fbpx
Wikipedia

Arrow–Debreu model

In mathematical economics, the Arrow–Debreu model is a theoretical general equilibrium model. It posits that under certain economic assumptions (convex preferences, perfect competition, and demand independence) there must be a set of prices such that aggregate supplies will equal aggregate demands for every commodity in the economy.[1]

The model is central to the theory of general (economic) equilibrium and it is often used as a general reference for other microeconomic models. It was proposed by Kenneth Arrow, Gérard Debreu in 1954,[1] and Lionel W. McKenzie independently in 1954,[2] with later improvements in 1959.[3][4]

The A-D model is one of the most general models of competitive economy and is a crucial part of general equilibrium theory, as it can be used to prove the existence of general equilibrium (or Walrasian equilibrium) of an economy. In general, there may be many equilibria.

Arrow (1972) and Debreu (1983) were separately awarded the Nobel Prize in Economics for their development of the model. McKenzie however was not awarded.[5]

Preliminary concepts edit

Convex sets and fixed points edit

 
A quarter turn of the convex unit disk leaves the point (0,0) fixed but moves every point on the non–convex unit circle.

In 1954, McKenzie and the pair Arrow and Debreu independently proved the existence of general equilibria by invoking the Kakutani fixed-point theorem on the fixed points of a continuous function from a compact, convex set into itself. In the Arrow–Debreu approach, convexity is essential, because such fixed-point theorems are inapplicable to non-convex sets. For example, the rotation of the unit circle by 90 degrees lacks fixed points, although this rotation is a continuous transformation of a compact set into itself; although compact, the unit circle is non-convex. In contrast, the same rotation applied to the convex hull of the unit circle leaves the point (0,0) fixed. Notice that the Kakutani theorem does not assert that there exists exactly one fixed point. Reflecting the unit disk across the y-axis leaves a vertical segment fixed, so that this reflection has an infinite number of fixed points.

Non-convexity in large economies edit

The assumption of convexity precluded many applications, which were discussed in the Journal of Political Economy from 1959 to 1961 by Francis M. Bator, M. J. Farrell, Tjalling Koopmans, and Thomas J. Rothenberg.[6] Ross M. Starr (1969) proved the existence of economic equilibria when some consumer preferences need not be convex.[6] In his paper, Starr proved that a "convexified" economy has general equilibria that are closely approximated by "quasi-equilbria" of the original economy; Starr's proof used the Shapley–Folkman theorem.[7]

Formal statement edit

The contents of both theorems [fundamental theorems of welfare economics] are old beliefs in economics. Arrow and Debreu have recently treated this question with techniques permitting proofs.

— Gérard Debreu, Valuation equilibrium and Pareto optimum (1954)

This statement is precisely correct; once there were beliefs, now there was knowledge. But more was at stake. Great scholars change the way that we think about the world, and about what and who we are. The Arrow-Debreu model, as communicated in Theory of Value changed basic thinking, and it quickly became the standard model of price theory. It is the “benchmark” model in Finance, International Trade, Public Finance, Transportation, and even macroeconomics... In rather short order it was no longer “as it is” in Marshall, Hicks, and Samuelson; rather it became “as it is” in Theory of Value.

— Hugo Sonnenschein, remarks at the Debreu conference, Berkeley, 2005

This section follows the presentation in,[8] which is based on.[9]

Intuitive description of the Arrow–Debreu model edit

The Arrow–Debreu model models an economy as a combination of three kinds of agents: the households, the producers, and the market. The households and producers transact with the market, but not with each other directly.

The households possess endowments (bundles of commodities they begin with), which one may think of as "inheritance". For the sake of mathematical clarity, all households are required to sell all their endowment to the market at the beginning. If they wish to retain some of the endowment, they would have to repurchase from the market later. The endowments may be working hours, use of land, tons of corn, etc.

The households possess proportional ownerships of producers, which can be thought of as joint-stock companies. The profit made by producer   is divided among the households in proportion to how much stock each household holds for the producer  . Ownership is imposed at the beginning, and the households may not sell, buy, create, or discard them.

The households receive a budget, as the sum of income from selling endowments and dividend from producer profits.

The households possess preferences over bundles of commodities, which under the assumptions given, makes them utility maximizers. The households choose the consumption plan with the highest utility that they can afford using their budget.

The producers are capable of transforming bundles of commodities into other bundles of commodities. The producers have no separate utility functions. Instead, they are all purely profit maximizers.

The market is only capable of "choosing" a market price vector, which is a list of prices for each commodity, which every producer and household takes (there is no bargaining behavior—every producer and household is a price taker). The market has no utility or profit. Instead, the market aims to choose a market price vector such that, even though each household and producer is maximizing their own utility and profit, their consumption plans and production plans "harmonize". That is, "the market clears". In other words, the market is playing the role of a "Walrasian auctioneer".

How an Arrow–Debreu model moves from beginning to end.
households producers
receive endowment and ownership of producers
sell all endowment to the market
plan production to maximize profit
enter purchase agreements between the market and each other
perform production plan
sell everything to the market
send all profits to households in proportion to ownership
plan consumption to maximize utility under budget constraint
buy the planned consumption from the market

Notation setup edit

In general, we write indices of agents as superscripts, and vector coordinate indices as subscripts.

useful notations for real vectors edit

  •   if  
  •   is the set of   such that  
  •   is the set of   such that  
  •   is the N-simplex. We often call it the price simplex since we will sometimes scale the price vector to lie on it.

market edit

  • The commodities are indexed as  . Here   is the number of commodities that exists in the economy. It is a finite number.
  • The price vector   is a vector of length  , with each coordinate being the price of a commodity. The prices may be zero or positive.

households edit

  • The households are indexed as  .
  • Each household begins with an endowment of commodities  .
  • Each household begins with a tuple of ownerships of the producers  . The ownerships satisfy  .
  • The budget that the household receives is the sum of its income from selling endowments at the market price, plus profits from its ownership of producers:
     
    (  stands for money)
  • Each household has a Consumption Possibility Set  .
  • Each household has a preference relation   over  .
  • With assumptions on   (given in the next section), each preference relation is representable by a utility function   by the Debreu theorems. Thus instead of maximizing preference, we can equivalently state that the household is maximizing its utility.
  • A consumption plan is a vector in  , written as  .
  •   is the set of consumption plans at least as preferable as  .
  • The budget set is the set of consumption plans that it can afford:
     
    .
  • For each price vector  , the household has a demand vector for commodities, as  . This function is defined as the solution to a constraint maximization problem. It depends on both the economy and the initial distribution.
     
    It may not be well-defined for all  . However, we will use enough assumptions such that that it is well-defined at equilibrium price vectors.

producers edit

  • The producers are indexed as  .
  • Each producer has a Production Possibility Set  . Note that the supply vector may have both positive and negative coordinates. For example,   indicates a production plan that uses up 1 unit of commodity 1 to produce 1 unit of commodity 2.
  • A production plan is a vector in  , written as  .
  • For each price vector  , the producer has a supply vector for commodities, as  . This function will be defined as the solution to a constraint maximization problem. It depends on both the economy and the initial distribution.
     
    It may not be well-defined for all  . However, we will use enough assumptions such that that it is well-defined at equilibrium price vectors.
  • The profit is
     

aggregates edit

  • aggregate consumption possibility set  .
  • aggregate production possibility set  .
  • aggregate endowment  
  • aggregate demand  
  • aggregate supply  
  • excess demand  

the whole economy edit

  • An economy is a tuple  . That is, it is a tuple specifying the commodities, the consumer preferences, consumption possibility sets, and the producers' production possibility sets.
  • An economy with initial distribution is an economy, along with an initial distribution tuple   for the economy.
  • A state of the economy is a tuple of price, consumption plans, and production plans for each household and producer:  .
  • A state is feasible iff each  , each  , and  .
  • The feasible production possibilities set, given endowment  , is  .
  • Given an economy with distribution, the state corresponding to a price vector   is  .
  • Given an economy with distribution, a price vector   is an equilibrium price vector for the economy with initial distribution, iff
     
    That is, if a commodity is not free, then supply exactly equals demand, and if a commodity is free, then supply is equal or greater than demand (we allow free commodity to be oversupplied).
  • A state is an equilibrium state iff it is the state corresponding to an equilibrium price vector.

Assumptions edit

on the households
assumption explanation can we relax it?
  is closed Technical assumption necessary for proofs to work. No. It is necessary for the existence of demand functions.
local nonsatiation:     Households always want to consume a little more. No. It is necessary for Walras's law to hold.
  is strictly convex strictly diminishing marginal utility Yes, to mere convexity, with Kakutani's fixed-point theorem. See next section.
  is convex diminishing marginal utility Yes, to nonconvexity, with Shapley–Folkman lemma.
continuity:   is closed. Technical assumption necessary for the existence of utility functions by the Debreu theorems. No. If the preference is not continuous, then the excess demand function may not be continuous.
  is strictly convex. For two consumption bundles, any bundle strictly between them is strictly better than the lesser. Yes, to mere convexity, with Kakutani's fixed-point theorem. See next section.
  is convex. For two consumption bundles, any bundle between them is no worse than the lesser. Yes, to nonconvexity, with Shapley–Folkman lemma.
The household always has at least one feasible consumption plan. no bankruptcy No. It is necessary for the existence of demand functions.
on the producers
assumption explanation can we relax it?
  is strictly convex diseconomies of scale Yes, to mere convexity, with Kakutani's fixed-point theorem. See next section.
  is convex no economies of scale Yes, to nonconvexity, with Shapley–Folkman lemma.
  contains 0. Producers can close down for free.
  is a closed set Technical assumption necessary for proofs to work. No. It is necessary for the existence of supply functions.
  is bounded There is no arbitrarily large "free lunch". No. Economy needs scarcity.
  is bounded The economy cannot reverse arbitrarily large transformations.

