a 1973 book that Bayes' theorem "is to the theory of probability what the Pythagorean theorem is to geometry".[13]

Stephen Stigler used a Bayesian argument to conclude that Bayes' theorem was discovered by Nicholas Saunderson, a blind English mathematician, some time before Bayes;[14][15] that interpretation, however, has been disputed.[16] Martyn Hooper[17] and Sharon McGrayne[18] have argued that Richard Price's contribution was substantial:

By modern standards, we should refer to the Bayes–Price rule. Price discovered Bayes's work, recognized its importance, corrected it, contributed to the article, and found a use for it. The modern convention of employing Bayes's name alone is unfair but so entrenched that anything else makes little sense.[18]

Statement of theorem

Bayes' theorem is stated mathematically as the following equation:[19]

 

where   and   are events and  .

  •   is a conditional probability: the probability of event   occurring given that   is true. It is also called the posterior probability of   given  .
  •   is also a conditional probability: the probability of event   occurring given that   is true. It can also be interpreted as the likelihood of   given a fixed   because  .
  •   and   are the probabilities of observing   and   respectively without any given conditions; they are known as the prior probability and marginal probability.

Proof

For events

Bayes' theorem may be derived from the definition of conditional probability:

 

where   is the probability of both A and B being true. Similarly,

 

Solving for   and substituting into the above expression for   yields Bayes' theorem:

 

For continuous random variables

For two continuous random variables X and Y, Bayes' theorem may be analogously derived from the definition of conditional density:

 
 

Therefore,

 

General case

Let   be the conditional distribution of   given   and let   be the distribution of  . The joint distribution is then  . The conditional distribution   of   given   is then determined by

 

Existence and uniqueness of the needed conditional expectation is a consequence of the Radon–Nikodym theorem. This was formulated by Kolmogorov in his famous book from 1933. Kolmogorov underlines the importance of conditional probability by writing "I wish to call attention to ... and especially the theory of conditional probabilities and conditional expectations ..." in the Preface.[20] The Bayes theorem determines the posterior distribution from the prior distribution. Bayes' theorem can be generalized to include improper prior distributions such as the uniform distribution on the real line.[21] Modern Markov chain Monte Carlo methods have boosted the importance of Bayes' theorem including cases with improper priors.[22]

Examples

Recreational mathematics

Bayes' rule and computing conditional probabilities provide a solution method for a number of popular puzzles, such as the Three Prisoners problem, the Monty Hall problem, the Two Child problem and the Two Envelopes problem.

Drug testing

 
Figure 1: Using a frequency box to show   visually by comparison of shaded areas

Suppose, a particular test for whether someone has been using cannabis is 90% sensitive, meaning the true positive rate (TPR) = 0.90. Therefore, it leads to 90% true positive results (correct identification of drug use) for cannabis users.

The test is also 80% specific, meaning true negative rate (TNR) = 0.80. Therefore, the test correctly identifies 80% of non-use for non-users, but also generates 20% false positives, or false positive rate (FPR) = 0.20, for non-users.

Assuming 0.05 prevalence, meaning 5% of people use cannabis, what is the probability that a random person who tests positive is really a cannabis user?

The Positive predictive value (PPV) of a test is the proportion of persons who are actually positive out of all those testing positive, and can be calculated from a sample as:

PPV = True positive / Tested positive

If sensitivity, specificity, and prevalence are known, PPV can be calculated using Bayes theorem. Let   mean "the probability that someone is a cannabis user given that they test positive," which is what is meant by PPV. We can write:

 

The fact that   is a direct application of the Law of Total Probability. In this case, it says that the probability that someone tests positive is the probability that a user tests positive, times the probability of being a user, plus the probability that a non-user tests positive, times the probability of being a non-user. This is true because the classifications user and non-user form a partition of a set, namely the set of people who take the drug test. This combined with the definition of conditional probability results in the above statement.

In other words, even if someone tests positive, the probability that they are a cannabis user is only 19%—this is because in this group, only 5% of people are users, and most positives are false positives coming from the remaining 95%.

If 1,000 people were tested:

  • 950 are non-users and 190 of them give false positive (0.20 × 950)
  • 50 of them are users and 45 of them give true positive (0.90 × 50)

The 1,000 people thus yields 235 positive tests, of which only 45 are genuine drug users, about 19%. See Figure 1 for an illustration using a frequency box, and note how small the pink area of true positives is compared to the blue area of false positives.

Sensitivity or specificity

The importance of specificity can be seen by showing that even if sensitivity is raised to 100% and specificity remains at 80%, the probability of someone testing positive really being a cannabis user only rises from 19% to 21%, but if the sensitivity is held at 90% and the specificity is increased to 95%, the probability rises to 49%.

Test
Actual
Positive Negative Total
User 45 5 50
Non-user 190 760 950
Total 235 765 1000
90% sensitive, 80% specific, PPV=45/235 ≈ 19%
Test
Actual
Positive Negative Total
User 50 0 50
Non-user 190 760 950
Total 240 760 1000
100% sensitive, 80% specific, PPV=50/240 ≈ 21%
Test
Actual
Positive Negative Total
User 45 5 50
Non-user 47 903 950
Total 92 908 1000
90% sensitive, 95% specific, PPV=45/92 ≈ 49%

Cancer rate

Even if 100% of patients with pancreatic cancer have a certain symptom, when someone has the same symptom, it does not mean that this person has a 100% chance of getting pancreatic cancer. Assuming the incidence rate of pancreatic cancer is 1/100000, while 10/99999 healthy individuals have the same symptoms worldwide, the probability of having pancreatic cancer given the symptoms is only 9.1%, and the other 90.9% could be "false positives" (that is, falsely said to have cancer; "positive" is a confusing term when, as here, the test gives bad news).

Based on incidence rate, the following table presents the corresponding numbers per 100,000 people.

Symptom
Cancer
Yes No Total
Yes 1 0 1
No 10 99989 99999
Total 11 99989 100000

Which can then be used to calculate the probability of having cancer when you have the symptoms:

 

Defective item rate

Condition

Machine
Defective Flawless Total
A 10 190 200
B 9 291 300
C 5 495 500
Total 24 976 1000

A factory produces items using three machines—A, B, and C—which account for 20%, 30%, and 50% of its output respectively. Of the items produced by machine A, 5% are defective; similarly, 3% of machine B's items and 1% of machine C's are defective. If a randomly selected item is defective, what is the probability it was produced by machine C?

Once again, the answer can be reached without using the formula by applying the conditions to a hypothetical number of cases. For example, if the factory produces 1,000 items, 200 will be produced by Machine A, 300 by Machine B, and 500 by Machine C. Machine A will produce 5% × 200 = 10 defective items, Machine B 3% × 300 = 9, and Machine C 1% × 500 = 5, for a total of 24. Thus, the likelihood that a randomly selected defective item was produced by machine C is 5/24 (~20.83%).

This problem can also be solved using Bayes' theorem: Let Xi denote the event that a randomly chosen item was made by the i th machine (for i = A,B,C). Let Y denote the event that a randomly chosen item is defective. Then, we are given the following information:

 

If the item was made by the first machine, then the probability that it is defective is 0.05; that is, P(Y | XA) = 0.05. Overall, we have

 

To answer the original question, we first find P(Y). That can be done in the following way:

 

Hence, 2.4% of the total output is defective.

We are given that Y has occurred, and we want to calculate the conditional probability of XC. By Bayes' theorem,

 

Given that the item is defective, the probability that it was made by machine C is 5/24. Although machine C produces half of the total output, it produces a much smaller fraction of the defective items. Hence the knowledge that the item selected was defective enables us to replace the prior probability P(XC) = 1/2 by the smaller posterior probability P(XC | Y) = 5/24.

Interpretations

 
Figure 2: A geometric visualisation of Bayes' theorem

The interpretation of Bayes' rule depends on the interpretation of probability ascribed to the terms. The two predominant interpretations are described below. Figure 2 shows a geometric visualization.

Bayesian interpretation

In the Bayesian (or epistemological) interpretation, probability measures a "degree of belief". Bayes' theorem links the degree of belief in a proposition before and after accounting for evidence. For example, suppose it is believed with 50% certainty that a coin is twice as likely to land heads than tails. If the coin is flipped a number of times and the outcomes observed, that degree of belief will probably rise or fall, but might even remain the same, depending on the results. For proposition A and evidence B,

  • P (A), the prior, is the initial degree of belief in A.
  • P (A | B), the posterior, is the degree of belief after incorporating news that B is true.
  • the quotient P(B | A)/P(B) represents the support B provides for A.

For more on the application of Bayes' theorem under the Bayesian interpretation of probability, see Bayesian inference.

Frequentist interpretation

 
Figure 3: Illustration of frequentist interpretation with tree diagrams

In the frequentist interpretation, probability measures a "proportion of outcomes". For example, suppose an experiment is performed many times. P(A) is the proportion of outcomes with property A (the prior) and P(B) is the proportion with property B. P(B | A) is the proportion of outcomes with property B out of outcomes with property A, and P(A | B) is the proportion of those with A out of those with B (the posterior).

The role of Bayes' theorem is best visualized with tree diagrams such as Figure 3. The two diagrams partition the same outcomes by A and B in opposite orders, to obtain the inverse probabilities. Bayes' theorem links the different partitionings.

