fbpx
Wikipedia

Meno

Meno (/ˈmn/; Greek: Μένων, Ménōn) is a Socratic dialogue written by Plato. Meno begins the dialogue by asking Socrates whether virtue is taught, acquired by practice, or comes by nature.[1] In order to determine whether virtue is teachable or not, Socrates tells Meno that they first need to determine what virtue is. When the characters speak of virtue, or rather arete, they refer to virtue in general, rather than particular virtues, such as justice or temperance. The first part of the work showcases Socratic dialectical style; Meno, unable to adequately define virtue, is reduced to confusion or aporia.[2] Socrates suggests that they seek an adequate definition for virtue together. In response, Meno suggests that it is impossible to seek what one does not know, because one will be unable to determine whether one has found it.[3]

Socrates challenges Meno's argument, often called "Meno's Paradox" or the "Learner's Paradox", by introducing the theory of knowledge as recollection (anamnesis). As presented in the dialogue, the theory proposes that souls are immortal and know all things in a disembodied state; learning in the embodied is actually a process of recollecting that which the soul knew before it came into a body.[4] Socrates demonstrates recollection in action by posing a mathematical puzzle to one of Meno's slaves.[5] Subsequently, Socrates and Meno return to the question of whether virtue is teachable, employing the method of hypothesis. Near the end of the dialogue, Meno poses another famous puzzle, called "The Meno Problem" or "The Value Problem for Knowledge", which questions why knowledge is valued more highly than true belief.[6] In response, Socrates provides a famous and somewhat enigmatic distinction between knowledge and true belief.[7]

Characters edit

Plato's Meno is a Socratic dialogue in which the two main speakers, Socrates and Meno (also transliterated as "Menon"), discuss human virtue: what it is, and whether or not it can be taught. Meno is visiting Athens from Thessaly with a large entourage of slaves attending him. Young, good-looking and well-born, he is a student of Gorgias, a prominent sophist whose views on virtue clearly influence that of Meno's. Early in the dialogue, Meno claims that he has held forth many times on the subject of virtue, and in front of large audiences.

One of Meno's slaves also has a speaking role, as one of the features of the dialogue is Socrates' use of the slave to demonstrate his idea of anamnesis: certain knowledge is innate and "recollected" by the soul through proper inquiry.

Another participant in the dialogue is Athenian politician Anytus, a prosecutor of Socrates with whom Meno is friendly.

Dialogue edit

Introduction of virtue edit

The dialogue begins with Meno asking Socrates to tell him if virtue can be taught. Socrates says that he does not know what virtue is, and neither does anyone else he knows.[8] Meno responds that, according to Gorgias, virtue is different for different people, that what is virtuous for a man is to conduct himself in the city so that he helps his friends, injures his enemies, and takes care all the while that he personally comes to no harm. Virtue is different for a woman, he says. Her domain is the management of the household, and she is supposed to obey her husband. He says that children (male and female) have their own proper virtue, and so do old men—free or slaves.[9] Socrates objects: there must be some virtue common to all human beings.

Socrates rejects the idea that human virtue depends on a person's sex or age. He leads Meno towards the idea that virtues are common to all people, that sophrosunê ('temperance', i.e. exercise of self-control) and dikê (aka dikaiosunê; 'justice', i.e. refrain from harming others) are virtues even in children and old men.[10] Meno proposes to Socrates that the "capacity to govern men" may be a virtue common to all people. Socrates points out to the slaveholder that "governing well" cannot be a virtue of a slave, because then he would not be a slave.[11]

One of the errors that Socrates points out is that Meno lists many particular virtues without defining a common feature inherent to virtues which makes them thus. Socrates remarks that Meno makes many out of one, like somebody who breaks a plate.[12]

Meno proposes that virtue is the desire for good things and the power to get them. Socrates points out that this raises a second problem—many people do not recognize evil.[13] The discussion then turns to the question of accounting for the fact that so many people are mistaken about good and evil and take one for the other. Socrates asks Meno to consider whether good things must be acquired virtuously in order to be really good.[14] Socrates leads onto the question of whether virtue is one thing or many.

No satisfactory definition of virtue emerges in the Meno. Socrates' comments, however, show that he considers a successful definition to be unitary, rather than a list of varieties of virtue, that it must contain all and only those terms which are genuine instances of virtue, and must not be circular.[15]

Meno's paradox edit

Meno asks Socrates:[16][17]

And how will you enquire, Socrates, into that which you do not know? What will you put forth as the subject of enquiry? And if you find what you want, how will you ever know that this is the thing which you did not know?

Socrates rephrases the question, which has come to be the canonical statement of the paradox:[16][18]

[A] man cannot enquire either about that which he knows, or about that which he does not know; for if he knows, he has no need to enquire; and if not, he cannot; for he does not know the very subject about which he is to enquire.

— translated by Benjamin Jowett, 1871

Dialogue with Meno's slave edit

Socrates responds to this sophistical paradox with a mythos ('narrative' or 'fiction') according to which souls are immortal and have learned everything prior to transmigrating into the human body. Since the soul has had contact with real things prior to birth, we have only to 'recollect' them when alive. Such recollection requires Socratic questioning, which according to Socrates is not teaching. Socrates demonstrates his method of questioning and recollection by interrogating a slave who is ignorant of geometry.

