fbpx
Wikipedia

Relativist fallacy

The relativist fallacy, also known as the subjectivist fallacy, is claiming that something is true for one person but not true for someone else, when in fact that thing is an objective fact. The fallacy rests on the law of noncontradiction. The fallacy applies only to objective facts, or what are alleged to be objective facts, rather than to facts about personal tastes or subjective experiences, and only to facts regarded in the same sense and at the same time.

Interpretations edit

There are at least two ways to interpret the relativist fallacy: either as identical to relativism (generally), or as the ad hoc adoption of a relativist stance purely to defend a controversial position.

On the one hand, discussions of the relativist fallacy that portray it as identical to relativism (e.g., linguistic relativism or cultural relativism) are themselves committing a commonly identified fallacy of informal logic—namely, begging the question against an earnest, intelligent, logically competent relativist. It is itself a fallacy to describe a controversial view as a "fallacy"—not, at least, without arguing that it is a fallacy. In any event, it does not do to argue as follows:

  1. To advocate relativism, even some sophisticated relativism, is to commit the relativist fallacy.
  2. If one commits a fallacy, one says something false or not worth serious consideration.
  3. Therefore, to advocate relativism, even some sophisticated relativism, is to say something false or not worth serious consideration.

This is an example of circular reasoning. The second step includes an argument from fallacy.

On the other hand, if someone adopts a simple relativist stance as an ad hoc defense of a controversial or otherwise compromised position—saying, in effect, that "what is true for you is not necessarily true for me," and thereby attempting to avoid having to mount any further defense of the position—one might be said to have committed a fallacy. The accusation of having committed a fallacy might rest on either of two grounds: (1) the relativism on which the bogus defense rests is so simple and meritless that it straightforwardly contradicts the law of noncontradiction; or (2) the defense (and thus the fallacy itself) is an example of ad hoc reasoning. It puts one in the position of asserting or implying that truth or standards of logical consistency are relative to a particular thinker or group and that under some other standard, the position is correct despite its failure to stand up to logic.

Determining whether someone has committed a relativist fallacy—by any interpretation—requires distinguishing between things that are true for a particular person, and things that are true about that person. Take, for example, the statement proffered by Alice: "More Americans than ever are overweight." One may introduce arguments for and against this proposition, based upon such things as standards of statistical analysis, the definition of "overweight," etc. The position answers to objective logical debate. If Bob answers Alice, saying "That may be true for you, but it is not true for me," he has given an answer that is fallacious as well as somewhat meaningless in the context of Alice's original statement.

Conversely, take the new statement by Alice, who is 5 feet 6 inches (1.68 m) tall, "270 pounds (120 kg) is grossly overweight." Bob, who is 6 feet 6 inches (1.98 m), and weighs an exact, well-conditioned 270 pounds (120 kg), replies, "That may be true for you, but it is not true for me." In this context, Bob's reply is both meaningful and arguably accurate. As he is discussing something that is true about himself, he is not barred from making an argument that considers subjective facts, and so he does not commit the fallacy.

See also edit

References edit

  • Law, Stephen (2005) Thinking Tools: The Relativist Fallacy, Think: Philosophy for everyone (A journal of the Royal Institute of Philosophy) 3: 57-58 y
  • Dowden, Bradley (2010). "Subjectivist fallacy". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 26 January 2020.

relativist, fallacy, this, article, multiple, issues, please, help, improve, discuss, these, issues, talk, page, learn, when, remove, these, template, messages, this, article, includes, list, general, references, lacks, sufficient, corresponding, inline, citat. This article has multiple issues Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page Learn how and when to remove these template messages This article includes a list of general references but it lacks sufficient corresponding inline citations Please help to improve this article by introducing more precise citations July 2014 Learn how and when to remove this template message This article needs additional citations for verification Please help improve this article by adding citations to reliable sources Unsourced material may be challenged and removed Find sources Relativist fallacy news newspapers books scholar JSTOR June 2014 Learn how and when to remove this template message Learn how and when to remove this template message The relativist fallacy also known as the subjectivist fallacy is claiming that something is true for one person but not true for someone else when in fact that thing is an objective fact The fallacy rests on the law of noncontradiction The fallacy applies only to objective facts or what are alleged to be objective facts rather than to facts about personal tastes or subjective experiences and only to facts regarded in the same sense and at the same time Interpretations editThere are at least two ways to interpret the relativist fallacy either as identical to relativism generally or as the ad hoc adoption of a relativist stance purely to defend a controversial position On the one hand discussions of the relativist fallacy that portray it as identical to relativism e g linguistic relativism or cultural relativism are themselves committing a commonly identified fallacy of informal logic namely begging the question against an earnest intelligent logically competent relativist It is itself a fallacy to describe a controversial view as a fallacy not at least without arguing that it is a fallacy In any event it does not do to argue as follows To advocate relativism even some sophisticated relativism is to commit the relativist fallacy If one commits a fallacy one says something false or not worth serious consideration Therefore to advocate relativism even some sophisticated relativism is to say something false or not worth serious consideration This is an example of circular reasoning The second step includes an argument from fallacy On the other hand if someone adopts a simple relativist stance as an ad hoc defense of a controversial or otherwise compromised position saying in effect that what is true for you is not necessarily true for me and thereby attempting to avoid having to mount any further defense of the position one might be said to have committed a fallacy The accusation of having committed a fallacy might rest on either of two grounds 1 the relativism on which the bogus defense rests is so simple and meritless that it straightforwardly contradicts the law of noncontradiction or 2 the defense and thus the fallacy itself is an example of ad hoc reasoning It puts one in the position of asserting or implying that truth or standards of logical consistency are relative to a particular thinker or group and that under some other standard the position is correct despite its failure to stand up to logic Determining whether someone has committed a relativist fallacy by any interpretation requires distinguishing between things that are true for a particular person and things that are true about that person Take for example the statement proffered by Alice More Americans than ever are overweight One may introduce arguments for and against this proposition based upon such things as standards of statistical analysis the definition of overweight etc The position answers to objective logical debate If Bob answers Alice saying That may be true for you but it is not true for me he has given an answer that is fallacious as well as somewhat meaningless in the context of Alice s original statement Conversely take the new statement by Alice who is 5 feet 6 inches 1 68 m tall 270 pounds 120 kg is grossly overweight Bob who is 6 feet 6 inches 1 98 m and weighs an exact well conditioned 270 pounds 120 kg replies That may be true for you but it is not true for me In this context Bob s reply is both meaningful and arguably accurate As he is discussing something that is true about himself he is not barred from making an argument that considers subjective facts and so he does not commit the fallacy See also editI m entitled to my opinion Special pleading Informal fallacyReferences editLaw Stephen 2005 Thinking Tools The Relativist Fallacy Think Philosophy for everyone A journal of the Royal Institute of Philosophy 3 57 58 y Dowden Bradley 2010 Subjectivist fallacy Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved 26 January 2020 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Relativist fallacy amp oldid 1193058374, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.