Example

 
Figure 4: Tree diagram illustrating the beetle example. R, C, P and   are the events rare, common, pattern and no pattern. Percentages in parentheses are calculated. Three independent values are given, so it is possible to calculate the inverse tree.

An entomologist spots what might, due to the pattern on its back, be a rare subspecies of beetle. A full 98% of the members of the rare subspecies have the pattern, so P(Pattern | Rare) = 98%. Only 5% of members of the common subspecies have the pattern. The rare subspecies is 0.1% of the total population. How likely is the beetle having the pattern to be rare: what is P(Rare | Pattern)?

From the extended form of Bayes' theorem (since any beetle is either rare or common),

 

Forms

Events

Simple form

For events A and B, provided that P(B) ≠ 0,

 

In many applications, for instance in Bayesian inference, the event B is fixed in the discussion, and we wish to consider the impact of its having been observed on our belief in various possible events A. In such a situation the denominator of the last expression, the probability of the given evidence B, is fixed; what we want to vary is A. Bayes' theorem then shows that the posterior probabilities are proportional to the numerator, so the last equation becomes:

 

In words, the posterior is proportional to the prior times the likelihood.[23]

If events A1, A2, ..., are mutually exclusive and exhaustive, i.e., one of them is certain to occur but no two can occur together, we can determine the proportionality constant by using the fact that their probabilities must add up to one. For instance, for a given event A, the event A itself and its complement ¬A are exclusive and exhaustive. Denoting the constant of proportionality by c we have

 

Adding these two formulas we deduce that

 

or

 

Alternative form

Contingency table
  Background

Proposition
B ¬B
(not B)
Total
A P(B|A)·P(A)
= P(A|B)·P(B)
P(¬B|A)·P(A)
= P(A|¬B)·P(¬B)
P(A)
¬A
(not A)
P(B|¬A)·P(¬A)
= P(¬A|B)·P(B)
P(¬B|¬A)·P(¬A)
= P(¬A|¬B)·P(¬B)
P(¬A) =
1−P(A)
Total    P(B)    P(¬B) = 1−P(B) 1

Another form of Bayes' theorem for two competing statements or hypotheses is:

 

For an epistemological interpretation:

For proposition A and evidence or background B,[24]

  •   is the prior probability, the initial degree of belief in A.
  •   is the corresponding initial degree of belief in not-A, that A is false, where  
  •   is the conditional probability or likelihood, the degree of belief in B given that proposition A is true.
  •   is the conditional probability or likelihood, the degree of belief in B given that proposition A is false.
  •   is the posterior probability, the probability of A after taking into account B.

Extended form

Often, for some partition {Aj} of the sample space, the event space is given in terms of P(Aj) and P(B | Aj). It is then useful to compute P(B) using the law of total probability:

 
 

In the special case where A is a binary variable:

 

Random variables

 
Figure 5: Bayes' theorem applied to an event space generated by continuous random variables X and Y. There exists an instance of Bayes' theorem for each point in the domain. In practice, these instances might be parametrized by writing the specified probability densities as a function of x and y.

Consider a sample space Ω generated by two random variables X and Y. In principle, Bayes' theorem applies to the events A = {X = x} and B = {Y = y}.

 

However, terms become 0 at points where either variable has finite probability density. To remain useful, Bayes' theorem must be formulated in terms of the relevant densities (see Derivation).

Simple form

If X is continuous and Y is discrete,

 

where each   is a density function.

If X is discrete and Y is continuous,

 

If both X and Y are continuous,

 

Extended form

 
Figure 6: A way to conceptualize event spaces generated by continuous random variables X and Y

A continuous event space is often conceptualized in terms of the numerator terms. It is then useful to eliminate the denominator using the law of total probability. For fY(y), this becomes an integral:

 

Bayes' rule in odds form

Bayes' theorem in odds form is:

 

where

 

is called the Bayes factor or likelihood ratio. The odds between two events is simply the ratio of the probabilities of the two events. Thus

 
 

Thus, the rule says that the posterior odds are the prior odds times the Bayes factor, or in other words, the posterior is proportional to the prior times the likelihood.

In the special case that   and  , one writes  , and uses a similar abbreviation for the Bayes factor and for the conditional odds. The odds on   is by definition the odds for and against  . Bayes' rule can then be written in the abbreviated form

 

or, in words, the posterior odds on   equals the prior odds on   times the likelihood ratio for   given information  . In short, posterior odds equals prior odds times likelihood ratio.

For example, if a medical test has a sensitivity of 90% and a specificity of 91%, then the positive Bayes factor is  . Now, if the prevalence of this disease is 9.09%, and if we take that as the prior probability, then the prior odds is about 1:10. So after receiving a positive test result, the posterior odds of actually having the disease becomes 1:1, which means that the posterior probability of having the disease is 50%. If a second test is performed in serial testing, and that also turns out to be positive, then the posterior odds of actually having the disease becomes 10:1, which means a posterior probability of about 90.91%. The negative Bayes factor can be calculated to be 91%/(100%-90%)=9.1, so if the second test turns out to be negative, then the posterior odds of actually having the disease is 1:9.1, which means a posterior probability of about 9.9%.

The example above can also be understood with more solid numbers: Assume the patient taking the test is from a group of 1000 people, where 91 of them actually have the disease (prevalence of 9.1%). If all these 1000 people take the medical test, 82 of those with the disease will get a true positive result (sensitivity of 90.1%), 9 of those with the disease will get a false negative result (false negative rate of 9.9%), 827 of those without the disease will get a true negative result (specificity of 91.0%), and 82 of those without the disease will get a false positive result (false positive rate of 9.0%). Before taking any test, the patient's odds for having the disease is 91:909. After receiving a positive result, the patient's odds for having the disease is

 

which is consistent with the fact that there are 82 true positives and 82 false positives in the group of 1000 people.

Correspondence to other mathematical frameworks

Propositional logic

Using   twice, one may use Bayes' theorem to also express   in terms of   and without negations:

 ,

when  . From this we can read off the inference

 .

In words: If certainly   implies  , we infer that certainly   implies  . Where  , the two implications being certain are equivalent statements. In the probability formulas, the conditional probability   generalizes the logical implication  , where now beyond assigning true or false, we assign probability values to statements. The assertion of   is captured by certainty of the conditional, the assertion of  . Relating the directions of implication, Bayes' theorem represents a generalization of the contraposition law, which in classical propositional logic can be expressed as:

 .

In this relation between implications, the positions of   resp.   get flipped.

The corresponding formula in terms of probability calculus is Bayes' theorem, which in its expanded form involving the prior probability/base rate   of only  , is expressed as:[25]

 .

Subjective logic

Bayes' theorem represents a special case of deriving inverted conditional opinions in subjective logic expressed as:

 

where   denotes the operator for inverting conditional opinions. The argument   denotes a pair of binomial conditional opinions given by source  , and the argument   denotes the prior probability (aka. the base rate) of  . The pair of derivative inverted conditional opinions is denoted  . The conditional opinion   generalizes the probabilistic conditional  , i.e. in addition to assigning a probability the source   can assign any subjective opinion to the conditional statement  . A binomial subjective opinion   is the belief in the truth of statement   with degrees of epistemic uncertainty, as expressed by source  . Every subjective opinion has a corresponding projected probability  . The application of Bayes' theorem to projected probabilities of opinions is a homomorphism, meaning that Bayes' theorem can be expressed in terms of projected probabilities of opinions:

 

Hence, the subjective Bayes' theorem represents a generalization of Bayes' theorem.[26]

Generalizations

Conditioned version

A conditioned version of the Bayes' theorem[27] results from the addition of a third event   on which all probabilities are conditioned:

 

Derivation

Using the chain rule

 

And, on the other hand

 

The desired result is obtained by identifying both expressions and solving for  .

Bayes' rule with 3 events

In the case of 3 events—A, B, and C—it can be shown that:

 
Proof[28]
 

Use in genetics

In genetics, Bayes' theorem can be used to calculate the probability of an individual having a specific genotype. Many people seek to approximate their chances of being affected by a genetic disease or their likelihood of being a carrier for a recessive gene of interest. A Bayesian analysis can be done based on family history or genetic testing, in order to predict whether an individual will develop a disease or pass one on to their children. Genetic testing and prediction is a common practice among couples who plan to have children but are concerned that they may both be carriers for a disease, especially within communities with low genetic variance.[29]

The first step in Bayesian analysis for genetics is to propose mutually exclusive hypotheses: for a specific allele, an individual either is or is not a carrier. Next, four probabilities are calculated: Prior Probability (the likelihood of each hypothesis considering information such as family history or predictions based on Mendelian Inheritance), Conditional Probability (of a certain outcome), Joint Probability (product of the first two), and Posterior Probability (a weighted product calculated by dividing the Joint Probability for each hypothesis by the sum of both joint probabilities). This type of analysis can be done based purely on family history of a condition or in concert with genetic testing.[citation needed]

Using pedigree to calculate probabilities

Hypothesis Hypothesis 1: Patient is a carrier Hypothesis 2: Patient is not a carrier
Prior Probability 1/2 1/2
Conditional Probability that all four offspring will be unaffected (1/2) · (1/2) · (1/2) · (1/2) = 1/16 About 1
Joint Probability (1/2) · (1/16) = 1/32 (1/2) · 1 = 1/2
Posterior Probability (1/32) / (1/32 + 1/2) = 1/17 (1/2) / (1/32 + 1/2) = 16/17

