fbpx
Wikipedia

Ramsey sentence

Ramsey sentences are formal logical reconstructions of theoretical propositions attempting to draw a line between science and metaphysics. A Ramsey sentence aims at rendering propositions containing non-observable theoretical terms (terms employed by a theoretical language) clear by substituting them with observational terms (terms employed by an observation language, also called empirical language).

Ramsey sentences were introduced by the logical empiricist philosopher Rudolf Carnap. However, they should not be confused with Carnap sentences, which are neutral on whether there exists anything to which the term applies. [1]

Distinction between scientific (real) questions and metaphysical (pseudo-)questions edit

For Carnap, questions such as “Are electrons real?” and “Can you prove electrons are real?” were not legitimate questions, nor did they contain any great philosophical or metaphysical truths. Rather, they were meaningless "pseudo-questions without cognitive content,” asked from outside a language framework of science. Inside this framework, entities such as electrons or sound waves, and relations such as mass and force not only exist and have meaning but are "useful" to the scientists who work with them. To accommodate such internal questions in a way that would justify their theoretical content empirically – and to do so while maintaining a distinction between analytic and synthetic propositions – Carnap set out to develop a systematized way to consolidate theory and empirical observation in a meaningful language formula.

Distinction between observable and non-observable edit

Carnap began by differentiating observable things from non-observable things. Immediately, a problem arises: neither the German nor the English language naturally distinguish predicate terms on the basis of an observational categorization. As Carnap admitted, "The line separating observable from non-observable is highly arbitrary." For example, the predicate "hot" can be perceived by touching a hand to a lighted coal. But "hot" might take place at such a microlevel (e.g., the theoretical "heat" generated by the production of proteins in a eukaryotic cell) that it is virtually non-observable (at present). Physicist-philosopher Moritz Schlick characterized the difference linguistically, as the difference between the German verbs "kennen" (knowing as being acquainted with a thing – perception) and "erkennen" (knowing as understanding a thing – even if non-observable). This linguistic distinction may explain Carnap's decision to divide the vocabulary into two artificial categories: a vocabulary of non-observable ("theoretical") terms (hereafter "VT"): i.e., terms we know of but are not acquainted with (erkennen), and a vocabulary of observable terms ("VO"), those terms we are acquainted with (kennen) and will accept arbitrarily. Accordingly, the terms thus distinguished were incorporated into comparable sentence structures: T-terms into theoretical sentences (T-sentences); O-terms into observational sentences (O-sentences).

The next step for Carnap was to connect these separate concepts by what he calls "correspondence rules" (C-rules), which are "mixed" sentences containing both T- and O-terms. Such a theory can be formulated as: T + C = df: the conjunction of T-postulates + the conjunction of C-rules – i.e.,  . This can be further expanded to include class terms such as for the class of all molecules, relations such as "betweenness," and predicates: e.g., TC ( t1, t2, . . ., tn, o1, o2, . . ., om). Though this enabled Carnap to establish what it means for a theory to be "empirical," this sentence neither defines the T-terms explicitly nor draws any distinction between its analytic and its synthetic content, therefore it was not yet sufficient for Carnap's purposes.

In the theories of Frank P. Ramsey, Carnap found the method he needed to take the next step, which was to substitute variables for each T-term, then to quantify existentially all T-terms in both T-sentences and C-rules. The resulting "Ramsey sentence" effectively eliminated the T-terms as such, while still providing an account of the theory's empirical content. The evolution of the formula proceeds thus:

Step 1 (empirical theory, assumed true): TC ( t1 . . . tn, o1 . . . om)
Step 2 (substitution of variables for T-terms): TC (x1 . . . xn, o1 . . . om)
Step 3 ( -quantification of the variables):  .

Step 3 is the complete Ramsey sentence, expressed "RTC," and to be read: "There are some (unspecified) relations such that TC (x1 . . . xn, o1 . . . om) is satisfied when the variables are assigned these relations. (This is equivalent to an interpretation as an appropriate model: there are relations r1 . . . rn such that TC (x1 . . . xn, o1 . . . om) is satisfied when xi is assigned the value ri, and  .)