Imposing an artificial restriction edit

The functions   are not necessarily well-defined for all price vectors  . For example, if producer 1 is capable of transforming   units of commodity 1 into   units of commodity 2, and we have  , then the producer can create plans with infinite profit, thus  , and   is undefined.

Consequently, we define "restricted market" to be the same market, except there is a universal upper bound  , such that every producer is required to use a production plan  , and each household is required to use a consumption plan  . Denote the corresponding quantities on the restricted market with a tilde. So for example,   is the excess demand function on the restricted market.[10]

  is chosen to be "large enough" for the economy, so that the restriction is not in effect under equilibrium conditions (see next section). In detail,   is chosen to be large enough such that:

  • For any consumption plan   such that  , the plan is so "extravagant" that even if all the producers coordinate, they would still fall short of meeting the demand.
  • For any list of production plans for the economy  , if  , then  for each  . In other words, for any attainable production plan under the given endowment  , each producer's individual production plan must lie strictly within the restriction.

Each requirement is satisfiable.

  • Define the set of attainable aggregate production plans to be  , then under the assumptions for the producers given above (especially the "no arbitrarily large free lunch" assumption),   is bounded for any   (proof omitted). Thus the first requirement is satisfiable.
  • Define the set of attainable individual production plans to be  then under the assumptions for the producers given above (especially the "no arbitrarily large transformations" assumption),   is bounded for any   (proof omitted). Thus the second requirement is satisfiable.

The two requirements together imply that the restriction is not a real restriction when the production plans and consumption plans are "interior" to the restriction.

  • At any price vector  , if  , then   exists and is equal to  . In other words, if the production plan of a restricted producer is interior to the artificial restriction, then the unrestricted producer would choose the same production plan. This is proved by exploiting the second requirement on  .
  • If all  , then the restricted and unrestricted households have the same budget. Now, if we also have  , then   exists and is equal to  . In other words, if the consumption plan of a restricted household is interior to the artificial restriction, then the unrestricted household would choose the same consumption plan. This is proved by exploiting the first requirement on  .

These two propositions imply that equilibria for the restricted market are equilibria for the unrestricted market:

Theorem — If   is an equilibrium price vector for the restricted market, then it is also an equilibrium price vector for the unrestricted market. Furthermore, we have  .

Existence of general equilibrium edit

As the last piece of the construction, we define Walras's law:

  • The unrestricted market satisfies Walras's law at   iff all   are defined, and  , that is,
     
  • The restricted market satisfies Walras's law at   iff  .

Walras's law can be interpreted on both sides:

  • On the side of the households, it is saying that the aggregate household expenditure is equal to aggregate profit and aggregate income from selling endowments. In other words, every household spends its entire budget.
  • On the side of the producers, it is saying that the aggregate profit plus the aggregate cost equals the aggregate revenue.

Theorem —   satisfies weak Walras's law: For all  ,

 
and if  , then   for some  .
Proof sketch

If total excess demand value is exactly zero, then every household has spent all their budget. Else, some household is restricted to spend only part of their budget. Therefore, that household's consumption bundle is on the boundary of the restriction, that is,  . We have chosen (in the previous section)   to be so large that even if all the producers coordinate, they would still fall short of meeting the demand. Consequently there exists some commodity   such that  

Theorem — An equilibrium price vector exists for the restricted market, at which point the restricted market satisfies Walras's law.

Proof sketch

By definition of equilibrium, if   is an equilibrium price vector for the restricted market, then at that point, the restricted market satisfies Walras's law.

  is continuous since all   are continuous.

Define a function

 
on the price simplex, where   is a fixed positive constant.

By the weak Walras law, this function is well-defined. By Brouwer's fixed-point theorem, it has a fixed point. By the weak Walras law, this fixed point is a market equilibrium.

Note that the above proof does not give an iterative algorithm for finding any equilibrium, as there is no guarantee that the function   is a contraction. This is unsurprising, as there is no guarantee (without further assumptions) that any market equilibrium is a stable equilibrium.

Corollary — An equilibrium price vector exists for the unrestricted market, at which point the unrestricted market satisfies Walras's law.

Uzawa equivalence theorem edit

(Uzawa, 1962)[11] showed that the existence of general equilibrium in an economy characterized by a continuous excess demand function fulfilling Walras’s Law is equivalent to Brouwer fixed-Point theorem. Thus, the use of Brouwer's fixed-point theorem is essential for showing that the equilibrium exists in general.[12]

Fundamental theorems of welfare economics edit

In welfare economics, one possible concern is finding a Pareto-optimal plan for the economy.

Intuitively, one can consider the problem of welfare economics to be the problem faced by a master planner for the whole economy: given starting endowment   for the entire society, the planner must pick a feasible master plan of production and consumption plans  . The master planner has a wide freedom in choosing the master plan, but any reasonable planner should agree that, if someone's utility can be increased, while everyone else's is not decreased, then it is a better plan. That is, the Pareto ordering should be followed.

Define the Pareto ordering on the set of all plans   by   iff   for all  .

Then, we say that a plan is Pareto-efficient with respect to a starting endowment  , iff it is feasible, and there does not exist another feasible plan that is strictly better in Pareto ordering.

In general, there are a whole continuum of Pareto-efficient plans for each starting endowment  .

With the set up, we have two fundamental theorems of welfare economics:[13]

First fundamental theorem of welfare economics — Any market equilibrium state is Pareto-efficient.

Proof sketch

The price hyperplane separates the attainable productions and the Pareto-better consumptions. That is, the hyperplane   separates   and  , where   is the set of all  , such that  , and  . That is, it is the set of aggregates of all possible consumption plans that are strictly Pareto-better.

The attainable productions are on the lower side of the price hyperplane, while the Pareto-better consumptions are strictly on the upper side of the price hyperplane. Thus any Pareto-better plan is not attainable.

  • Any Pareto-better consumption plan must cost at least as much for every household, and cost more for at least one household.
  • Any attainable production plan must profit at most as much for every producer.

Second fundamental theorem of welfare economics — For any total endowment  , and any Pareto-efficient state achievable using that endowment, there exists a distribution of endowments   and private ownerships   of the producers, such that the given state is a market equilibrium state for some price vector  .

Proof idea: any Pareto-optimal consumption plan is separated by a hyperplane from the set of attainable consumption plans. The slope of the hyperplane would be the equilibrium prices. Verify that under such prices, each producer and household would find the given state optimal. Verify that Walras's law holds, and so the expenditures match income plus profit, and so it is possible to provide each household with exactly the necessary budget.

Proof

Since the state is attainable, we have  . The equality does not necessarily hold, so we define the set of attainable aggregate consumptions  . Any aggregate consumption bundle in   is attainable, and any outside is not.

Find the market price  .

Define   to be the set of all  , such that  , and  . That is, it is the set of aggregates of all possible consumption plans that are strictly Pareto-better. Since each   is convex, and each preference is convex, the set   is also convex.
Now, since the state is Pareto-optimal, the set   must be unattainable with the given endowment. That is,   is disjoint from  . Since both sets are convex, there exists a separating hyperplane between them.
Let the hyperplane be defined by  , where  , and  . The sign is chosen such that   and  .

Claim:  .

Suppose not, then there exists some   such that  . Then   if   is large enough, but we also have  , contradiction.

We have by construction  , and  . Now we claim:  .

For each household  , let   be the set of consumption plans for   that are at least as good as  , and   be the set of consumption plans for   that are strictly better than  .
By local nonsatiation of  , the closed half-space   contains  .
By continuity of  , the open half-space   contains  .
Adding them up, we find that the open half-space   contains  .

Claim (Walras's law):  

Since the production is attainable, we have  , and since  , we have  .
By construction of the separating hyperplane, we also have  , thus we have an equality.

Claim: at price  , each producer   maximizes profit at  ,

If there exists some production plan   such that one producer can reach higher profit  , then
 
but then we would have a point in   on the other side of the separating hyperplane, violating our construction.

Claim: at price   and budget  , household   maximizes utility at  .

Otherwise, there exists some   such that   and  . Then, consider aggregate consumption bundle  . It is in  , but also satisfies  . But this contradicts previous claim that  .

By Walras's law, the aggregate endowment income and profit exactly equals aggregate expenditure. It remains to distribute them such that each household   obtains exactly   as its budget. This is trivial.

Here is a greedy algorithm to do it: first distribute all endowment of commodity 1 to household 1. If household 1 can reach its budget before distributing all of it, then move on to household 2. Otherwise, start distributing all endowment of commodity 2, etc. Similarly for ownerships of producers.

Convexity vs strict convexity edit

The assumptions of strict convexity can be relaxed to convexity. This modification changes supply and demand functions from point-valued functions into set-valued functions (or "correspondences"), and the application of Brouwer's fixed-point theorem into Kakutani's fixed-point theorem.