Example of a Bayesian analysis table for a female individual's risk for a disease based on the knowledge that the disease is present in her siblings but not in her parents or any of her four children. Based solely on the status of the subject's siblings and parents, she is equally likely to be a carrier as to be a non-carrier (this likelihood is denoted by the Prior Hypothesis). However, the probability that the subject's four sons would all be unaffected is 1/16 (12·12·12·12) if she is a carrier, about 1 if she is a non-carrier (this is the Conditional Probability). The Joint Probability reconciles these two predictions by multiplying them together. The last line (the Posterior Probability) is calculated by dividing the Joint Probability for each hypothesis by the sum of both joint probabilities.[30]

Using genetic test results

Parental genetic testing can detect around 90% of known disease alleles in parents that can lead to carrier or affected status in their child. Cystic fibrosis is a heritable disease caused by an autosomal recessive mutation on the CFTR gene,[31] located on the q arm of chromosome 7.[32]

Bayesian analysis of a female patient with a family history of cystic fibrosis (CF), who has tested negative for CF, demonstrating how this method was used to determine her risk of having a child born with CF:

Because the patient is unaffected, she is either homozygous for the wild-type allele, or heterozygous. To establish prior probabilities, a Punnett square is used, based on the knowledge that neither parent was affected by the disease but both could have been carriers:

Mother


Father
W

Homozygous for the wild-
type allele (a non-carrier)

M

Heterozygous
(a CF carrier)

W

Homozygous for the wild-
type allele (a non-carrier)

WW MW
M

Heterozygous (a CF carrier)

MW MM

(affected by cystic fibrosis)

Given that the patient is unaffected, there are only three possibilities. Within these three, there are two scenarios in which the patient carries the mutant allele. Thus the prior probabilities are 23 and 13.

Next, the patient undergoes genetic testing and tests negative for cystic fibrosis. This test has a 90% detection rate, so the conditional probabilities of a negative test are 1/10 and 1.  Finally, the joint and posterior probabilities are calculated as before.

Hypothesis Hypothesis 1: Patient is a carrier Hypothesis 2: Patient is not a carrier
Prior Probability 2/3 1/3
Conditional Probability of a negative test 1/10 1
Joint Probability 1/15 1/3
Posterior Probability 1/6 5/6

After carrying out the same analysis on the patient's male partner (with a negative test result), the chances of their child being affected is equal to the product of the parents' respective posterior probabilities for being carriers times the chances that two carriers will produce an affected offspring (14).

Genetic testing done in parallel with other risk factor identification

Bayesian analysis can be done using phenotypic information associated with a genetic condition, and when combined with genetic testing this analysis becomes much more complicated. Cystic fibrosis, for example, can be identified in a fetus through an ultrasound looking for an echogenic bowel, meaning one that appears brighter than normal on a scan. This is not a foolproof test, as an echogenic bowel can be present in a perfectly healthy fetus. Parental genetic testing is very influential in this case, where a phenotypic facet can be overly influential in probability calculation. In the case of a fetus with an echogenic bowel, with a mother who has been tested and is known to be a CF carrier, the posterior probability that the fetus actually has the disease is very high (0.64). However, once the father has tested negative for CF, the posterior probability drops significantly (to 0.16).[30]

Risk factor calculation is a powerful tool in genetic counseling and reproductive planning, but it cannot be treated as the only important factor to consider. As above, incomplete testing can yield falsely high probability of carrier status, and testing can be financially inaccessible or unfeasible when a parent is not present.

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Laplace refined Bayes's theorem over a period of decades:
    • Laplace announced his independent discovery of Bayes' theorem in: Laplace (1774) "Mémoire sur la probabilité des causes par les événements," "Mémoires de l'Académie royale des Sciences de MI (Savants étrangers)," 4: 621–656. Reprinted in: Laplace, "Oeuvres complètes" (Paris, France: Gauthier-Villars et fils, 1841), vol. 8, pp. 27–65. Available on-line at: Gallica. Bayes' theorem appears on p. 29.
    • Laplace presented a refinement of Bayes' theorem in: Laplace (read: 1783 / published: 1785) "Mémoire sur les approximations des formules qui sont fonctions de très grands nombres," "Mémoires de l'Académie royale des Sciences de Paris," 423–467. Reprinted in: Laplace, "Oeuvres complètes" (Paris, France: Gauthier-Villars et fils, 1844), vol. 10, pp. 295–338. Available on-line at: Gallica. Bayes' theorem is stated on page 301.
    • See also: Laplace, "Essai philosophique sur les probabilités" (Paris, France: Mme. Ve. Courcier [Madame veuve (i.e., widow) Courcier], 1814), page 10. English translation: Pierre Simon, Marquis de Laplace with F. W. Truscott and F. L. Emory, trans., "A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities" (New York, New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1902), p. 15.

References

  1. ^ "Bayes' Theorem". Merriam-Webster Dictionary.
  2. ^ "Bayes' Theorem". CollinsDictionary.com. HarperCollins. Retrieved 2023-08-12.
  3. ^ Joyce, James (2003), "Bayes' Theorem", in Zalta, Edward N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2019 ed.), Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University, retrieved 2020-01-17
  4. ^ Jeffreys, Sir Harold (1973). Scientific Inference. Cambridge: At the University Press. OCLC 764571529.
  5. ^ Frame, Paul (2015). Liberty's Apostle. Wales: University of Wales Press. p. 44. ISBN 978-1783162161. Retrieved 23 February 2021.
  6. ^ Allen, Richard (1999). David Hartley on Human Nature. SUNY Press. pp. 243–244. ISBN 978-0791494516. Retrieved 16 June 2013.
  7. ^ Bayes, Thomas & Price, Richard (1763). "An Essay towards solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chance. By the late Rev. Mr. Bayes, communicated by Mr. Price, in a letter to John Canton, A.M.F.R.S." Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London. 53: 370–418. doi:10.1098/rstl.1763.0053.
  8. ^ Holland, pp. 46–7.
  9. ^ Price, Richard (1991). Price: Political Writings. Cambridge University Press. p. xxiii. ISBN 978-0521409698. Retrieved 16 June 2013.
  10. ^ Mitchell 1911, p. 314.
  11. ^ Daston, Lorraine (1988). Classical Probability in the Enlightenment. Princeton Univ Press. p. 268. ISBN 0691084971.
  12. ^ Stigler, Stephen M. (1986). "Inverse Probability". The History of Statistics: The Measurement of Uncertainty Before 1900. Harvard University Press. pp. 99–138. ISBN 978-0674403413.
  13. ^ Jeffreys, Harold (1973). Scientific Inference (3rd ed.). Cambridge University Press. p. 31. ISBN 978-0521180788.
  14. ^ Stigler, Stephen M. (1983). "Who Discovered Bayes' Theorem?". The American Statistician. 37 (4): 290–296. doi:10.1080/00031305.1983.10483122.
  15. ^ de Vaux, Richard; Velleman, Paul; Bock, David (2016). Stats, Data and Models (4th ed.). Pearson. pp. 380–381. ISBN 978-0321986498.
  16. ^ Edwards, A. W. F. (1986). "Is the Reference in Hartley (1749) to Bayesian Inference?". The American Statistician. 40 (2): 109–110. doi:10.1080/00031305.1986.10475370.
  17. ^ Hooper, Martyn (2013). "Richard Price, Bayes' theorem, and God". Significance. 10 (1): 36–39. doi:10.1111/j.1740-9713.2013.00638.x. S2CID 153704746.
  18. ^ a b McGrayne, S. B. (2011). The Theory That Would Not Die: How Bayes' Rule Cracked the Enigma Code, Hunted Down Russian Submarines & Emerged Triumphant from Two Centuries of Controversy. Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0300188226.
  19. ^ Stuart, A.; Ord, K. (1994), Kendall's Advanced Theory of Statistics: Volume I – Distribution Theory, Edward Arnold, §8.7
  20. ^ Kolmogorov, A.N. (1933) [1956]. Foundations of the Theory of Probability. Chelsea Publishing Company.
  21. ^ Taraldsen, Gunnar; Tufto, Jarle; Lindqvist, Bo H. (2021-07-24). "Improper priors and improper posteriors". Scandinavian Journal of Statistics. 49 (3): 969–991. doi:10.1111/sjos.12550. ISSN 0303-6898. S2CID 237736986.
  22. ^ Robert, Christian P.; Casella, George (2004). Monte Carlo Statistical Methods. Springer. ISBN 978-1475741452. OCLC 1159112760.
  23. ^ Lee, Peter M. (2012). "Chapter 1". Bayesian Statistics. Wiley. ISBN 978-1-1183-3257-3.
  24. ^ . Trinity University. Archived from the original on 21 August 2004. Retrieved 5 August 2014.
  25. ^ Audun Jøsang, 2016, Subjective Logic; A formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty. Springer, Cham, ISBN 978-3-319-42337-1
  26. ^ Audun Jøsang, 2016, Generalising Bayes' Theorem in Subjective Logic. IEEE International Conference on Multisensor Fusion and Integration for Intelligent Systems (MFI 2016), Baden-Baden, September 2016
  27. ^ Koller, D.; Friedman, N. (2009). . Massachusetts: MIT Press. p. 1208. ISBN 978-0-262-01319-2. Archived from the original on 2014-04-27.
  28. ^ Graham Kemp (https://math.stackexchange.com/users/135106/graham-kemp), Bayes' rule with 3 variables, URL (version: 2015-05-14): https://math.stackexchange.com/q/1281558
  29. ^ Kraft, Stephanie A; Duenas, Devan; Wilfond, Benjamin S; Goddard, Katrina AB (24 September 2018). "The evolving landscape of expanded carrier screening: challenges and opportunities". Genetics in Medicine. 21 (4): 790–797. doi:10.1038/s41436-018-0273-4. PMC 6752283. PMID 30245516.
  30. ^ a b Ogino, Shuji; Wilson, Robert B; Gold, Bert; Hawley, Pamela; Grody, Wayne W (October 2004). "Bayesian analysis for cystic fibrosis risks in prenatal and carrier screening". Genetics in Medicine. 6 (5): 439–449. doi:10.1097/01.GIM.0000139511.83336.8F. PMID 15371910.
  31. ^ "Types of CFTR Mutations". Cystic Fibrosis Foundation, www.cff.org/What-is-CF/Genetics/Types-of-CFTR-Mutations/.
  32. ^ "CFTR Gene – Genetics Home Reference". U.S. National Library of Medicine, National Institutes of Health, ghr.nlm.nih.gov/gene/CFTR#location.