In this form, the Ramsey sentence captures the factual content of the theory. Though Ramsey believed this formulation was adequate to the needs of science, Carnap disagreed, with regard to a comprehensive reconstruction. In order to delineate a distinction between analytic and synthetic content, Carnap thought the reconstructed sentence would have to satisfy three desired requirements:

  1. The factual (FT) component must be observationally equivalent to the original theory (TC).
  2. The analytic (AT) component must be observationally uninformative.
  3. The combination of FT and AT must be logically equivalent to the original theory – that is,  .

Requirement 1 is satisfied by RTC in that the existential quantification of the T-terms does not change the logical truth (L-truth) of either statement, and the reconstruction FT has the same O-sentences as the theory itself, hence RTC is observationally equivalent to TC : (i.e., for every O-sentence: O,   ). As stated, however, requirements 2 and 3 remain unsatisfied. That is, taken individually, AT does contain observational information (such-and-such a theoretical entity is observed to do such-and-such, or hold such-and-such a relation); and AT does not necessarily follow from FT.

Carnap's solution is to make the two statements conditional. If there are some relations such that [TC (x1 . . . xn, o1 . . . om)] is satisfied when the variables are assigned some relations, then the relations assigned to those variables by the original theory will satisfy [TC (t1 . . . tn, o1 . . . om)] – or: RTC → TC. This important move satisfies both remaining requirements and effectively creates a distinction between the total formula's analytic and synthetic components. Specifically, for requirement 2: The conditional sentence does not make any information claim about the O-sentences in TC, it states only that "if" the variables in are satisfied by the relations, "then" the O-sentences will be true. This means that every O-sentence in TC that is logically implied by the sentence RTC → TC is L-true (i.e., every O-sentence in AT is true or not-true: the metal expands or it does not; the chemical turns blue or it does not, etc.). Thus TC can be taken as the non-informative (i.e., non-factual) component of the statement, or AT. Requirement 3 is satisfied by inference: given AT, infer FT → AT. This makes AT + FT nothing more than a reformulation of the original theory, hence AT Ù FT ó TC.

Carnap took as a fundamental requirement a respect for the analytic–synthetic distinction. This is met by using two distinct processes in the formulation: drawing an empirical connection between the statement's factual content and the original theory (observational equivalence), and by requiring the analytic content to be observationally non-informative.

Application edit

Carnap's reconstruction as it is given here is not intended to be a literal method for formulating scientific propositions. To capture what Pierre Duhem would call the entire "holistic" universe relating to any specified theory would require long and complicated renderings of RTC → TC. Instead, it is to be taken as demonstrating logically that there is a way that science could formulate empirical, observational explications of theoretical concepts – and in that context the Ramsey and Carnap construct can be said to provide a formal justificatory distinction between scientific observation and metaphysical inquiry.

Criticism edit

Among critics of the Ramsey formalism are John Winnie, who extended the requirements to include an "observationally non-creative" restriction on Carnap's AT – and both W. V. O. Quine and Carl Hempel attacked Carnap's initial assumptions by emphasizing the ambiguity that persists between observable and non-observable terms.

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ David Lewis (1970). "How to Define Theoretical Terms". The Journal of Philosophy. 67 (13): 427–446. doi:10.2307/2023861. JSTOR 2023861.

Works cited edit

  • Carnap, R. (1950) "Empiricism, Semantics, and Ontology," in Paul Moser and Arnold Nat, Human Knowledge Oxford University Press. (2003).
  • Carnap, R. (1966) An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science (esp. Parts III, and V), ed. Martin Gardner. Dover Publications, New York. 1995.
  • Carnap, R. (2000) [originally: 29 December 1959] "Theoretical Concepts in Science," with introduction by Stathis Psillos. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 31(1).
  • Demopoulos, W. "Carnap on the Reconstruction of Scientific Theories," The Cambridge Companion to Carnap, eds. R. Creath and M. Friedman.
  • Moser, P. K. and vander Nat, A. (2003) Human Knowledge Oxford Univ. Press.
  • Schlick, Moritz (1918) General Theory of Knowledge (Allegemeine Erkenntnislehre). Trans. Albert Blumberg. Open Court Publishing, Chicago/La Salle, IL. (2002).
  • Hallvard Lillehammer, D. H. Mellor (2005), Ramsey's legacy, Oxford University Press, p. 109.
  • Stathis Psillos, "Carnap, the Ramsey-Sentence and Realistic Empiricism", 2000.