This modification is similar to the generalization of the minimax theorem to the existence of Nash equilibria.

The two fundamental theorems of welfare economics holds without modification.

converting from strict convexity to convexity
strictly convex case convex case
  is strictly convex   is convex
  is strictly convex   is convex
  is strictly convex   is convex
  is point-valued   is set-valued
  is continuous   has closed graph ("upper hemicontinuous")
    for any  
... ...
equilibrium exists by Brouwer's fixed-point theorem equilibrium exists by Kakutani's fixed-point theorem

Equilibrium vs "quasi-equilibrium" edit

The definition of market equilibrium assumes that every household performs utility maximization, subject to budget constraints. That is,

 
The dual problem would be cost minimization subject to utility constraints. That is,
 
for some real number  . The duality gap between the two problems is nonnegative, and may be positive. Consequently, some authors study the dual problem and the properties of its "quasi-equilibrium"[14] (or "compensated equilibrium"[15]). Every equilibrium is a quasi-equilibrium, but the converse is not necessarily true.[15]

Extensions edit

Accounting for strategic bargaining edit

In the model, all producers and households are "price takers", meaning that they simply transact with the market using the price vector  . In particular, behaviors such as cartel, monopoly, consumer coalition, etc are not modelled. Edgeworth's limit theorem shows that under certain stronger assumptions, the households can do no better than price-take at the limit of an infinitely large economy.

Setup edit

In detail, we continue with the economic model on the households and producers, but we consider a different method to design production and distribution of commodities than the market economy. It may be interpreted as a model of a "socialist" economy.

  • There is no money, market, or private ownership of producers.
  • Since we have abolished private ownership, money, and the profit motive, there is no point in distinguishing one producer from the next. Consequently, instead of each producer planning individually  , it is as if the whole society has one great producer producing  .
  • Households still have the same preferences and endowments, but they no longer have budgets.
  • Producers do not produce to maximize profit, since there is no profit. All households come together to make a state  —a production and consumption plan for the whole economy—with the following constraints:
     
  • Any nonempty subset of households may eliminate all other households, while retaining control of the producers.

This economy is thus a cooperative game with each household being a player, and we have the following concepts from cooperative game theory:

  • A blocking coalition is a nonempty subset of households, such that there exists a strictly Pareto-better plan even if they eliminate all other households.
  • A state is a core state iff there are no blocking coalitions.
  • The core of an economy is the set of core states.

Since we assumed that any nonempty subset of households may eliminate all other households, while retaining control of the producers, the only states that can be executed are the core states. A state that is not a core state would immediately be objected by a coalition of households.

We need one more assumption on  , that it is a cone, that is,   for any  . This assumption rules out two ways for the economy to become trivial.

  • The curse of free lunch: In this model, the whole   is available to any nonempty coalition, even a coalition of one. Consequently, if nobody has any endowment, and yet   contains some "free lunch"  , then (assuming preferences are monotonic) every household would like to take all of   for itself, and consequently there exists *no* core state. Intuitively, the picture of the world is a committee of selfish people, vetoing any plan that doesn't give the entire free lunch to itself.
  • The limit to growth: Consider a society with 2 commodities. One is "labor" and another is "food". Households have only labor as endowment, but they only consume food. The   looks like a ramp with a flat top. So, putting in 0-1 thousand hours of labor produces 0-1 thousand kg of food, linearly, but any more labor produces no food. Now suppose each household is endowed with 1 thousand hours of labor. It's clear that every household would immediately block every other household, since it's always better for one to use the entire   for itself.

Main results (Debreu and Scarf, 1963) edit

Proposition — Market equilibria are core states.

Proof

Define the price hyperplane  . Since it's a supporting hyperplane of  , and   is a convex cone, the price hyperplane passes the origin. Thus  .

Since   is the total profit, and every producer can at least make zero profit (that is,   ), this means that the profit is exactly zero for every producer. Consequently, every household's budget is exactly from selling endowment.

 

By utility maximization, every household is already doing as much as it could. Consequently, we have  .

In particular, for any coalition  , and any production plan   that is Pareto-better, we have

 
and consequently, the point   lies above the price hyperplane, making it unattainable.

In Debreu and Scarf's paper, they defined a particular way to approach an infinitely large economy, by "replicating households". That is, for any positive integer  , define an economy where there are   households that have exactly the same consumption possibility set and preference as household  .

Let   stand for the consumption plan of the  -th replicate of household  . Define a plan to be equitable iff   for any   and  .

In general, a state would be quite complex, treating each replicate differently. However, core states are significantly simpler: they are equitable, treating every replicate equally.

Proposition — Any core state is equitable.

Proof

We use the "underdog coalition".

Consider a core state  . Define average distributions  .

It is attainable, so we have  

Suppose there exist any inequality, that is, some  , then by convexity of preferences, we have  , where   is the worst-treated household of type  .

Now define the "underdog coalition" consisting of the worst-treated household of each type, and they propose to distribute according to  . This is Pareto-better for the coalition, and since   is conic, we also have  , so the plan is attainable. Contradiction.

Consequently, when studying core states, it is sufficient to consider one consumption plan for each type of households. Now, define   to be the set of all core states for the economy with   replicates per household. It is clear that  , so we may define the limit set of core states  .

We have seen that   contains the set of market equilibria for the original economy. The converse is true under minor additional assumption:[16]

(Debreu and Scarf, 1963) — If   is a polygonal cone, or if every   has nonempty interior with respect to  , then   is the set of market equilibria for the original economy.

The assumption that   is a polygonal cone, or every   has nonempty interior, is necessary to avoid the technical issue of "quasi-equilibrium". Without the assumption, we can only prove that   is contained in the set of quasi-equilibria.

Accounting for nonconvexity edit

The assumption that production possibility sets are convex is a strong constraint, as it implies that there is no economy of scale. Similarly, we may consider nonconvex consumption possibility sets and nonconvex preferences. In such cases, the supply and demand functions   may be discontinuous with respect to price vector, thus a general equilibrium may not exist.

However, we may "convexify" the economy, find an equilibrium for it, then by the Shapley–Folkman–Starr theorem, it is an approximate equilibrium for the original economy.

In detail, given any economy satisfying all the assumptions given, except convexity of   and  , we define the "convexified economy" to be the same economy, except that

  •  
  •  
  •   iff  .

where   denotes the convex hull.

With this, any general equilibrium for the convexified economy is also an approximate equilibrium for the original economy. That is, if   is an equilibrium price vector for the convexified economy, then[17]

 
where   is the Euclidean distance, and   is any upper bound on the inner radii of all   (see page on Shapley–Folkman–Starr theorem for the definition of inner radii).

The convexified economy may not satisfy the assumptions. For example, the set   is closed, but its convex hull is not closed. Imposing the further assumption that the convexified economy also satisfies the assumptions, we find that the original economy always has an approximate equilibrium.

Accounting for time, space, and uncertainty edit

The commodities in the Arrow–Debreu model are entirely abstract. Thus, although it is typically represented as a static market, it can be used to model time, space, and uncertainty by splitting one commodity into several, each contingent on a certain time, place, and state of the world. For example, "apples" can be split into "apples in New York in September if oranges are available" and "apples in Chicago in June if oranges are not available".

Given some base commodities, the Arrow–Debreu complete market is a market where there is a separate commodity for every future time, for every place of delivery, for every state of the world under consideration, for every base commodity.

In financial economics the term "Arrow–Debreu" most commonly refers to an Arrow–Debreu security. A canonical Arrow–Debreu security is a security that pays one unit of numeraire if a particular state of the world is reached and zero otherwise (the price of such a security being a so-called "state price"). As such, any derivatives contract whose settlement value is a function on an underlying whose value is uncertain at contract date can be decomposed as linear combination of Arrow–Debreu securities.

Since the work of Breeden and Lizenberger in 1978,[18] a large number of researchers have used options to extract Arrow–Debreu prices for a variety of applications in financial economics.[19]

Accounting for the existence of money edit

No theory of money is offered here, and it is assumed that the economy works without the help of a good serving as medium of exchange.

— Gérard Debreu, Theory of value: An axiomatic analysis of economic equilibrium (1959)

To the pure theorist, at the present juncture the most interesting and challenging aspect of money is that it can find no place in an Arrow–Debreu economy. This circumstance should also be of considerable significance to macroeconomists, but it rarely is.

— Frank Hahn, The foundations of monetary theory (1987)

Typically, economists consider the functions of money to be as a unit of account, store of value, medium of exchange, and standard of deferred payment. This is however incompatible with the Arrow–Debreu complete market described above. In the complete market, there is only a one-time transaction at the market "at the beginning of time". After that, households and producers merely execute their planned productions, consumptions, and deliveries of commodities until the end of time. Consequently, there is no use for storage of value or medium of exchange. This applies not just to the Arrow–Debreu complete market, but also to models (such as those with markets of contingent commodities and Arrow insurance contracts) that differ in form, but are mathematically equivalent to it.[20]

Computing general equilibria edit

Scarf (1967)[21] was the first algorithm that computes the general equilibrium. See Scarf (2018)[22] and Kubler (2012)[23] for reviews.