Bibliography

Further reading

  • Grunau, Hans-Christoph (24 January 2014). "Preface Issue 3/4-2013". Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung. 115 (3–4): 127–128. doi:10.1365/s13291-013-0077-z.
  • Gelman, A, Carlin, JB, Stern, HS, and Rubin, DB (2003), "Bayesian Data Analysis", Second Edition, CRC Press.
  • Grinstead, CM and Snell, JL (1997), "Introduction to Probability (2nd edition)," American Mathematical Society (free pdf available) [1].
  • "Bayes formula", Encyclopedia of Mathematics, EMS Press, 2001 [1994]
  • McGrayne, SB (2011). The Theory That Would Not Die: How Bayes' Rule Cracked the Enigma Code, Hunted Down Russian Submarines & Emerged Triumphant from Two Centuries of Controversy. Yale University Press. ISBN 978-0-300-18822-6.
  • Laplace, Pierre Simon (1986). "Memoir on the Probability of the Causes of Events". Statistical Science. 1 (3): 364–378. doi:10.1214/ss/1177013621. JSTOR 2245476.
  • Lee, Peter M (2012), Bayesian Statistics: An Introduction, 4th edition. Wiley. ISBN 978-1-118-33257-3.
  • Puga JL, Krzywinski M, Altman N (31 March 2015). "Bayes' theorem". Nature Methods. 12 (4): 277–278. doi:10.1038/nmeth.3335. PMID 26005726.
  • Rosenthal, Jeffrey S (2005), "Struck by Lightning: The Curious World of Probabilities". HarperCollins. (Granta, 2008. ISBN 9781862079960).
  • Stigler, Stephen M. (August 1986). "Laplace's 1774 Memoir on Inverse Probability". Statistical Science. 1 (3): 359–363. doi:10.1214/ss/1177013620.
  • Stone, JV (2013), download chapter 1 of "Bayes' Rule: A Tutorial Introduction to Bayesian Analysis", Sebtel Press, England.
  • Bayesian Reasoning for Intelligent People, An introduction and tutorial to the use of Bayes' theorem in statistics and cognitive science.
  • Morris, Dan (2016), Read first 6 chapters for free of "" Blue Windmill ISBN 978-1549761744. A short tutorial on how to understand problem scenarios and find P(B), P(A), and P(B|A).

External links

  • Visual explanation of Bayes using trees on YouTube
  • Bayes' frequentist interpretation explained visually on YouTube
  • Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics (B). Contains origins of "Bayesian", "Bayes' Theorem", "Bayes Estimate/Risk/Solution", "Empirical Bayes", and "Bayes Factor".
  • A tutorial on probability and Bayes' theorem devised for Oxford University psychology students
  • An Intuitive Explanation of Bayes' Theorem by Eliezer S. Yudkowsky
  • Bayesian Clinical Diagnostic Model