External links edit

  • "Epistemic Structural Realism and Ramsey Sentences"
  • "Theoretical Terms in Science"

ramsey, sentence, formal, logical, reconstructions, theoretical, propositions, attempting, draw, line, between, science, metaphysics, aims, rendering, propositions, containing, observable, theoretical, terms, terms, employed, theoretical, language, clear, subs. Ramsey sentences are formal logical reconstructions of theoretical propositions attempting to draw a line between science and metaphysics A Ramsey sentence aims at rendering propositions containing non observable theoretical terms terms employed by a theoretical language clear by substituting them with observational terms terms employed by an observation language also called empirical language Ramsey sentences were introduced by the logical empiricist philosopher Rudolf Carnap However they should not be confused with Carnap sentences which are neutral on whether there exists anything to which the term applies 1 Contents 1 Distinction between scientific real questions and metaphysical pseudo questions 2 Distinction between observable and non observable 3 Application 4 Criticism 5 See also 6 Notes 7 Works cited 8 External linksDistinction between scientific real questions and metaphysical pseudo questions editFor Carnap questions such as Are electrons real and Can you prove electrons are real were not legitimate questions nor did they contain any great philosophical or metaphysical truths Rather they were meaningless pseudo questions without cognitive content asked from outside a language framework of science Inside this framework entities such as electrons or sound waves and relations such as mass and force not only exist and have meaning but are useful to the scientists who work with them To accommodate such internal questions in a way that would justify their theoretical content empirically and to do so while maintaining a distinction between analytic and synthetic propositions Carnap set out to develop a systematized way to consolidate theory and empirical observation in a meaningful language formula Distinction between observable and non observable editCarnap began by differentiating observable things from non observable things Immediately a problem arises neither the German nor the English language naturally distinguish predicate terms on the basis of an observational categorization As Carnap admitted The line separating observable from non observable is highly arbitrary For example the predicate hot can be perceived by touching a hand to a lighted coal But hot might take place at such a microlevel e g the theoretical heat generated by the production of proteins in a eukaryotic cell that it is virtually non observable at present Physicist philosopher Moritz Schlick characterized the difference linguistically as the difference between the German verbs kennen knowing as being acquainted with a thing perception and erkennen knowing as understanding a thing even if non observable This linguistic distinction may explain Carnap s decision to divide the vocabulary into two artificial categories a vocabulary of non observable theoretical terms hereafter VT i e terms we know of but are not acquainted with erkennen and a vocabulary of observable terms VO those terms we are acquainted with kennen and will accept arbitrarily Accordingly the terms thus distinguished were incorporated into comparable sentence structures T terms into theoretical sentences T sentences O terms into observational sentences O sentences The next step for Carnap was to connect these separate concepts by what he calls correspondence rules C rules which are mixed sentences containing both T and O terms Such a theory can be formulated as T C df the conjunction of T postulates the conjunction of C rules i e T 1 T 2 T n C 1 C 2 C m displaystyle T 1 land T 2 land cdots land T n C 1 land C 2 land cdots land C m nbsp This can be further expanded to include class terms such as for the class of all molecules relations such as betweenness and predicates e g TC t1 t2 tn o1 o2 om Though this enabled Carnap to establish what it means for a theory to be empirical this sentence neither defines the T terms explicitly nor draws any distinction between its analytic and its synthetic content therefore it was not yet sufficient for Carnap s purposes In the theories of Frank P Ramsey Carnap found the method he needed to take the next step which was to substitute variables for each T term then to quantify existentially all T terms in both T sentences and C rules The resulting Ramsey sentence effectively eliminated the T terms as such while still providing an account of the theory s empirical content The evolution of the formula proceeds thus Step 1 empirical theory assumed true TC t1 tn o1 om Step 2 substitution of variables for T terms TC x1 xn o1 om Step 3 displaystyle exists nbsp quantification of the variables x 1 x n T C x 1 x n o 1 o m displaystyle exists x 1 ldots exists x n TC x 1 ldots x n o 1 ldots o m nbsp Step 3 is the complete Ramsey sentence expressed RTC and to be read There are some unspecified relations such that TC x1 xn o1 om is satisfied when the variables are assigned these relations This is equivalent to an interpretation as an