Number of equilibria edit

Certain economies at certain endowment vectors may have infinitely equilibrium price vectors. However, "generically", an economy has only finitely many equilibrium price vectors. Here, "generically" means "on all points, except a closed set of Lebesgue measure zero", as in Sard's theorem.[24][25]

There are many such genericity theorems. One example is the following:[26][27]

Genericity — For any strictly positive endowment distribution  , and any strictly positive price vector  , define the excess demand   as before.

If on all  ,

  •   is well-defined,
  •   is differentiable,
  •   has  ,

then for generically any endowment distribution  , there are only finitely many equilibria  .

Proof (sketch)

Define the "equilibrium manifold" as the set of solutions to  . By Walras's law, one of the constraints is redundant. By assumptions that   has rank  , no more constraints are redundant. Thus the equilibrium manifold has dimension  , which is equal to the space of all distributions of strictly positive endowments  .

By continuity of  , the projection is closed. Thus by Sard's theorem, the projection from the equilibrium manifold to   is critical on only a set of measure 0. It remains to check that the preimage of the projection is generically not just discrete, but also finite.

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ a b Arrow, K. J.; Debreu, G. (1954). "Existence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy". Econometrica. 22 (3): 265–290. doi:10.2307/1907353. JSTOR 1907353.
  2. ^ McKenzie, Lionel W. (1954). "On Equilibrium in Graham's Model of World Trade and Other Competitive Systems". Econometrica. 22 (2): 147–161. doi:10.2307/1907539. JSTOR 1907539.
  3. ^ McKenzie, Lionel W. (1959). "On the Existence of General Equilibrium for a Competitive Economy". Econometrica. 27 (1): 54–71. doi:10.2307/1907777. JSTOR 1907777.
arrow, debreu, model, mathematical, economics, theoretical, general, equilibrium, model, posits, that, under, certain, economic, assumptions, convex, preferences, perfect, competition, demand, independence, there, must, prices, such, that, aggregate, supplies,. In mathematical economics the Arrow Debreu model is a theoretical general equilibrium model It posits that under certain economic assumptions convex preferences perfect competition and demand independence there must be a set of prices such that aggregate supplies will equal aggregate demands for every commodity in the economy 1 The model is central to the theory of general economic equilibrium and it is often used as a general reference for other microeconomic models It was proposed by Kenneth Arrow Gerard Debreu in 1954 1 and Lionel W McKenzie independently in 1954 2 with later improvements in 1959 3 4 The A D model is one of the most general models of competitive economy and is a crucial part of general equilibrium theory as it can be used to prove the existence of general equilibrium or Walrasian equilibrium of an economy In general there may be many equilibria Arrow 1972 and Debreu 1983 were separately awarded the Nobel Prize in Economics for their development of the model McKenzie however was not awarded 5 Contents 1 Preliminary concepts 1 1 Convex sets and fixed points 1 2 Non convexity in large economies 2 Formal statement 2 1 Intuitive description of the Arrow Debreu model 2 2 Notation setup 2 2 1 useful notations for real vectors 2 2 2 market 2 2 3 households 2 2 4 producers 2 2 5 aggregates 2 2 6 the whole economy 2 3 Assumptions 2 4 Imposing an artificial restriction 2 5 Existence of general equilibrium 2 6 Uzawa equivalence theorem 2 7 Fundamental theorems of welfare economics 2 8 Convexity vs strict convexity 2 9 Equilibrium vs quasi equilibrium 3 Extensions 3 1 Accounting for strategic bargaining 3 1 1 Setup 3 1 2 Main results Debreu and Scarf 1963 3 2 Accounting for nonconvexity 3 3 Accounting for time space and uncertainty 3 4 Accounting for the existence of money 3 5 Computing general equilibria 3 6 Number of equilibria 4 See also 5 References 6 Further reading 7 External linksPreliminary concepts editConvex sets and fixed points edit nbsp A quarter turn of the convex unit disk leaves the point 0 0 fixed but moves every point on the non convex unit circle Main article Kakutani fixed point theorem See also Convex set Compact set Continuous function Fixed point theorem and Brouwer fixed point theorem In 1954 McKenzie and the pair Arrow and Debreu independently proved the existence of general equilibria by invoking the Kakutani fixed point theorem on the fixed points of a continuous function from a compact convex set into itself In the Arrow Debreu approach convexity is essential because such fixed point theorems are inapplicable to non convex sets For example the rotation of the unit circle by 90 degrees lacks fixed points although this rotation is a continuous transformation of a compact set into itself although compact the unit circle is non convex In contrast the same rotation applied to the convex hull of the unit circle leaves the point 0 0 fixed Notice that the Kakutani theorem does not assert that there exists exactly one fixed point Reflecting the unit disk across the y axis leaves a vertical segment fixed so that this reflection has an infinite number of fixed points Non convexity in large economies edit See also Shapley Folkman lemma and Market failure The assumption of convexity precluded many applications which were discussed in the Journal of Political Economy from 1959 to 1961 by Francis M Bator M J Farrell Tjalling Koopmans and Thomas J Rothenberg 6 Ross M Starr 1969 proved the existence of economic equilibria when some consumer preferences need not be convex 6 In his paper Starr proved that a convexified economy has general equilibria that are closely approximated by quasi equilbria of the original economy Starr s proof used the Shapley Folkman theorem 7 Formal statement editThe contents of both theorems fundamental theorems of welfare economics are old beliefs in economics Arrow and Debreu have recently treated this question with techniques permitting proofs Gerard Debreu Valuation equilibrium and Pareto optimum 1954 This statement is precisely correct once there were beliefs now there was knowledge But more was at stake Great scholars change the way that we think about the world and about what and who we are The Arrow Debreu model as communicated in Theory of Value changed basic thinking and it quickly became the standard model of price theory It is the benchmark model in Finance International Trade Public Finance Transportation and even macroeconomics In rather short order it was no longer as it is in Marshall Hicks and Samuelson rather it became as it is in Theory of Value Hugo Sonnenschein remarks at the Debreu conference Berkeley 2005 This section follows the presentation in 8 which is based on 9 Intuitive description of the Arrow Debreu model edit The Arrow Debreu model models an economy as a combination of three kinds of agents the households the producers and the market The households and producers transact with the market but not with each other directly The households possess endowments bundles of commodities they begin with which one may think of as inheritance For the sake of mathematical clarity all households are required to sell all their endowment to the market at the beginning If they wish to retain some of the endowment they would have to repurchase from the market later The endowments may be working hours use of land tons of corn etc The households possess proportional ownerships of producers which can be thought of as joint stock companies The profit made by producer j displaystyle j nbsp is divided among the households in proportion to how much stock each household holds for the producer j displaystyle j nbsp Ownership is imposed at the beginning and the households may not sell buy create or discard them The households receive a budget as the sum of income from selling endowments and dividend from producer profits The households possess preferences over bundles of commodities which under the assumptions given makes them utility maximizers The households choose the consumption plan with the highest utility that they can afford using their budget The producers are capable of transforming bundles of commodities into other bundles of commodities The producers have no separate utility functions Instead they are all purely profit maximizers The market is only capable of choosing a market price vector which is a list of prices for each commodity which every producer and household takes there is no bargaining behavior every producer and household is a price taker The market has no utility or profit Instead the market aims to choose a market price vector such that even though each household and producer is maximizing their own utility and profit their consumption plans and production plans harmonize That is the market clears In other words the market is playing the role of a Walrasian auctioneer How an Arrow Debreu model moves from beginning to end households producersreceive endowment and ownership of producerssell all endowment to the marketplan production to maximize profitenter purchase agreements between the market and each otherperform production plansell everything to the marketsend all profits to households in proportion to ownershipplan consumption to maximize utility under budget constraintbuy the planned consumption from the marketNotation setup edit In general we write indices of agents as superscripts and vector coordinate indices as subscripts useful notations for real vectors edit x y displaystyle x succeq y nbsp if n x n y n displaystyle forall n x n geq y n nbsp R N displaystyle mathbb R N nbsp is the set of x displaystyle x nbsp such that x 0 displaystyle x succeq 0 nbsp R N displaystyle mathbb R N nbsp is the set of x displaystyle x nbsp such that x 0 displaystyle x succ 0 nbsp D N x R N x 1 x N 0 n 1 N x n 1 displaystyle Delta N left x in mathbb R N x 1 x N geq 0 sum n in 1 N x n 1 right nbsp is the N simplex We often call it the price simplex since we will sometimes scale the price vector to lie on it market edit The commodities are indexed as n 1 N displaystyle n in 1 N nbsp Here N displaystyle N nbsp is the number of commodities that exists in the economy It is a finite number The price vector p p 1 p N R N displaystyle p p 1 p N in mathbb R N nbsp is a vector of length N displaystyle N nbsp with each coordinate being the price of a commodity The prices may be zero or positive households edit The households are indexed as i I displaystyle