bayes, theorem, bayes, rule, redirects, here, concept, decision, theory, bayes, estimator, probability, theory, statistics, bayz, alternatively, bayes, bayes, rule, named, after, thomas, bayes, describes, probability, event, based, prior, knowledge, conditions. Bayes rule redirects here For the concept in decision theory see Bayes estimator In probability theory and statistics Bayes theorem b eɪ z BAYZ or b eɪ z ɪ z BAY ziz alternatively Bayes law or Bayes rule 1 2 named after Thomas Bayes describes the probability of an event based on prior knowledge of conditions that might be related to the event 3 For example if the risk of developing health problems is known to increase with age Bayes theorem allows the risk to an individual of a known age to be assessed more accurately by conditioning it relative to their age rather than simply assuming that the individual is typical of the population as a whole One of the many applications of Bayes theorem is Bayesian inference a particular approach to statistical inference When applied the probabilities involved in the theorem may have different probability interpretations With Bayesian probability interpretation the theorem expresses how a degree of belief expressed as a probability should rationally change to account for the availability of related evidence Bayesian inference is fundamental to Bayesian statistics being considered by one authority as to the theory of probability what Pythagoras s theorem is to geometry 4 Contents 1 History 2 Statement of theorem 2 1 Proof 2 1 1 For events 2 1 2 For continuous random variables 2 1 3 General case 3 Examples 3 1 Recreational mathematics 3 2 Drug testing 3 2 1 Sensitivity or specificity 3 3 Cancer rate 3 4 Defective item rate 4 Interpretations 4 1 Bayesian interpretation 4 2 Frequentist interpretation 4 2 1 Example 5 Forms 5 1 Events 5 1 1 Simple form 5 1 2 Alternative form 5 1 3 Extended form 5 2 Random variables 5 2 1 Simple form 5 2 2 Extended form 5 3 Bayes rule in odds form 6 Correspondence to other mathematical frameworks 6 1 Propositional logic 6 2 Subjective logic 7 Generalizations 7 1 Conditioned version 7 1 1 Derivation 7 2 Bayes rule with 3 events 8 Use in genetics 8 1 Using pedigree to calculate probabilities 8 2 Using genetic test results 8 3 Genetic testing done in parallel with other risk factor identification 9 See also 10 Notes 11 References 12 Bibliography 13 Further reading 14 External linksHistory EditBayes theorem is named after the Reverend Thomas Bayes b eɪ z also a statistician and philosopher Bayes used conditional probability to provide an algorithm his Proposition 9 that uses evidence to calculate limits on an unknown parameter His work was published in 1763 as An Essay towards solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances Bayes studied how to compute a distribution for the probability parameter of a binomial distribution in modern terminology On Bayes s death his family transferred his papers to a friend the minister philosopher and mathematician Richard Price Over two years Richard Price significantly edited the unpublished manuscript before sending it to a friend who read it aloud at the Royal Society on 23 December 1763 5 Price edited 6 Bayes s major work An Essay towards solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chances 1763 which appeared in Philosophical Transactions 7 and contains Bayes theorem Price wrote an introduction to the paper which provides some of the philosophical basis of Bayesian statistics and chose one of the two solutions offered by Bayes In 1765 Price was elected a Fellow of the Royal Society in recognition of his work on the legacy of Bayes 8 9 On 27 April a letter sent to his friend Benjamin Franklin was read out at the Royal Society and later published where Price applies this work to population and computing life annuities 10 Independently of Bayes Pierre Simon Laplace in 1774 and later in his 1812 Theorie analytique des probabilites used conditional probability to formulate the relation of an updated posterior probability from a prior probability given evidence He reproduced and extended Bayes s results in 1774 apparently unaware of Bayes s work note 1 11 The Bayesian interpretation of probability was developed mainly by Laplace 12 About 200 years later Sir Harold Jeffreys put Bayes s algorithm and Laplace s formulation on an axiomatic basis writing in a 1973 book that Bayes theorem is to the theory of probability what the Pythagorean theorem is to geometry 13 Stephen Stigler used a Bayesian argument to conclude that Bayes theorem was discovered by Nicholas Saunderson a blind English mathematician some time before Bayes 14 15 that interpretation however has been disputed 16 Martyn Hooper 17 and Sharon McGrayne 18 have argued that Richard Price s contribution was substantial By modern standards we should refer to the Bayes Price rule Price discovered Bayes s work recognized its importance corrected it contributed to the article and found a use for it The modern convention of employing Bayes s name alone is unfair but so entrenched that anything else makes little sense 18 Statement of theorem EditBayes theorem is stated mathematically as the following equation 19 P A B P B A P A P B displaystyle P A vert B frac P B vert A P A P B where A displaystyle A and B displaystyle B are events and P B 0 displaystyle P B neq 0 P A B displaystyle P A vert B is a conditional probability the probability of event A displaystyle A occurring given that B displaystyle B is true It is also called the posterior probability of A displaystyle A given B displaystyle B P B A displaystyle P B vert A is also a conditional probability the probability of event B displaystyle B occurring given that A displaystyle A is true It can also be interpreted as the likelihood of A displaystyle A given a fixed B displaystyle B because P B A L A B displaystyle P B vert A L A vert B P A displaystyle P A and P B displaystyle P B are the probabilities of observing A displaystyle A and B displaystyle B respectively without any given conditions they are known as the prior probability and marginal probability Proof Edit For events Edit Bayes theorem may be derived from the definition of conditional probability P A B P A B P B if P B 0 displaystyle P A vert B frac P A cap B P B text if P B neq 0 where P A B displaystyle P A cap B is the probability of both A and B being true Similarly P B A P A B P A if P A 0 displaystyle P B vert A frac P A cap B P A text if P A neq 0 Solving for P A B displaystyle P A cap B and substituting into the above expression for P A B displaystyle P A vert B yields Bayes theorem P A B P B A P A P B if P B 0 displaystyle P A vert B frac P B vert A P A P B text if P B neq 0 For continuous random variables Edit For two continuous random variables X and Y Bayes theorem may be analogously derived from the definition of conditional density f X Y y x f X Y x y f Y y displaystyle f X vert Y y x frac f X Y x y f Y y f Y X x y f X Y x y f X x displaystyle f Y vert X x y frac f X Y x y f X x Therefore f X Y y x f Y X x y f X x f Y y displaystyle f X vert Y y x frac f Y vert X x y f X x f Y y General case Edit Let P Y x displaystyle P Y x be the conditional distribution of Y displaystyle Y given X x displaystyle X x and let P X displaystyle P X be the distribution of X displaystyle X The joint distribution is then P X Y d x d y P Y x d y P X d x displaystyle P X Y dx dy P Y x dy P X dx The conditional distribution P X y displaystyle P X y of X displaystyle X given Y y displaystyle Y y is then determined byP X y A E 1 A X Y y displaystyle P X y A E 1 A X Y y Existence and uniqueness of the needed conditional expectation is a consequence of the Radon Nikodym theorem This was formulated by Kolmogorov in his famous book from 1933 Kolmogorov underlines the importance of conditional probability by writing I wish to call attention to and especially the theory of conditional probabilities and conditional expectations in the Preface 20 The Bayes theorem determines the posterior distribution from the prior distribution Bayes theorem can be generalized to include improper prior distributions such as the uniform distribution on the real line 21 Modern Markov chain Monte Carlo methods have boosted the importance of Bayes theorem including cases with improper priors 22 Examples EditRecreational mathematics Edit Bayes rule and computing conditional probabilities provide a solution method for a number of popular puzzles such as the Three Prisoners problem the Monty Hall problem the Two Child problem and the Two Envelopes problem Drug testing Edit Figure 1 Using a frequency box to show P User Positive displaystyle P text User vert text Positive visually by comparison of shaded areasSuppose a particular test for whether someone has been using cannabis is 90 sensitive meaning the true positive rate TPR 0 90 Therefore it leads to 90 true positive results correct identification of drug use for cannabis users The test is also 80 specific meaning true negative rate TNR 0 80 Therefore the test correctly identifies 80 of non use for non users but also generates 20 false positives or false positive rate FPR 0 20 for non users Assuming 0 05 prevalence meaning 5 of people use cannabis what is the probability that a random person who tests positive is really a cannabis user The Positive predictive value PPV of a test is the proportion of persons who are actually positive out of all those testing positive and can be calculated from a sample as PPV True positive Tested positiveIf sensitivity specificity and prevalence are known PPV can be calculated using Bayes theorem Let P User Positive displaystyle P text User vert text Positive mean the probability that someone is a cannabis user given that they test positive which is what is meant by PPV We can write P User Positive P Positive User P User P Positive P Positive User P User P Positive User P User P Positive Non user P Non user 0 90 0 05 0 90 0 05 0 20 0 95 0 045 0 045 0 19 19 displaystyle begin aligned P text User vert text Positive amp frac P text Positive vert text User P text User P text Positive amp frac P text Positive vert text User P text User P text Positive vert text User P text User P text Positive vert text Non user P text Non user 8pt amp frac 0 90 times 0 05 0 90 times 0 05 0 20 times 0 95 frac 0 045 0 045 0 19 approx 19 end aligned The fact that P Positive P Positive User P User P Positive Non user P Non user displaystyle P text Positive P text Positive vert text User P text User P text Positive vert text Non user P text Non user is a direct application of the Law of Total Probability In this case it says that the probability that someone tests positive is the probability that a user tests positive times the probability of being a user plus the probability that a non user tests positive times the probability of being a non user This is true because the classifications user and non user form a partition of a set namely the set of people who take the drug test This combined with the definition of conditional probability results in the above statement In other words even if someone tests positive the probability that they are a cannabis user is only 19 this is because in this group only 5 of people are users and most positives are false positives coming from the remaining 95 If 1 000 people were tested 950 are non users and 190 of them give false positive 0 20 950 50 of them are users and 45 of them give true positive 0 90 50 The 1 000 people