appropriate model there are relations r1 rn such that TC x1 xn o1 om is satisfied when xi is assigned the value ri and 1 i m displaystyle 1 leq i leq m nbsp In this form the Ramsey sentence captures the factual content of the theory Though Ramsey believed this formulation was adequate to the needs of science Carnap disagreed with regard to a comprehensive reconstruction In order to delineate a distinction between analytic and synthetic content Carnap thought the reconstructed sentence would have to satisfy three desired requirements The factual FT component must be observationally equivalent to the original theory TC The analytic AT component must be observationally uninformative The combination of FT and AT must be logically equivalent to the original theory that is F T A T T C displaystyle F T A T Leftrightarrow TC nbsp Requirement 1 is satisfied by RTC in that the existential quantification of the T terms does not change the logical truth L truth of either statement and the reconstruction FT has the same O sentences as the theory itself hence RTC is observationally equivalent to TC i e for every O sentence O T C O R T C O displaystyle TC models O Leftrightarrow R TC models O nbsp As stated however requirements 2 and 3 remain unsatisfied That is taken individually AT does contain observational information such and such a theoretical entity is observed to do such and such or hold such and such a relation and AT does not necessarily follow from FT Carnap s solution is to make the two statements conditional If there are some relations such that TC x1 xn o1 om is satisfied when the variables are assigned some relations then the relations assigned to those variables by the original theory will satisfy TC t1 tn o1 om or RTC TC This important move satisfies both remaining requirements and effectively creates a distinction between the total formula s analytic and synthetic components Specifically for requirement 2 The conditional sentence does not make any information claim about the O sentences in TC it states only that if the variables in are satisfied by the relations then the O sentences will be true This means that every O sentence in TC that is logically implied by the sentence RTC TC is L true i e every O sentence in AT is true or not true the metal expands or it does not the chemical turns blue or it does not etc Thus TC can be taken as the non informative i e non factual component of the statement or AT Requirement 3 is satisfied by inference given AT infer FT AT This makes AT FT nothing more than a reformulation of the original theory hence AT U FT o TC Carnap took as a fundamental requirement a respect for the analytic synthetic distinction This is met by using two distinct processes in the formulation drawing an empirical connection between the statement s factual content and the original theory observational equivalence and by requiring the analytic content to be observationally non informative Application editCarnap s reconstruction as it is given here is not intended to be a literal method for formulating scientific propositions To capture what Pierre Duhem would call the entire holistic universe relating to any specified theory would require long and complicated renderings of RTC TC Instead it is to be taken as demonstrating logically that there is a way that science could formulate empirical observational explications of theoretical concepts and in that context the Ramsey and Carnap construct can be said to provide a formal justificatory distinction between scientific observation and metaphysical inquiry Criticism editAmong critics of the Ramsey formalism are John Winnie who extended the requirements to include an observationally non creative restriction on Carnap s AT and both W V O Quine and Carl Hempel attacked Carnap s initial assumptions by emphasizing the ambiguity that persists between observable and non observable terms See also editRamsey style epistemic structural realismNotes edit David Lewis 1970 How to Define Theoretical Terms The Journal of Philosophy 67 13 427 446 doi 10 2307 2023861 JSTOR 2023861 Works cited editCarnap R 1950 Empiricism Semantics and Ontology in Paul Moser and Arnold Nat Human Knowledge Oxford University Press 2003 Carnap R 1966 An Introduction to the Philosophy of Science esp Parts III and V ed Martin Gardner Dover Publications New York 1995 Carnap R 2000 originally 29 December 1959 Theoretical Concepts in Science with introduction by Stathis Psillos Studies in History and Philosophy of Science 31 1 Demopoulos W Carnap on the Reconstruction of Scientific Theories The Cambridge Companion to Carnap eds R Creath and M Friedman Moser P K and vander Nat A 2003 Human Knowledge Oxford Univ Press Schlick Moritz 1918 General Theory of Knowledge Allegemeine Erkenntnislehre Trans Albert Blumberg Open Court Publishing Chicago La Salle IL 2002 Hallvard Lillehammer D H Mellor 2005 Ramsey s legacy Oxford University Press p 109 Stathis Psillos Carnap the Ramsey Sentence and Realistic Empiricism 2000 External links edit Epistemic Structural Realism and Ramsey Sentences Theoretical Terms in Science Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Ramsey sentence amp oldid 1142059741, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.