Socrates begins one of the most influential dialogues of Western philosophy regarding the argument for inborn knowledge. By drawing geometric figures in the ground Socrates demonstrates that the slave is initially unaware of the length that a side must be in order to double the area of a square with 2-foot sides. The slave guesses first that the original side must be doubled in length (4 feet), and when this proves too much, that it must be 3 feet. This is still too much, and the slave is at a loss.

Socrates claims that before he got hold of him the slave (who has been picked at random from Meno's entourage) might have thought he could speak "well and fluently" on the subject of a square double the size of a given square.[19] Socrates comments that this "numbing" he caused in the slave has done him no harm and has even benefited him.[20]

 
The blue square is twice the area of the yellow square

Socrates then adds three more squares to the original square, to form a larger square four times the size. He draws four diagonal lines which bisect each of the smaller squares. Through questioning, Socrates leads the slave to the discovery that the square formed by these diagonals has an area of eight square feet, double that of the original. He says that the slave has "spontaneously recovered" knowledge he knew from a past life[21] without having been taught. Socrates is satisfied that new beliefs were "newly aroused" in the slave.

After witnessing the example with the slave boy, Meno tells Socrates that he thinks that Socrates is correct in his theory of recollection, to which Socrates agrees:[16][22]

Some things I have said of which I am not altogether confident. But that we shall be better and braver and less helpless if we think that we ought to enquire, than we should have been if we indulged in the idle fancy that there was no knowing and no use in seeking to know what we do not know; that is a theme upon which I am ready to fight, in word and deed, to the utmost of my power.

— translated by Benjamin Jowett, 1871

Anytus edit

Meno now beseeches Socrates to return to the original question, how virtue is acquired, and in particular, whether or not it is acquired by teaching or through life experience. Socrates proceeds on the hypothesis that virtue is knowledge, and it is quickly agreed that, if this is true, virtue is teachable. They turn to the question of whether virtue is indeed knowledge. Socrates is hesitant, because, if virtue were knowledge, there should be teachers and learners of it, but there are none.

Coincidentally Anytus appears, whom Socrates praises as the son of Anthemion, who earned his fortune with intelligence and hard work. He says that Anthemion had his son well-educated and so Anytus is well-suited to join the investigation. Socrates suggests that the sophists are teachers of virtue. Anytus is horrified, saying that he neither knows any, nor cares to know any. Socrates then questions why it is that men do not always produce sons of the same virtue as themselves. He alludes to other notable male figures, such as Themistocles, Aristides, Pericles and Thucydides, and casts doubt on whether these men produced sons as capable of virtue as themselves. Anytus becomes offended and accuses Socrates of slander, warning him to be careful expressing such opinions. (The historical Anytus was one of Socrates' accusers in his trial.) Socrates suggests that Anytus does not realize what slander is, and continues his dialogue with Meno as to the definition of virtue.

True belief and knowledge edit

After the discussion with Anytus, Socrates returns to quizzing Meno for his own thoughts on whether the sophists are teachers of virtue and whether virtue can be taught. Meno is again at a loss, and Socrates suggests that they have made a mistake in agreeing that knowledge is required for virtue. He points out the similarities and differences between "true belief" and "knowledge". True beliefs are as useful to us as knowledge, but they often fail to "stay in their place" and must be "tethered" by what he calls aitias logismos ('calculation of reason' or 'reasoned explanation'), immediately adding that this is anamnesis, or recollection.[23]

Whether or not Plato intends that the tethering of true beliefs with reasoned explanations must always involve anamnesis is explored in later interpretations of the text.[24][25] Socrates' distinction between "true belief" and "knowledge" forms the basis of the philosophical definition of knowledge as "justified true belief". Myles Burnyeat and others, however, have argued that the phrase aitias logismos refers to a practical working out of a solution, rather than a justification.[26]

Socrates concludes that, in the virtuous people of the present and the past, at least, virtue has been the result of divine inspiration, akin to the inspiration of the poets, whereas a knowledge of it will require answering the basic question, what is virtue?. In most modern readings these closing remarks are "evidently ironic",[27] but Socrates' invocation of the gods may be sincere, albeit "highly tentative".[28]

This passage in the Meno is often seen as the first statement of the problem of the value of knowledge: how is knowledge more valuable than mere true belief?[29] The nature of knowledge and belief is also discussed in the Thaetetus.

Meno and Protagoras edit

Meno's theme is also dealt with in the dialogue Protagoras, where Plato ultimately has Socrates arrive at the opposite conclusion: virtue can be taught. Likewise, while in Protagoras knowledge is uncompromisingly this-worldly, in Meno the theory of recollection points to a link between knowledge and eternal truths.[15]

Texts and translations edit

  • Meno, in a collection of Plato's Dialogues at Standard Ebooks
  • Jowett, Benjamin. 1871. "Meno." – via Internet Classics Archive. Project Gutenberg: 1643.
  • Lamb, W. R. M., trans. [1924] 1967. "Meno." Plato in Twelve Volumes 3. Cambridge, MA, Harvard University Press. ISBN 0-674-99183-4, 0-674-99184-2. – via Perseus Project.
  • Woods, Cathal, trans. 2011. "Meno." SSRN 1910945.