thus yields 235 positive tests of which only 45 are genuine drug users about 19 See Figure 1 for an illustration using a frequency box and note how small the pink area of true positives is compared to the blue area of false positives Sensitivity or specificity Edit The importance of specificity can be seen by showing that even if sensitivity is raised to 100 and specificity remains at 80 the probability of someone testing positive really being a cannabis user only rises from 19 to 21 but if the sensitivity is held at 90 and the specificity is increased to 95 the probability rises to 49 TestActual Positive Negative TotalUser 45 5 50Non user 190 760 950Total 235 765 100090 sensitive 80 specific PPV 45 235 19 TestActual Positive Negative TotalUser 50 0 50Non user 190 760 950Total 240 760 1000100 sensitive 80 specific PPV 50 240 21 TestActual Positive Negative TotalUser 45 5 50Non user 47 903 950Total 92 908 100090 sensitive 95 specific PPV 45 92 49 Cancer rate Edit Even if 100 of patients with pancreatic cancer have a certain symptom when someone has the same symptom it does not mean that this person has a 100 chance of getting pancreatic cancer Assuming the incidence rate of pancreatic cancer is 1 100000 while 10 99999 healthy individuals have the same symptoms worldwide the probability of having pancreatic cancer given the symptoms is only 9 1 and the other 90 9 could be false positives that is falsely said to have cancer positive is a confusing term when as here the test gives bad news Based on incidence rate the following table presents the corresponding numbers per 100 000 people SymptomCancer Yes No TotalYes 1 0 1No 10 99989 99999Total 11 99989 100000Which can then be used to calculate the probability of having cancer when you have the symptoms P Cancer Symptoms P Symptoms Cancer P Cancer P Symptoms P Symptoms Cancer P Cancer P Symptoms Cancer P Cancer P Symptoms Non Cancer P Non Cancer 1 0 00001 1 0 00001 10 99999 0 99999 1 11 9 1 displaystyle begin aligned P text Cancer text Symptoms amp frac P text Symptoms text Cancer P text Cancer P text Symptoms amp frac P text Symptoms text Cancer P text Cancer P text Symptoms text Cancer P text Cancer P text Symptoms text Non Cancer P text Non Cancer 8pt amp frac 1 times 0 00001 1 times 0 00001 10 99999 times 0 99999 frac 1 11 approx 9 1 end aligned Defective item rate Edit ConditionMachine Defective Flawless TotalA 10 190 200B 9 291 300C 5 495 500Total 24 976 1000A factory produces items using three machines A B and C which account for 20 30 and 50 of its output respectively Of the items produced by machine A 5 are defective similarly 3 of machine B s items and 1 of machine C s are defective If a randomly selected item is defective what is the probability it was produced by machine C Once again the answer can be reached without using the formula by applying the conditions to a hypothetical number of cases For example if the factory produces 1 000 items 200 will be produced by Machine A 300 by Machine B and 500 by Machine C Machine A will produce 5 200 10 defective items Machine B 3 300 9 and Machine C 1 500 5 for a total of 24 Thus the likelihood that a randomly selected defective item was produced by machine C is 5 24 20 83 This problem can also be solved using Bayes theorem Let Xi denote the event that a randomly chosen item was made by the i th machine for i A B C Let Y denote the event that a randomly chosen item is defective Then we are given the following information P X A 0 2 P X B 0 3 P X C 0 5 displaystyle P X A 0 2 quad P X B 0 3 quad P X C 0 5 If the item was made by the first machine then the probability that it is defective is 0 05 that is P Y XA 0 05 Overall we have P Y X A 0 05 P Y X B 0 03 P Y X C 0 01 displaystyle P Y X A 0 05 quad P Y X B 0 03 quad P Y X C 0 01 To answer the original question we first find P Y That can be done in the following way P Y i P Y X i P X i 0 05 0 2 0 03 0 3 0 01 0 5 0 024 displaystyle P Y sum i P Y X i P X i 0 05 0 2 0 03 0 3 0 01 0 5 0 024 Hence 2 4 of the total output is defective We are given that Y has occurred and we want to calculate the conditional probability of XC By Bayes theorem P X C Y P Y X C P X C P Y 0 01 0 50 0 024 5 24 displaystyle P X C Y frac P Y X C P X C P Y frac 0 01 cdot 0 50 0 024 frac 5 24 Given that the item is defective the probability that it was made by machine C is 5 24 Although machine C produces half of the total output it produces a much smaller fraction of the defective items Hence the knowledge that the item selected was defective enables us to replace the prior probability P XC 1 2 by the smaller posterior probability P XC Y 5 24 Interpretations Edit Figure 2 A geometric visualisation of Bayes theoremThe interpretation of Bayes rule depends on the interpretation of probability ascribed to the terms The two predominant interpretations are described below Figure 2 shows a geometric visualization Bayesian interpretation Edit In the Bayesian or epistemological interpretation probability measures a degree of belief Bayes theorem links the degree of belief in a proposition before and after accounting for evidence For example suppose it is believed with 50 certainty that a coin is twice as likely to land heads than tails If the coin is flipped a number of times and the outcomes observed that degree of belief will probably rise or fall but might even remain the same depending on the results For proposition A and evidence B P A the prior is the initial degree of belief in A P A B the posterior is the degree of belief after incorporating news that B is true the quotient P B A P B represents the support B provides for A For more on the application of Bayes theorem under the Bayesian interpretation of probability see Bayesian inference Frequentist interpretation Edit Figure 3 Illustration of frequentist interpretation with tree diagramsIn the frequentist interpretation probability measures a proportion of outcomes For example suppose an experiment is performed many times P A is the proportion of outcomes with property A the prior and P B is the proportion with property B P B A is the proportion of outcomes with property B out of outcomes with property A and P A B is the proportion of those with A out of those with B the posterior The role of Bayes theorem is best visualized with tree diagrams such as Figure 3 The two diagrams partition the same outcomes by A and B in opposite orders to obtain the inverse probabilities Bayes theorem links the different partitionings Example Edit Figure 4 Tree diagram illustrating the beetle example R C P and P displaystyle overline P are the events rare common pattern and no pattern Percentages in parentheses are calculated Three independent values are given so it is possible to calculate the inverse tree An entomologist spots what might due to the pattern on its back be a rare subspecies of beetle A full 98 of the members of the rare subspecies have the pattern so P Pattern Rare 98 Only 5 of members of the common subspecies have the pattern The rare subspecies is 0 1 of the total population How likely is the beetle having the pattern to be rare what is P Rare Pattern From the extended form of Bayes theorem since any beetle is either rare or common P Rare Pattern P Pattern Rare P Rare P Pattern P Pattern Rare P Rare P Pattern Rare P Rare P Pattern Common P Common 0 98 0 001 0 98 0 001 0 05 0 999 1 9 displaystyle begin aligned P text Rare vert text Pattern amp frac P text Pattern vert text Rare P text Rare P text Pattern 8pt amp frac P text Pattern vert text Rare P text Rare P text Pattern vert text Rare P text Rare P text Pattern vert text Common P text Common 8pt amp frac 0 98 times 0 001 0 98 times 0 001 0 05 times 0 999 8pt amp approx 1 9 end aligned Forms EditEvents Edit Simple form Edit For events A and B provided that P B 0 P A B P B A P A P B displaystyle P A B frac P B A P A P B In many applications for instance in Bayesian inference the event B is fixed in the discussion and we wish to consider the impact of its having been observed on our belief in various possible events A In such a situation the denominator of the last expression the probability of the given evidence B is fixed what we want to vary is A Bayes theorem then shows that the posterior probabilities are proportional to the numerator so the last equation becomes P A B P A P B A displaystyle P A B propto P A cdot P B A In words the posterior is proportional to the prior times the likelihood 23 If events A1 A2 are mutually exclusive and exhaustive i e one of them is certain to occur but no two can occur together we can determine the proportionality constant by using the fact that their probabilities must add up to one For instance for a given event A the event A itself and its complement A are exclusive and exhaustive Denoting the constant of proportionality by c we have P A B c P A P B A and P A B c P A P B A displaystyle P A B c cdot P A cdot P B A text and P neg A B c cdot P neg A cdot P B neg A Adding these two formulas we deduce that 1 c P B A P A P B A P A displaystyle 1 c cdot P B A cdot P A P B neg A cdot P neg A or c 1 P B A P A P B A P A 1 P B displaystyle c frac 1 P B A cdot P A P B neg A cdot P neg A frac 1 P B Alternative form Edit Contingency table BackgroundProposition B B not B TotalA P B A P A P A B P B P B A P A P A B P B P A A not A P B A P A P A B P B P B A P A P A B P B P A 1 P A Total P B P B 1 P B 1Another form of Bayes theorem for two competing statements or hypotheses is P A B P B A P A P B A P A P B A P A displaystyle P A B frac P B A P A P B A P A P B neg A P neg A For an epistemological interpretation For proposition A and evidence or background B 24 P A displaystyle P A is the prior probability the initial degree of belief in A P A displaystyle P neg A is the corresponding initial degree of belief in not A that A is false where P A 1 P A displaystyle P neg A 1 P A P B A displaystyle P B A is the conditional probability or likelihood the degree of belief in B given that proposition A is true P B A displaystyle P B neg A is the conditional probability or likelihood the degree of belief in B given that proposition A is false P A B displaystyle P A B is the posterior probability the probability of A after taking into account B Extended form Edit Often for some partition Aj of the sample space the event space is given in terms of P Aj and P B Aj It is then useful to compute P B using the law of total probability P B j P B A j P A j displaystyle P B sum j P B A j P A j P A i B P B A i P A i j P B A j P A j displaystyle Rightarrow P A i B frac P B A i P A i sum limits j P B A j P A j cdot In the special case where A is a binary variable P A B P B A P A P B A P A P B A P A displaystyle P A B frac P B A P A P B A P A P B neg A P neg A cdot Random variables Edit Figure 5 Bayes theorem applied to an event space generated by continuous random variables X and Y There exists an instance of Bayes theorem for each point in the domain In practice these instances might be parametrized by writing the specified probability densities as a function of x and y Consider a sample space W generated by two random variables X and Y In principle Bayes theorem applies to the events A X x and B Y y P X x Y y P Y y X x P X x P Y y displaystyle P X x Y y frac P Y y X x P X x P Y y However terms become 0 at points where either variable has finite probability density To remain useful Bayes theorem must be formulated in terms of the relevant densities see Derivation Simple form Edit If X is continuous