i in I nbsp Each household begins with an endowment of commodities r i R N displaystyle r i in mathbb R N nbsp Each household begins with a tuple of ownerships of the producers a i j 0 displaystyle alpha i j geq 0 nbsp The ownerships satisfy i I a i j 1 j J displaystyle sum i in I alpha i j 1 quad forall j in J nbsp The budget that the household receives is the sum of its income from selling endowments at the market price plus profits from its ownership of producers M i p p r i j J a i j P j p displaystyle M i p langle p r i rangle sum j in J alpha i j Pi j p nbsp M displaystyle M nbsp stands for money Each household has a Consumption Possibility Set C P S i R N displaystyle CPS i subset mathbb R N nbsp Each household has a preference relation i displaystyle succeq i nbsp over C P S i displaystyle CPS i nbsp With assumptions on i displaystyle succeq i nbsp given in the next section each preference relation is representable by a utility function u i C P S i 0 1 displaystyle u i CPS i to 0 1 nbsp by the Debreu theorems Thus instead of maximizing preference we can equivalently state that the household is maximizing its utility A consumption plan is a vector in C P S i displaystyle CPS i nbsp written as x i displaystyle x i nbsp U i x i displaystyle U i x i nbsp is the set of consumption plans at least as preferable as x i displaystyle x i nbsp The budget set is the set of consumption plans that it can afford B i p x i C P S i p x i M i p displaystyle B i p x i in CPS i langle p x i rangle leq M i p nbsp For each price vector p displaystyle p nbsp the household has a demand vector for commodities as D i p R N displaystyle D i p in mathbb R N nbsp This function is defined as the solution to a constraint maximization problem It depends on both the economy and the initial distribution D i p arg max x i B i p u i x i displaystyle D i p arg max x i in B i p u i x i nbsp It may not be well defined for all p R N displaystyle p in mathbb R N nbsp However we will use enough assumptions such that that it is well defined at equilibrium price vectors producers edit The producers are indexed as j J displaystyle j in J nbsp Each producer has a Production Possibility Set P P S j displaystyle PPS j nbsp Note that the supply vector may have both positive and negative coordinates For example 1 1 0 displaystyle 1 1 0 nbsp indicates a production plan that uses up 1 unit of commodity 1 to produce 1 unit of commodity 2 A production plan is a vector in P P S j displaystyle PPS j nbsp written as y j displaystyle y j nbsp For each price vector p displaystyle p nbsp the producer has a supply vector for commodities as S j p R N displaystyle S j p in mathbb R N nbsp This function will be defined as the solution to a constraint maximization problem It depends on both the economy and the initial distribution S j p arg max y j P P S j p y j displaystyle S j p arg max y j in PPS j langle p y j rangle nbsp It may not be well defined for all p R N displaystyle p in mathbb R N nbsp However we will use enough assumptions such that that it is well defined at equilibrium price vectors The profit is P j p p S j p max y j P P S j p y j displaystyle Pi j p langle p S j p rangle max y j in PPS j langle p y j rangle nbsp aggregates edit aggregate consumption possibility set C P S i I C P S i displaystyle CPS sum i in I CPS i nbsp aggregate production possibility set P P S j J P P S j displaystyle PPS sum j in J PPS j nbsp aggregate endowment r i r i displaystyle r sum i r i nbsp aggregate demand D p i D i p displaystyle D p sum i D i p nbsp aggregate supply S p j S j p displaystyle S p sum j S j p nbsp excess demand Z p D p S p r displaystyle Z p D p S p r nbsp the whole economy edit An economy is a tuple N I J C P S i i P P S j displaystyle N I J CPS i succeq i PPS j nbsp That is it is a tuple specifying the commodities the consumer preferences consumption possibility sets and the producers production possibility sets An economy with initial distribution is an economy along with an initial distribution tuple r i a i j i I j J displaystyle r i alpha i j i in I j in J nbsp for the economy A state of the economy is a tuple of price consumption plans and production plans for each household and producer p n n 1 N x i i I y j j J displaystyle p n n in 1 N x i i in I y j j in J nbsp A state is feasible iff each x i C P S i displaystyle x i in CPS i nbsp each y j P P S j displaystyle y j in PPS j nbsp and i I x i j J y j r displaystyle sum i in I x i preceq sum j in J y j r nbsp The feasible production possibilities set given endowment r displaystyle r nbsp is P P S r y P P S y r 0 displaystyle PPS r y in PPS y r succeq 0 nbsp Given an economy with distribution the state corresponding to a price vector p displaystyle p nbsp is p D i p i I S j p j J displaystyle p D i p i in I S j p j in J nbsp Given an economy with distribution a price vector p displaystyle p nbsp is an equilibrium price vector for the economy with initial distribution iffZ p n 0 if p n 0 0 if p n gt 0 displaystyle Z p n begin cases leq 0 text if p n 0 0 text if p n gt 0 end cases nbsp That is if a commodity is not free then supply exactly equals demand and if a commodity is free then supply is equal or greater than demand we allow free commodity to be oversupplied A state is an equilibrium state iff it is the state corresponding to an equilibrium price vector Assumptions edit on the households assumption explanation can we relax it C P S i displaystyle CPS i nbsp is closed Technical assumption necessary for proofs to work No It is necessary for the existence of demand functions local nonsatiation x C P S i ϵ gt 0 displaystyle forall x in CPS i epsilon gt 0 nbsp x C P S i x i x x x lt ϵ displaystyle exists x in CPS i x succ i x x x lt epsilon nbsp Households always want to consume a little more No It is necessary for Walras s law to hold C P S i displaystyle CPS i nbsp is strictly convex strictly diminishing marginal utility Yes to mere convexity with Kakutani s fixed point theorem See next section C P S i displaystyle CPS i nbsp is convex diminishing marginal utility Yes to nonconvexity with Shapley Folkman lemma continuity U i x i displaystyle U i x i nbsp is closed Technical assumption necessary for the existence of utility functions by the Debreu theorems No If the preference is not continuous then the excess demand function may not be continuous U i x i displaystyle U i x i nbsp is strictly convex For two consumption bundles any bundle strictly between them is strictly better than the lesser Yes to mere convexity with Kakutani s fixed point theorem See next section U i x i displaystyle U i x i nbsp is convex For two consumption bundles any bundle between them is no worse than the lesser Yes to nonconvexity with Shapley Folkman lemma The household always has at least one feasible consumption plan no bankruptcy No It is necessary for the existence of demand functions on the producers assumption explanation can we relax it P P S j displaystyle PPS j nbsp is strictly convex diseconomies of scale Yes to mere convexity with Kakutani s fixed point theorem See next section P P S j displaystyle PPS j nbsp is convex no economies of scale Yes to nonconvexity with Shapley Folkman lemma P P S j displaystyle PPS j nbsp contains 0 Producers can close down for free P P S j displaystyle PPS j nbsp is a closed set Technical assumption necessary for proofs to work No It is necessary for the existence of supply functions P P S R N displaystyle PPS cap mathbb R N nbsp is bounded There is no arbitrarily large free lunch No Economy needs scarcity P P S P P S displaystyle PPS cap PPS nbsp is bounded The economy cannot reverse arbitrarily large transformations Imposing an artificial restriction edit The functions D i p S j p displaystyle D i p S j p nbsp are not necessarily well defined for all price vectors p displaystyle p nbsp For example if producer 1 is capable of transforming t displaystyle t nbsp units of commodity 1 into t 1 2 1 displaystyle sqrt t 1 2 1 nbsp units of commodity 2 and we have p 1 p 2 lt 1 displaystyle p 1 p 2 lt 1 nbsp then the producer can create plans with infinite profit thus P j p displaystyle Pi j p infty nbsp and S j p displaystyle S j p nbsp is undefined Consequently we define restricted market to be the same market except there is a universal upper bound C displaystyle C nbsp such that every producer is required to use a production plan y j C displaystyle y j leq C nbsp and each household is required to use a consumption plan x i C displaystyle x i leq C nbsp Denote the corresponding quantities on the restricted market with a tilde So for example Z p displaystyle tilde Z p nbsp is the excess demand function on the restricted market 10 C displaystyle C nbsp is chosen to be large enough for the economy so that the restriction is not in effect under equilibrium conditions see next section In detail C displaystyle C nbsp is chosen to be large enough such that For any consumption plan x displaystyle x nbsp such that x 0 x C displaystyle x succeq 0 x C nbsp the plan is so extravagant that even if all the producers coordinate they would still fall short of meeting the demand For any list of production plans for the economy y j P P S j j J displaystyle y j in PPS j j in J nbsp if j J y j r 0 displaystyle sum j in J y j r succeq 0 nbsp then y j lt C displaystyle y j lt C nbsp for each j J displaystyle j in J nbsp In other words for any attainable production plan under the given endowment r displaystyle r nbsp each producer s individual production plan must lie strictly within the restriction Each requirement is satisfiable Define the set of attainable aggregate production plans to be P P S r j J y j y j P P S j for each j J and j J y j r 0 displaystyle PPS r left sum j in J y j y j in PPS j text for each j in J text and sum j in J y j r succeq 0 right nbsp then under the assumptions for the producers given above especially the no arbitrarily large free lunch assumption P P S r displaystyle PPS r nbsp is bounded for any r 0 displaystyle r succeq 0 nbsp proof omitted Thus the first requirement is satisfiable Define the set of attainable individual production plans to be P P S r j y j P P S j y j is a part of some attainable production plan under endowment r displaystyle PPS r j y j in PPS j y j text is a part of some attainable production plan under endowment r nbsp then under the assumptions for the producers given above especially the no arbitrarily large transformations assumption P P S r j displaystyle PPS r j nbsp is bounded for any j J r 0 displaystyle j in J r succeq 0 nbsp proof omitted Thus