and Y is discrete f X Y y x P Y y X x f X x P Y y displaystyle f X Y y x frac P Y y X x f X x P Y y where each f displaystyle f is a density function If X is discrete and Y is continuous P X x Y y f Y X x y P X x f Y y displaystyle P X x Y y frac f Y X x y P X x f Y y If both X and Y are continuous f X Y y x f Y X x y f X x f Y y displaystyle f X Y y x frac f Y X x y f X x f Y y Extended form Edit Figure 6 A way to conceptualize event spaces generated by continuous random variables X and YA continuous event space is often conceptualized in terms of the numerator terms It is then useful to eliminate the denominator using the law of total probability For fY y this becomes an integral f Y y f Y X 3 y f X 3 d 3 displaystyle f Y y int infty infty f Y X xi y f X xi d xi Bayes rule in odds form Edit Bayes theorem in odds form is O A 1 A 2 B O A 1 A 2 L A 1 A 2 B displaystyle O A 1 A 2 vert B O A 1 A 2 cdot Lambda A 1 A 2 vert B where L A 1 A 2 B P B A 1 P B A 2 displaystyle Lambda A 1 A 2 vert B frac P B vert A 1 P B vert A 2 is called the Bayes factor or likelihood ratio The odds between two events is simply the ratio of the probabilities of the two events Thus O A 1 A 2 P A 1 P A 2 displaystyle O A 1 A 2 frac P A 1 P A 2 O A 1 A 2 B P A 1 B P A 2 B displaystyle O A 1 A 2 vert B frac P A 1 vert B P A 2 vert B Thus the rule says that the posterior odds are the prior odds times the Bayes factor or in other words the posterior is proportional to the prior times the likelihood In the special case that A 1 A displaystyle A 1 A and A 2 A displaystyle A 2 neg A one writes O A O A A P A 1 P A displaystyle O A O A neg A P A 1 P A and uses a similar abbreviation for the Bayes factor and for the conditional odds The odds on A displaystyle A is by definition the odds for and against A displaystyle A Bayes rule can then be written in the abbreviated form O A B O A L A B displaystyle O A vert B O A cdot Lambda A vert B or in words the posterior odds on A displaystyle A equals the prior odds on A displaystyle A times the likelihood ratio for A displaystyle A given information B displaystyle B In short posterior odds equals prior odds times likelihood ratio For example if a medical test has a sensitivity of 90 and a specificity of 91 then the positive Bayes factor is L P True Positive P False Positive 90 100 91 10 displaystyle Lambda P text True Positive P text False Positive 90 100 91 10 Now if the prevalence of this disease is 9 09 and if we take that as the prior probability then the prior odds is about 1 10 So after receiving a positive test result the posterior odds of actually having the disease becomes 1 1 which means that the posterior probability of having the disease is 50 If a second test is performed in serial testing and that also turns out to be positive then the posterior odds of actually having the disease becomes 10 1 which means a posterior probability of about 90 91 The negative Bayes factor can be calculated to be 91 100 90 9 1 so if the second test turns out to be negative then the posterior odds of actually having the disease is 1 9 1 which means a posterior probability of about 9 9 The example above can also be understood with more solid numbers Assume the patient taking the test is from a group of 1000 people where 91 of them actually have the disease prevalence of 9 1 If all these 1000 people take the medical test 82 of those with the disease will get a true positive result sensitivity of 90 1 9 of those with the disease will get a false negative result false negative rate of 9 9 827 of those without the disease will get a true negative result specificity of 91 0 and 82 of those without the disease will get a false positive result false positive rate of 9 0 Before taking any test the patient s odds for having the disease is 91 909 After receiving a positive result the patient s odds for having the disease is 91 909 90 1 9 0 91 90 1 909 9 0 1 1 displaystyle frac 91 909 times frac 90 1 9 0 frac 91 times 90 1 909 times 9 0 1 1 which is consistent with the fact that there are 82 true positives and 82 false positives in the group of 1000 people Correspondence to other mathematical frameworks EditPropositional logic Edit Using P B A 1 P B A displaystyle P neg B vert A 1 P B vert A twice one may use Bayes theorem to also express P B A displaystyle P neg B vert neg A in terms of P A B displaystyle P A vert B and without negations P B A 1 1 P A B P B P A displaystyle P neg B vert neg A 1 left 1 P A vert B right frac P B P neg A when P A 1 P A 0 displaystyle P neg A 1 P A neq 0 From this we can read off the inference P A B 1 P B A 1 displaystyle P A vert B 1 implies P neg B vert neg A 1 In words If certainly B displaystyle B implies A displaystyle A we infer that certainly A displaystyle neg A implies B displaystyle neg B Where P B 0 displaystyle P B neq 0 the two implications being certain are equivalent statements In the probability formulas the conditional probability P A B displaystyle P A vert B generalizes the logical implication B A displaystyle B implies A where now beyond assigning true or false we assign probability values to statements The assertion of B A displaystyle B implies A is captured by certainty of the conditional the assertion of P A B 1 displaystyle P A vert B 1 Relating the directions of implication Bayes theorem represents a generalization of the contraposition law which in classical propositional logic can be expressed as B A A B displaystyle B implies A iff neg A implies neg B In this relation between implications the positions of A displaystyle A resp B displaystyle B get flipped The corresponding formula in terms of probability calculus is Bayes theorem which in its expanded form involving the prior probability base rate a displaystyle a of only A displaystyle A is expressed as 25 P A B P B A a A P B A a A P B A a A displaystyle P A vert B P B vert A frac a A P B vert A a A P B vert neg A a neg A Subjective logic Edit Bayes theorem represents a special case of deriving inverted conditional opinions in subjective logic expressed as w A B S w A B S w B A S w B A S ϕ a A displaystyle omega A tilde B S omega A tilde lnot B S omega B vert A S omega B vert lnot A S widetilde phi a A where ϕ displaystyle widetilde phi denotes the operator for inverting conditional opinions The argument w B A S w B A S displaystyle omega B vert A S omega B vert lnot A S denotes a pair of binomial conditional opinions given by source S displaystyle S and the argument a A displaystyle a A denotes the prior probability aka the base rate of A displaystyle A The pair of derivative inverted conditional opinions is denoted w A B S w A B S displaystyle omega A tilde B S omega A tilde lnot B S The conditional opinion w A B S displaystyle omega A vert B S generalizes the probabilistic conditional P A B displaystyle P A vert B i e in addition to assigning a probability the source S displaystyle S can assign any subjective opinion to the conditional statement A B displaystyle A vert B A binomial subjective opinion w A S displaystyle omega A S is the belief in the truth of statement A displaystyle A with degrees of epistemic uncertainty as expressed by source S displaystyle S Every subjective opinion has a corresponding projected probability P w A S displaystyle P omega A S The application of Bayes theorem to projected probabilities of opinions is a homomorphism meaning that Bayes theorem can be expressed in terms of projected probabilities of opinions P w A B S P w B A S a A P w B A S a A P w B A S a A displaystyle P omega A tilde B S frac P omega B vert A S a A P omega B vert A S a A P omega B vert lnot A S a lnot A Hence the subjective Bayes theorem represents a generalization of Bayes theorem 26 Generalizations EditConditioned version Edit A conditioned version of the Bayes theorem 27 results from the addition of a third event C displaystyle C on which all probabilities are conditioned P A B C P B A C P A C P B C displaystyle P A vert B cap C frac P B vert A cap C P A vert C P B vert C Derivation Edit Using the chain rule P A B C P A B C P B C P C displaystyle P A cap B cap C P A vert B cap C P B vert C P C And on the other hand P A B C P B A C P B A C P A C P C displaystyle P A cap B cap C P B cap A cap C P B vert A cap C P A vert C P C The desired result is obtained by identifying both expressions and solving for P A B C displaystyle P A vert B cap C Bayes rule with 3 events Edit In the case of 3 events A B and C it can be shown that P A B C P B A C P A C P B C displaystyle P A vert B C frac P B vert A C P A vert C P B vert C Proof 28 P A B C P A B C P B C P B A C P A C P B C P B A C P A C P C P B C P B A C P A C P C P B C P C P B A C P A C P B C displaystyle begin aligned P A vert B C amp frac P A B C P B C 1ex amp frac P B vert A C P A C P B C 1ex amp frac P B vert A C P A vert C P C P B C 1ex amp frac P B vert A C P A vert C P C P B vert C P C 1ex amp frac P B vert A C P A vert C P B vert C end aligned Use in genetics EditIn genetics Bayes theorem can be used to calculate the probability of an individual having a specific genotype Many people seek to approximate their chances of being affected by a genetic disease or their likelihood of being a carrier for a recessive gene of interest A Bayesian analysis can be done based on family history or genetic testing in order to predict whether an individual will develop a disease or pass one on to their children Genetic testing and prediction is a common practice among couples who plan to have children but are concerned that they may both be carriers for a disease especially within communities with low genetic variance 29 The first step in Bayesian analysis for genetics is to propose mutually exclusive hypotheses for a specific allele an individual either is or is not a carrier Next four probabilities are calculated Prior Probability the likelihood of each hypothesis considering information such as family history or predictions based on Mendelian Inheritance Conditional Probability of a certain outcome Joint Probability product of the first two and Posterior Probability a weighted product calculated by dividing the Joint Probability for each hypothesis by the sum of both joint probabilities This type of analysis can be done based purely on family history of a condition or in concert with genetic testing citation needed Using pedigree to calculate probabilities Edit Hypothesis Hypothesis 1 Patient is a carrier Hypothesis 2 Patient is not a carrierPrior Probability 1 2 1 2Conditional Probability that all four offspring will be unaffected 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 16 About 1Joint Probability 1 2 1 16 1 32 1 2 1 1 2Posterior Probability 1 32 1 32 1 2 1 17 1 2 1 32 1 2 16 17Example of a Bayesian analysis table for a female individual s risk for a disease based on the knowledge that the disease is present in her siblings but not in her parents or any of her four children Based solely on the status of the subject s siblings and parents she is equally likely to be a carrier as to be a non carrier this likelihood is denoted by the Prior Hypothesis However the probability that the subject s four sons would all be unaffected is 1 16 1 2 1 2 1 2 1 2 if she is a carrier about 1 if she is a non carrier this is the Conditional Probability The Joint Probability reconciles these two predictions by multiplying them together The last line the Posterior Probability is calculated by dividing the Joint Probability for each hypothesis by the sum of both joint probabilities 30 Using genetic test results Edit Parental genetic testing can detect around 90 of known disease alleles in parents that can lead to carrier or affected status in their child Cystic fibrosis is a heritable disease caused by an autosomal recessive mutation on the CFTR gene 31 located on the q arm of chromosome 7 32 Bayesian analysis of a female patient with a family history of cystic fibrosis CF who has tested negative for CF demonstrating how this method was used to determine her risk of having a child born with CF Because the patient is unaffected she is either homozygous for the wild type allele or heterozygous To establish prior probabilities a Punnett square is used based on the knowledge that neither parent was affected by the disease but both could have been carriers MotherFather W Homozygous for the wild type allele a non carrier M Heterozygous a CF carrier W Homozygous for the wild type allele a non carrier WW MWM Heterozygous a CF carrier MW MM affected by cystic fibrosis Given that the patient is unaffected there are only three possibilities Within these three there are two scenarios in which the patient carries the mutant allele Thus the prior probabilities are 2 3 and 1 3 Next the patient undergoes genetic testing and tests negative for cystic fibrosis This test has a 90 detection rate so the conditional probabilities of a negative test are 1 10 and 1 Finally the joint and posterior probabilities are calculated as before Hypothesis Hypothesis 1 Patient is a carrier Hypothesis 2 Patient is not a carrierPrior Probability 2 3 1 3Conditional Probability of a negative test 1 10 1Joint Probability 1 15 1 3Posterior Probability 1 6 5 6After carrying out the same analysis on the patient s male partner with a negative test result the chances of their child being affected is equal to the product of the parents respective posterior probabilities for being carriers times the chances that two carriers will produce an affected offspring 1 4 Genetic testing done in parallel with other risk factor identification Edit Bayesian analysis can be done using phenotypic information associated with a genetic condition and when combined with genetic testing this analysis becomes much more complicated Cystic fibrosis for example can be identified in a fetus through an ultrasound looking for an echogenic bowel meaning one that appears brighter than normal on a scan This is not a foolproof test as an echogenic bowel can be present in a perfectly healthy fetus Parental genetic testing is very influential in this case where a phenotypic facet can be overly influential in probability calculation In the case of a fetus with an echogenic bowel with a mother who has been tested and is known to be a CF carrier the posterior probability that the fetus actually has the disease is very high 0 64 However once the father has tested negative for CF the posterior probability drops significantly to 0 16 30 Risk factor calculation is a powerful tool in genetic counseling and reproductive planning but it cannot be treated as the only important factor to consider As above incomplete testing can yield falsely high probability of carrier status and testing can be financially inaccessible or unfeasible when a parent is not present See also Edit Mathematics portalBayesian epistemology Inductive probability Quantum Bayesianism Why Most Published Research Findings Are False a 2005 essay in metascience by John IoannidisNotes Edit Laplace refined Bayes s theorem over a period of decades Laplace announced his independent discovery of Bayes theorem in Laplace 1774 Memoire sur la probabilite des causes par les evenements Memoires de l Academie royale des Sciences de MI Savants etrangers 4 621 656 Reprinted in Laplace Oeuvres completes Paris France Gauthier Villars et fils 1841 vol 8 pp 27 65 Available on line at Gallica Bayes theorem appears on p 29 Laplace presented a refinement of Bayes theorem in Laplace read 1783 published 1785 Memoire sur les approximations des formules qui sont fonctions de tres grands nombres Memoires de l Academie royale des Sciences de Paris 423 467 Reprinted in Laplace Oeuvres completes Paris France Gauthier Villars et fils 1844 vol 10 pp 295 338 Available on line at Gallica Bayes theorem is stated on page 301 See also Laplace Essai philosophique sur les probabilites Paris France Mme Ve Courcier Madame veuve i e widow Courcier 1814 page 10 English translation Pierre Simon Marquis de Laplace with F W Truscott and F L Emory trans A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities New York New York John Wiley amp Sons 1902 p 15 References Edit Bayes Theorem Merriam Webster Dictionary Bayes Theorem CollinsDictionary com HarperCollins Retrieved 2023 08 12 Joyce James 2003 Bayes Theorem in Zalta Edward N ed The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Spring 2019 ed Metaphysics Research Lab Stanford University retrieved 2020 01 17 Jeffreys Sir Harold 1973 Scientific Inference Cambridge At the University Press OCLC 764571529 Frame Paul 2015 Liberty s Apostle Wales University of Wales Press p 44 ISBN 978 1783162161 Retrieved 23 February 2021 Allen Richard 1999 David Hartley on Human Nature SUNY Press pp 243 244 ISBN 978 0791494516 Retrieved 16 June 2013 Bayes Thomas amp Price Richard 1763 An Essay towards solving a Problem in the Doctrine of Chance By the late Rev Mr Bayes communicated by Mr Price in a letter to John Canton A M F R S Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society of London 53 370 418 doi 10 1098 rstl 1763 0053 Holland pp 46 7 Price Richard 1991 Price Political Writings Cambridge University Press p xxiii ISBN 978 0521409698 Retrieved 16 June 2013 Mitchell 1911 p 314 Daston Lorraine 1988 Classical Probability in the Enlightenment Princeton Univ Press p 268 ISBN 0691084971 Stigler Stephen M 1986 Inverse Probability The History of Statistics The Measurement of Uncertainty Before 1900 Harvard University Press pp 99 138 ISBN 978 0674403413 Jeffreys Harold 1973 Scientific Inference 3rd ed Cambridge University Press p 31 ISBN 978 0521180788 Stigler Stephen M 1983 Who Discovered Bayes Theorem The American Statistician 37 4 290 296 doi 10 1080 00031305 1983 10483122 de Vaux Richard Velleman Paul Bock David 2016 Stats Data and Models 4th ed Pearson pp 380 381 ISBN 978 0321986498 Edwards A W F 1986 Is the Reference in Hartley 1749 to Bayesian Inference The American Statistician 40 2 109 110 doi 10 1080 00031305 1986 10475370 Hooper Martyn 2013 Richard Price Bayes theorem and God Significance 10 1 36 39 doi 10 1111 j 1740 9713 2013 00638 x S2CID 153704746 a b McGrayne S B 2011 The Theory That Would Not Die How Bayes Rule Cracked the Enigma Code Hunted Down Russian Submarines amp Emerged Triumphant from Two Centuries of Controversy Yale University Press ISBN 978 0300188226 Stuart A Ord K 1994 Kendall s Advanced Theory of Statistics Volume I Distribution Theory Edward Arnold 8 7 Kolmogorov A N 1933 1956 Foundations of the Theory of Probability Chelsea Publishing Company Taraldsen Gunnar Tufto Jarle Lindqvist Bo H 2021 07 24 Improper priors and improper posteriors Scandinavian Journal of Statistics 49 3 969 991 doi 10 1111 sjos 12550 ISSN 0303 6898 S2CID 237736986 Robert Christian P Casella George 2004 Monte Carlo Statistical Methods Springer ISBN 978 1475741452 OCLC 1159112760 Lee Peter M 2012 Chapter 1 Bayesian Statistics Wiley ISBN 978 1 1183 3257 3 Bayes Theorem Introduction Trinity University Archived from the original on 21 August 2004 Retrieved 5 August 2014 Audun Josang 2016 Subjective Logic A formalism for Reasoning Under Uncertainty Springer Cham ISBN 978 3 319 42337 1 Audun Josang 2016 Generalising Bayes Theorem in Subjective Logic IEEE International Conference on Multisensor Fusion and Integration for Intelligent Systems MFI 2016 Baden Baden September 2016 Koller D Friedman N 2009 Probabilistic Graphical Models Massachusetts MIT Press p 1208 ISBN 978 0 262 01319 2 Archived from the original on 2014 04 27 Graham Kemp https math stackexchange com users 135106 graham kemp Bayes rule with 3 variables URL version 2015 05 14 https math stackexchange com q 1281558 Kraft Stephanie A Duenas Devan Wilfond Benjamin S Goddard Katrina AB 24 September 2018 The evolving landscape of expanded carrier screening challenges and opportunities Genetics in Medicine 21 4 790 797 doi 10 1038 s41436 018 0273 4 PMC 6752283 PMID 30245516 a b Ogino Shuji Wilson Robert B Gold Bert Hawley Pamela Grody Wayne W October 2004 Bayesian analysis for cystic fibrosis risks in prenatal and carrier screening Genetics in Medicine 6 5 439 449 doi 10 1097 01 GIM 0000139511 83336 8F PMID 15371910 Types of CFTR Mutations Cystic Fibrosis Foundation www cff org What is CF Genetics Types of CFTR Mutations CFTR Gene Genetics Home Reference U S National Library of Medicine National Institutes of Health ghr nlm nih gov gene CFTR location Bibliography Edit This article incorporates text from a publication now in the public domain Mitchell John Malcolm 1911 Price Richard In Chisholm Hugh ed Encyclopaedia Britannica Vol 22 11th ed Cambridge University Press pp 314 315 Further reading EditGrunau Hans Christoph 24 January 2014 Preface Issue 3 4 2013 Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker Vereinigung 115 3 4 127 128 doi 10 1365 s13291 013 0077 z Gelman A Carlin JB Stern HS and Rubin DB 2003 Bayesian Data Analysis Second Edition CRC Press Grinstead CM and Snell JL 1997 Introduction to Probability 2nd edition American Mathematical Society free pdf available 1 Bayes formula Encyclopedia of Mathematics EMS Press 2001 1994 McGrayne SB 2011 The Theory That Would Not Die How Bayes Rule Cracked the Enigma Code Hunted Down Russian Submarines amp Emerged Triumphant from Two Centuries of Controversy Yale University Press ISBN 978 0 300 18822 6 Laplace Pierre Simon 1986 Memoir on the Probability of the Causes of Events Statistical Science 1 3 364 378 doi 10 1214 ss 1177013621 JSTOR 2245476 Lee Peter M 2012 Bayesian Statistics An Introduction 4th edition Wiley ISBN 978 1 118 33257 3 Puga JL Krzywinski M Altman N 31 March 2015 Bayes theorem Nature Methods 12 4 277 278 doi 10 1038 nmeth 3335 PMID 26005726 Rosenthal Jeffrey S 2005 Struck by Lightning The Curious World of Probabilities HarperCollins Granta 2008 ISBN 9781862079960 Stigler Stephen M August 1986 Laplace s 1774 Memoir on Inverse Probability Statistical Science 1 3 359 363 doi 10 1214 ss 1177013620 Stone JV 2013 download chapter 1 of Bayes Rule A Tutorial Introduction to Bayesian Analysis Sebtel Press England Bayesian Reasoning for Intelligent People An introduction and tutorial to the use of Bayes theorem in statistics and cognitive science Morris Dan 2016 Read first 6 chapters for free of Bayes Theorem Examples A Visual Introduction For Beginners Blue Windmill ISBN 978 1549761744 A short tutorial on how to understand problem scenarios and find P B P A and P B A External links EditVisual explanation of Bayes using trees on YouTube Bayes frequentist interpretation explained visually on YouTube Earliest Known Uses of Some of the Words of Mathematics B Contains origins of Bayesian Bayes Theorem Bayes Estimate Risk Solution Empirical Bayes and Bayes Factor A tutorial on probability and Bayes theorem devised for Oxford University psychology students An Intuitive Explanation of Bayes Theorem by Eliezer S Yudkowsky Bayesian Clinical Diagnostic Model Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Bayes 27 theorem amp oldid 1170002252, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.