the second requirement is satisfiable The two requirements together imply that the restriction is not a real restriction when the production plans and consumption plans are interior to the restriction At any price vector p displaystyle p nbsp if S j p lt C displaystyle tilde S j p lt C nbsp then S j p displaystyle S j p nbsp exists and is equal to S j p displaystyle tilde S j p nbsp In other words if the production plan of a restricted producer is interior to the artificial restriction then the unrestricted producer would choose the same production plan This is proved by exploiting the second requirement on C displaystyle C nbsp If all S j p S j p displaystyle S j p tilde S j p nbsp then the restricted and unrestricted households have the same budget Now if we also have D i p lt C displaystyle tilde D i p lt C nbsp then D i p displaystyle D i p nbsp exists and is equal to D i p displaystyle tilde D i p nbsp In other words if the consumption plan of a restricted household is interior to the artificial restriction then the unrestricted household would choose the same consumption plan This is proved by exploiting the first requirement on C displaystyle C nbsp These two propositions imply that equilibria for the restricted market are equilibria for the unrestricted market Theorem If p displaystyle p nbsp is an equilibrium price vector for the restricted market then it is also an equilibrium price vector for the unrestricted market Furthermore we have D i p D i p S j p S j p displaystyle tilde D i p D i p tilde S j p S j p nbsp Existence of general equilibrium edit As the last piece of the construction we define Walras s law The unrestricted market satisfies Walras s law at p displaystyle p nbsp iff all S j p D i p displaystyle S j p D i p nbsp are defined and p Z p 0 displaystyle langle p Z p rangle 0 nbsp that is j J p S j p p r i I p D i p displaystyle sum j in J langle p S j p rangle langle p r rangle sum i in I langle p D i p rangle nbsp The restricted market satisfies Walras s law at p displaystyle p nbsp iff p Z p 0 displaystyle langle p tilde Z p rangle 0 nbsp Walras s law can be interpreted on both sides On the side of the households it is saying that the aggregate household expenditure is equal to aggregate profit and aggregate income from selling endowments In other words every household spends its entire budget On the side of the producers it is saying that the aggregate profit plus the aggregate cost equals the aggregate revenue Theorem Z displaystyle tilde Z nbsp satisfies weak Walras s law For all p R N displaystyle p in mathbb R N nbsp p Z p 0 displaystyle langle p tilde Z p rangle leq 0 nbsp and if p Z p lt 0 displaystyle langle p tilde Z p rangle lt 0 nbsp then Z p n gt 0 displaystyle tilde Z p n gt 0 nbsp for some n displaystyle n nbsp Proof sketch If total excess demand value is exactly zero then every household has spent all their budget Else some household is restricted to spend only part of their budget Therefore that household s consumption bundle is on the boundary of the restriction that is D i p C displaystyle tilde D i p C nbsp We have chosen in the previous section C displaystyle C nbsp to be so large that even if all the producers coordinate they would still fall short of meeting the demand Consequently there exists some commodity n displaystyle n nbsp such that D i p n gt S p n r n displaystyle tilde D i p n gt tilde S p n r n nbsp Theorem An equilibrium price vector exists for the restricted market at which point the restricted market satisfies Walras s law Proof sketch By definition of equilibrium if p displaystyle p nbsp is an equilibrium price vector for the restricted market then at that point the restricted market satisfies Walras s law Z displaystyle tilde Z nbsp is continuous since all S j D i displaystyle tilde S j tilde D i nbsp are continuous Define a functionf p max 0 p g Z p n max 0 p n g Z p n displaystyle f p frac max 0 p gamma tilde Z p sum n max 0 p n gamma tilde Z p n nbsp on the price simplex where g displaystyle gamma nbsp is a fixed positive constant By the weak Walras law this function is well defined By Brouwer s fixed point theorem it has a fixed point By the weak Walras law this fixed point is a market equilibrium Note that the above proof does not give an iterative algorithm for finding any equilibrium as there is no guarantee that the function f displaystyle f nbsp is a contraction This is unsurprising as there is no guarantee without further assumptions that any market equilibrium is a stable equilibrium Corollary An equilibrium price vector exists for the unrestricted market at which point the unrestricted market satisfies Walras s law Uzawa equivalence theorem edit Uzawa 1962 11 showed that the existence of general equilibrium in an economy characterized by a continuous excess demand function fulfilling Walras s Law is equivalent to Brouwer fixed Point theorem Thus the use of Brouwer s fixed point theorem is essential for showing that the equilibrium exists in general 12 Fundamental theorems of welfare economics edit In welfare economics one possible concern is finding a Pareto optimal plan for the economy Intuitively one can consider the problem of welfare economics to be the problem faced by a master planner for the whole economy given starting endowment r displaystyle r nbsp for the entire society the planner must pick a feasible master plan of production and consumption plans x i i I y j j J displaystyle x i i in I y j j in J nbsp The master planner has a wide freedom in choosing the master plan but any reasonable planner should agree that if someone s utility can be increased while everyone else s is not decreased then it is a better plan That is the Pareto ordering should be followed Define the Pareto ordering on the set of all plans x i i I y j j J displaystyle x i i in I y j j in J nbsp by x i i I y j j J x i i I y j j J displaystyle x i i in I y j j in J succeq x i i in I y j j in J nbsp iff x i i x i displaystyle x i succeq i x i nbsp for all i I displaystyle i in I nbsp Then we say that a plan is Pareto efficient with respect to a starting endowment r displaystyle r nbsp iff it is feasible and there does not exist another feasible plan that is strictly better in Pareto ordering In general there are a whole continuum of Pareto efficient plans for each starting endowment r displaystyle r nbsp With the set up we have two fundamental theorems of welfare economics 13 First fundamental theorem of welfare economics Any market equilibrium state is Pareto efficient Proof sketch The price hyperplane separates the attainable productions and the Pareto better consumptions That is the hyperplane p q p D p displaystyle langle p q rangle langle p D p rangle nbsp separates r P P S r displaystyle r PPS r nbsp and U displaystyle U nbsp where U displaystyle U nbsp is the set of all i I x i displaystyle sum i in I x i nbsp such that i I x i C P S i x i i x i displaystyle forall i in I x i in CPS i x i succeq i x i nbsp and i I x i i x i displaystyle exists i in I x i succ i x i nbsp That is it is the set of aggregates of all possible consumption plans that are strictly Pareto better The attainable productions are on the lower side of the price hyperplane while the Pareto better consumptions are strictly on the upper side of the price hyperplane Thus any Pareto better plan is not attainable Any Pareto better consumption plan must cost at least as much for every household and cost more for at least one household Any attainable production plan must profit at most as much for every producer Second fundamental theorem of welfare economics For any total endowment r displaystyle r nbsp and any Pareto efficient state achievable using that endowment there exists a distribution of endowments r i i I displaystyle r i i in I nbsp and private ownerships a i j i I j J displaystyle alpha i j i in I j in J nbsp of the producers such that the given state is a market equilibrium state for some price vector p R N displaystyle p in mathbb R N nbsp Proof idea any Pareto optimal consumption plan is separated by a hyperplane from the set of attainable consumption plans The slope of the hyperplane would be the equilibrium prices Verify that under such prices each producer and household would find the given state optimal Verify that Walras s law holds and so the expenditures match income plus profit and so it is possible to provide each household with exactly the necessary budget Proof Since the state is attainable we have i I x i j J y j r displaystyle sum i in I x i preceq sum j in J y j r nbsp The equality does not necessarily hold so we define the set of attainable aggregate consumptions V r y z y P P S z 0 displaystyle V r y z y in PPS z succeq 0 nbsp Any aggregate consumption bundle in V displaystyle V nbsp is attainable and any outside is not Find the market price p displaystyle p nbsp Define U displaystyle U nbsp to be the set of all i I x i displaystyle sum i in I x i nbsp such that i I x i C P S i x i i x i displaystyle forall i in I x i in CPS i x i succeq i x i nbsp and i I x i i x i displaystyle exists i in I x i succ i x i nbsp That is it is the set of aggregates of all possible consumption plans that are strictly Pareto better Since each C P S i displaystyle CPS i nbsp is convex and each preference is convex the set U displaystyle U nbsp is also convex Now since the state is Pareto optimal the set U displaystyle U nbsp must be unattainable with the given endowment That is U displaystyle U nbsp is disjoint from V displaystyle V nbsp Since both sets are convex there exists a separating hyperplane between them Let the hyperplane be defined by p q c displaystyle langle p q rangle c nbsp where p R N p 0 displaystyle p in mathbb R N p neq 0 nbsp and c i I p x i displaystyle c sum i in I langle p x i rangle nbsp The sign is chosen such that p U c displaystyle langle p U rangle geq c nbsp and p r P P S c displaystyle langle p r PPS rangle leq c nbsp Claim p 0 displaystyle p succ 0 nbsp Suppose not then there exists some n 1 N displaystyle n in 1 N nbsp such that p n lt 0 displaystyle p n lt 0 nbsp Then p r 0 k e n gt c displaystyle langle p r 0 ke n rangle gt c nbsp if k displaystyle k nbsp is large enough but we also have r 0 k e n V displaystyle r 0 ke n in V nbsp contradiction We have by construction p i I x i c displaystyle langle p sum i in I x i rangle c nbsp and p V c displaystyle langle p V rangle leq c nbsp Now we claim p U gt c displaystyle langle p U rangle gt c nbsp For each household i displaystyle i nbsp let U i x i displaystyle U i x i nbsp be the set of consumption plans for i displaystyle i nbsp that are at least as good as x i displaystyle x i nbsp and U i x i displaystyle U i x i nbsp be the set of consumption plans for i displaystyle i nbsp that are strictly better than x i displaystyle x i nbsp By local nonsatiation of i displaystyle succeq i nbsp the closed half space p q p x i displaystyle langle p q rangle geq langle p x i rangle nbsp contains U i x i displaystyle U i x i nbsp By continuity of i displaystyle succeq i nbsp the open half space p q gt p x i displaystyle langle p q rangle gt langle p x i rangle nbsp contains U i x i displaystyle U i x i nbsp Adding them up we find that the open half space p q gt c displaystyle langle p q rangle gt c nbsp contains U displaystyle U nbsp Claim Walras s law p r j y j c p i x i displaystyle langle p r sum j y j rangle c langle p sum i x i rangle nbsp Since the production is attainable we have r j y j i x i displaystyle r sum j y j succeq sum i x i nbsp and since p 0 displaystyle p succ 0 nbsp we have p r j y j p i x i displaystyle langle p r sum j y j rangle geq langle p sum i x i rangle nbsp By construction of the separating hyperplane we also have p r j y j c p i x i displaystyle langle p r sum j y j rangle leq c langle p sum i x i rangle nbsp thus we have an equality Claim at price p displaystyle p nbsp each producer j displaystyle j nbsp maximizes profit at y j displaystyle y j nbsp If there exists some production plan y j displaystyle y j nbsp such that one producer can reach higher profit p y j gt p y j displaystyle langle p y j rangle gt langle p y j rangle nbsp then p r j J p y j gt p r j J p y j c displaystyle langle p r rangle sum j in J langle p y j rangle gt langle p r rangle sum j in J langle p y j rangle c nbsp but then we would have a point in r P P S displaystyle r PPS nbsp on the other side of the separating hyperplane violating our construction Claim at price p displaystyle p nbsp and budget p x i displaystyle langle p x i rangle nbsp household i displaystyle i nbsp maximizes utility at x i displaystyle x i nbsp Otherwise there exists some x i displaystyle x i nbsp such that x i i x i displaystyle x i succ i x i nbsp and p x i p x i displaystyle langle p x i rangle leq langle p x i rangle nbsp Then consider aggregate consumption bundle q i I i i x i x i displaystyle q sum i in I i neq i x i x i nbsp It is in U displaystyle U nbsp but also satisfies p q p x i c displaystyle langle p q rangle leq sum langle p x i rangle c nbsp But this contradicts previous claim that p U gt c displaystyle langle p U rangle gt c nbsp By Walras s law the aggregate endowment income and profit exactly equals aggregate expenditure It remains to distribute them such that each household i displaystyle i nbsp obtains exactly p x i displaystyle langle p x i rangle nbsp as its budget This is trivial Here is a greedy algorithm to do it first distribute all endowment of commodity 1 to household 1 If household 1 can reach its budget before distributing all of it then move on to household 2 Otherwise start distributing all endowment of commodity 2 etc Similarly for ownerships of producers Convexity vs strict convexity edit The assumptions of strict convexity can be relaxed to convexity This modification changes supply and demand functions from point valued functions into set valued functions or correspondences and the application of Brouwer s fixed point theorem into Kakutani s fixed point theorem This modification is similar to the generalization of the minimax theorem to the existence of Nash equilibria The two fundamental theorems of welfare economics holds without modification converting from strict convexity to convexity strictly convex case convex caseP P S j displaystyle PPS j nbsp is strictly convex P P S j displaystyle PPS j nbsp is convexC P S i displaystyle CPS i nbsp is strictly convex C P S i displaystyle CPS i nbsp is convex i displaystyle succeq i nbsp is strictly convex i displaystyle succeq i nbsp is convexS j p displaystyle tilde S j p nbsp is point valued S j p displaystyle tilde S j p nbsp is set valuedS j p displaystyle tilde S j p nbsp is continuous S j p displaystyle tilde S j p nbsp has closed graph upper hemicontinuous p Z p 0 displaystyle langle p tilde Z p rangle leq 0 nbsp p z 0 displaystyle langle p z rangle leq 0 nbsp for any z Z p displaystyle z in tilde Z p nbsp equilibrium exists by Brouwer s fixed point theorem equilibrium exists by Kakutani s fixed point theoremEquilibrium vs quasi equilibrium edit The definition of market equilibrium assumes that every household performs utility maximization subject to budget constraints That is max x i u i x i p x i M i p displaystyle begin cases max x i u i x i langle p x i rangle leq M i p end cases nbsp The dual problem would be cost minimization subject to utility constraints That is u i x i u 0 i min x i p x i displaystyle begin cases u i x i geq u 0 i min x i langle p x i rangle end cases nbsp for some real number u 0 i displaystyle u 0 i nbsp The duality gap between the two problems is nonnegative and may be positive Consequently some authors study the dual problem and the properties of its quasi equilibrium 14 or compensated equilibrium 15 Every equilibrium is a quasi equilibrium but the converse is not necessarily true 15 Extensions editAccounting for strategic bargaining edit In the model all producers and households are price takers meaning that they simply transact with the market using the price vector p displaystyle p nbsp In particular behaviors such as cartel monopoly consumer coalition etc are not modelled Edgeworth s limit theorem shows that under certain stronger assumptions the households can do no better than price take at the limit of an infinitely large economy Setup edit In detail we continue with the economic model on the households and producers but we consider a different method to design production and distribution of commodities than the market economy It may be interpreted as a model of a socialist economy There is no money market or private ownership of producers Since we have abolished private ownership money and the profit motive there is no point in distinguishing one producer from the next Consequently instead of each producer planning individually y j P P S j displaystyle y j in PPS j nbsp it is as if the whole society has one great producer producing y P P S displaystyle y in PPS nbsp Households still have the same preferences and endowments but they no longer have budgets Producers do not produce to maximize profit since there is no profit All households come together to make a state x i i I y displaystyle x i i in I y nbsp a production and consumption plan for the whole economy with the following constraints x i C P S i y P P S y i x i r i displaystyle x i in CPS i y in PPS y succeq sum i x i r i nbsp Any nonempty subset of households may eliminate all other households while retaining control of the producers This economy is thus a cooperative game with each household being a player and we have the following concepts from cooperative game theory A blocking coalition is a nonempty subset of households such that there exists a strictly Pareto better plan even if they eliminate all other households A state is a core state iff there are no blocking coalitions The core of an economy is the set of core states Since we assumed that any nonempty subset of households may eliminate all other households while retaining control of the producers the only states that can be executed are the core states A state that is not a core state would immediately be objected by a coalition of households We need one more assumption on P P S displaystyle PPS nbsp that it is a cone that is k P P S P P S displaystyle k cdot PPS subset PPS nbsp for any k 0 displaystyle k geq 0 nbsp This assumption rules out two ways for the economy to become trivial The curse of free lunch In this model the whole P P S displaystyle PPS nbsp is available to any nonempty coalition even a coalition of one Consequently if nobody has any endowment and yet P P S displaystyle PPS nbsp contains some free lunch y 0 displaystyle y succ 0 nbsp then assuming preferences are monotonic every household would like to take all of y displaystyle y nbsp for itself and consequently there exists no core state Intuitively the picture of the world is a committee of selfish people vetoing any plan that doesn t give the entire free lunch to itself The limit to growth Consider a society with 2 commodities One is labor and another is food Households have only labor as endowment but they only consume food The P P S displaystyle PPS nbsp looks like a ramp with a flat top So putting in 0 1 thousand hours of labor produces 0 1 thousand kg of food linearly but any more labor produces no food Now suppose each household is endowed with 1 thousand hours of labor It s clear that every household would immediately block every other household since it s always better for one to use the entire P P S displaystyle PPS nbsp for itself Main results Debreu and Scarf 1963 edit Proposition Market equilibria are core states Proof Define the price hyperplane p q p j y j displaystyle langle p q rangle langle p sum j y j rangle nbsp Since it s a supporting hyperplane of P P S displaystyle PPS nbsp and P P S displaystyle PPS nbsp is a convex cone the price hyperplane passes the origin Thus p j y j p i x i r i 0 displaystyle langle p sum j y j rangle langle p sum i x i r i rangle 0 nbsp Since j p y j displaystyle sum j langle p y j rangle nbsp is the total profit and every producer can at least make zero profit that is 0 P P S j displaystyle 0 in PPS j nbsp this means that the profit is exactly zero for every producer Consequently every household s budget is exactly from selling endowment p x i p r i displaystyle langle p x i rangle langle p r i rangle nbsp By utility maximization every household is already doing as much as it could Consequently we have p U i x i gt p r i displaystyle langle p U i x i rangle gt langle p r i rangle nbsp In particular for any coalition I I displaystyle I subset I nbsp and any production plan x i displaystyle x i nbsp that is Pareto better we have i I p x i gt i I p r i displaystyle sum i in I langle p x i rangle gt sum i in I langle p r i rangle nbsp and consequently the point i I x i r i displaystyle sum i in I x i r i nbsp lies above the price hyperplane making it unattainable In Debreu and Scarf s paper they defined a particular way to approach an infinitely large economy by replicating households That is for any positive integer K displaystyle K nbsp define an economy where there are K displaystyle K nbsp households that have exactly the same consumption possibility set and preference as household i displaystyle i nbsp Let x i k displaystyle x i k nbsp stand for the consumption plan of the k displaystyle k nbsp th replicate of household i displaystyle i nbsp Define a plan to be equitable iff x i k i x i k displaystyle x i k sim i x i k nbsp for any i I displaystyle i in I nbsp and k k K displaystyle k k in K nbsp In general a state would be quite complex treating each replicate differently However core states are significantly simpler they are equitable treating every replicate equally Proposition Any core state is equitable Proof We use the underdog coalition Consider a core state x i k displaystyle x i k nbsp Define average distributions x i 1 K k K x i k displaystyle bar x i frac 1 K sum k in K x i k nbsp It is attainable so we have K i x i r i P P S displaystyle K sum i bar x i r i in PPS nbsp Suppose there exist any inequality that is some x i k i x i k displaystyle x i k succ i x i k nbsp then by convexity of preferences we have x i i x i k displaystyle bar x i succ i x i k nbsp where k displaystyle k nbsp is the worst treated household of type i displaystyle i nbsp Now define the underdog coalition consisting of the worst treated household of each type and they propose to distribute according to x i displaystyle bar x i nbsp This is Pareto better for the coalition and since P P displaystyle PP nbsp is conic we also have i x i r i P P S displaystyle sum i bar x i r i in PPS nbsp so the plan is attainable Contradiction Consequently when studying core states it is sufficient to consider one consumption plan for each type of households Now define C K displaystyle C K nbsp to be the set of all core states for the economy with K displaystyle K nbsp replicates per household It is clear that C 1 C 2 displaystyle C 1 supset C 2 supset cdots nbsp so we may define the limit set of core states C K 1 C K displaystyle C cap K 1 infty C K nbsp We have seen that C displaystyle C nbsp contains the set of market equilibria for the original economy The converse is true under minor additional assumption 16 Debreu and Scarf 1963 If P P S displaystyle PPS nbsp is a polygonal cone or if every C P S i displaystyle CPS i nbsp has nonempty interior with respect to R N displaystyle mathbb R N nbsp then C displaystyle C nbsp is the set of market equilibria for the original economy The assumption that P P S displaystyle PPS nbsp is a polygonal cone or every C P S i displaystyle CPS i nbsp has nonempty interior is necessary to avoid the technical issue of quasi equilibrium Without the assumption we can only prove that C displaystyle C nbsp is contained in the set of quasi equilibria Accounting for nonconvexity edit The assumption that production possibility sets are convex is a strong constraint as it implies that there is no economy of scale Similarly we may consider nonconvex consumption possibility sets and nonconvex preferences In such cases the supply and demand functions S j p D i p displaystyle S j p D i p nbsp may be discontinuous with respect to price vector thus a general equilibrium may not exist However we may convexify the economy find an equilibrium for it then by the Shapley Folkman Starr theorem it is an approximate equilibrium for the original economy In detail given any economy satisfying all the assumptions given except convexity of P P S j C P S i displaystyle PPS j CPS i nbsp and i displaystyle succeq i nbsp we define the convexified economy to be the same economy except that P P S j C o n v P P S j displaystyle PPS j mathrm Conv PPS j nbsp C P S i C o n v C P S i displaystyle CPS i mathrm Conv CPS i nbsp x i y displaystyle x succeq i y nbsp iff z C P S i y C o n v U i z x C o n v U i z displaystyle forall z in CPS i y in mathrm Conv U i z implies x in mathrm Conv U i z nbsp where C o n v displaystyle mathrm Conv nbsp denotes the convex hull With this any general equilibrium for the convexified economy is also an approximate equilibrium for the original economy That is if p displaystyle p nbsp is an equilibrium price vector for the convexified economy then 17 d D p S p D p S p N L d r D p S p N L displaystyle begin aligned d D p S p D p S p amp leq N sqrt L d r D p S p amp leq N sqrt L end aligned nbsp where d displaystyle d cdot cdot nbsp is the Euclidean distance and L displaystyle L nbsp is any upper bound on the inner radii of all P P S j C P S i displaystyle PPS j CPS i nbsp see page on Shapley Folkman Starr theorem for the definition of inner radii The convexified economy may not satisfy the assumptions For example the set x 0 x 0 x y x y 1 x gt 0 displaystyle x 0 x geq 0 cup x y xy 1 x gt 0 nbsp is closed but its convex hull is not closed Imposing the further assumption that the convexified economy also satisfies the assumptions we find that the original economy always has an approximate equilibrium Accounting for time space and uncertainty edit Further information Financial economics State prices State prices Application to financial assets and Contingent claim analysis The commodities in the Arrow Debreu model are entirely abstract Thus although it is typically represented as a static market it can be used to model time space and uncertainty by splitting one commodity into several each contingent on a certain time place and state of the world For example apples can be split into apples in New York in September if oranges are available and apples in Chicago in June if oranges are not available Given some base commodities the Arrow Debreu complete market is a market where there is a separate commodity for every future time for every place of delivery for every state of the world under consideration for every base commodity In financial economics the term Arrow Debreu most commonly refers to an Arrow Debreu security A canonical Arrow Debreu security is a security that pays one unit of numeraire if a particular state of the world is reached and zero otherwise the price of such a security being a so called state price As such any derivatives contract whose settlement value is a function on an underlying whose value is uncertain at contract date can be decomposed as linear combination of Arrow Debreu securities Since the work of Breeden and Lizenberger in 1978 18 a large number of researchers have used options to extract Arrow Debreu prices for a variety of applications in financial economics 19 Accounting for the existence of money edit No theory of money is offered here and it is assumed that the economy works without the help of a good serving as medium of exchange Gerard Debreu Theory of value An axiomatic analysis of economic equilibrium 1959 To the pure theorist at the present juncture the most interesting and challenging aspect of money is that it can find no place in an Arrow Debreu economy This circumstance should also be of considerable significance to macroeconomists but it rarely is Frank Hahn The foundations of monetary theory 1987 Typically economists consider the functions of money to be as a unit of account store of value medium of exchange and standard of deferred payment This is however incompatible with the Arrow Debreu complete market described above In the complete market there is only a one time transaction at the market at the beginning of time After that households and producers merely execute their planned productions consumptions and deliveries of commodities until the end of time Consequently there is no use for storage of value or medium of exchange This applies not just to the Arrow Debreu complete market but also to models such as those with markets of contingent commodities and Arrow insurance contracts that differ in form but are mathematically equivalent to it 20 Computing general equilibria edit Main article Computable general equilibrium Scarf 1967 21 was the first algorithm that computes the general equilibrium See Scarf 2018 22 and Kubler 2012 23 for reviews Number of equilibria edit See also General equilibrium theory Uniqueness Certain economies at certain endowment vectors may have infinitely equilibrium price vectors However generically an economy has only finitely many equilibrium price vectors Here generically means on all points except a closed set of Lebesgue measure zero as in Sard s theorem 24 25 There are many such genericity theorems One example is the following 26 27 Genericity For any strictly positive endowment distribution r 1 r I R N displaystyle r 1 r I in mathbb R N nbsp and any strictly positive price vector p R N displaystyle p in mathbb R N nbsp define the excess demand Z p r 1 r I displaystyle Z p r 1 r I nbsp as before If on all p r 1 r I R N displaystyle p r 1 r I in mathbb R N nbsp Z p r 1 r I displaystyle Z p r 1 r I nbsp is well defined Z displaystyle Z nbsp is differentiable p Z displaystyle nabla p Z nbsp has N 1 displaystyle N 1 nbsp then for generically any endowment distribution r 1 r I R N displaystyle r 1 r I in mathbb R N nbsp there are only finitely many equilibria p R N displaystyle p in mathbb R N nbsp Proof sketch Define the equilibrium manifold as the set of solutions to Z 0 displaystyle Z 0 nbsp By Walras s law one of the constraints is redundant By assumptions that p Z displaystyle nabla p Z nbsp has rank N 1 displaystyle N 1 nbsp no more constraints are redundant Thus the equilibrium manifold has dimension N I displaystyle N times I nbsp which is equal to the space of all distributions of strictly positive endowments R N I displaystyle mathbb R N times I nbsp By continuity of Z displaystyle Z nbsp the projection is closed Thus by Sard s theorem the projection from the equilibrium manifold to R N I displaystyle mathbb R N times I nbsp is critical on only a set of measure 0 It remains to check that the preimage of the projection is generically not just discrete but also finite See also editModel economics Incomplete markets Fisher market a simpler market model in which the total quantity of each product is given and each buyer comes only with a monetary budget List of asset pricing articles Financial economics Underlying economicsReferences edit a b Arrow K J Debreu G 1954 Existence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy Econometrica 22 3 265 290 doi 10 2307 1907353 JSTOR 1907353 McKenzie Lionel W 1954 On Equilibrium in Graham s Model of World Trade and Other Competitive Systems Econometrica 22 2 147 161 doi 10 2307 1907539 JSTOR 1907539 McKenzie Lionel W 1959 On the Existence of General Equilibrium for a Competitive Economy Econometrica 27 1 54 71 doi 10 2307 1907777 JSTOR 1907777 a hre, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.