References edit

  1. ^ Plato, Meno, 70a
  2. ^ Plato, Meno, 80a-b
  3. ^ Plato, Meno, 80d
  4. ^ Plato, Meno, 81a-e
  5. ^ Plato, Meno, 82a-86c
  6. ^ Plato, Meno, 97b-d
  7. ^ Plato, Meno, 98a
  8. ^ Plato, Meno, 71b
  9. ^ Plato, Meno, 71e
  10. ^ Plato, Meno, 73b
  11. ^ Plato, Meno, 73c–d
  12. ^ Plato, Meno, 77a
  13. ^ Plato, Meno, 77d–e
  14. ^ Plato, Meno, 78b
  15. ^ a b Day, Jane Mary. 1994. Plato's Meno in Focus. Routledge. p. 19. ISBN 0-415-00297-4.
  16. ^ a b c Plato, Meno (translated by B. Jowett 1871).
  17. ^ Plato. [380 BC] 1976. Meno, translated by G. M. A. Grube. Indianapolis: Hackett. line 80d, p. 9.
  18. ^ Plato. [380 BC] 1976. Meno, translated by G. M. A. Grube. Indianapolis: Hackett. line 80e:

    "[A] man cannot search either for what he knows or for what he does not know; He cannot search for what he knows--since he knows it, there is no need to search--nor for what he does not know, for he does not know what to look for."

  19. ^ Plato, Meno, 84c
  20. ^ Plato, Meno, 84b
  21. ^ Plato, Meno, 85d
  22. ^ Plato, Meno, 86b
  23. ^ Vlastos, Gregory. 1996. Studies in Greek Philosophy: Socrates, Plato, and Their Tradition 2. Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-01938-X. p. 155.
  24. ^ Fine, Gail. 1992. "Inquiry in the 'Meno'." In The Cambridge Companion to Plato, edited by R. Kraut. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-43610-9. p. 221.
  25. ^ Kahn, Charles. 2006. "Plato on Recollection." In A Companion to Plato 37, edited by H. H. Benson. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 1-4051-1521-1. p. 122.
  26. ^ Fine, Gail. 2004. "Knowledge and True Belief in the Meno", Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 27(winter): 61–62, edited by D. Sedley. ISBN 0-19-927712-5.
  27. ^ Waterfield, Robin. 2005. Meno and Other Dialogues, (Oxford World Classics). Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-280425-1. pxliv.
  28. ^ Scott, Dominic. 2006. Plato's 'Meno' . Cambridge University Press. p 193. ISBN 0-521-64033-4.
  29. ^ Pritchard, Duncan, John Turri, and J. Adam Carter. [2007] 2018. "The Value of Knowledge" (revised). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.

Sources edit

External links edit

meno, this, article, about, plato, dialogue, thessalian, general, character, from, plato, dialogue, general, other, uses, disambiguation, this, article, relies, excessively, references, primary, sources, please, improve, this, article, adding, secondary, terti. This article is about Plato s dialogue For the Thessalian general and character from Plato s dialogue see Meno general For other uses see Meno disambiguation This article relies excessively on references to primary sources Please improve this article by adding secondary or tertiary sources Find sources Meno news newspapers books scholar JSTOR November 2022 Learn how and when to remove this template message You can help expand this article with text translated from the corresponding article in German October 2023 Click show for important translation instructions View a machine translated version of the German article Machine translation like DeepL or Google Translate is a useful starting point for translations but translators must revise errors as necessary and confirm that the translation is accurate rather than simply copy pasting machine translated text into the English Wikipedia Consider adding a topic to this template there are already 9 112 articles in the main category and specifying topic will aid in categorization Do not translate text that appears unreliable or low quality If possible verify the text with references provided in the foreign language article You must provide copyright attribution in the edit summary accompanying your translation by providing an interlanguage link to the source of your translation A model attribution edit summary is Content in this edit is translated from the existing German Wikipedia article at de Menon see its history for attribution You should also add the template Translated de Menon to the talk page For more guidance see Wikipedia Translation Meno ˈ m iː n oʊ Greek Menwn Menōn is a Socratic dialogue written by Plato Meno begins the dialogue by asking Socrates whether virtue is taught acquired by practice or comes by nature 1 In order to determine whether virtue is teachable or not Socrates tells Meno that they first need to determine what virtue is When the characters speak of virtue or rather arete they refer to virtue in general rather than particular virtues such as justice or temperance The first part of the work showcases Socratic dialectical style Meno unable to adequately define virtue is reduced to confusion or aporia 2 Socrates suggests that they seek an adequate definition for virtue together In response Meno suggests that it is impossible to seek what one does not know because one will be unable to determine whether one has found it 3 Socrates challenges Meno s argument often called Meno s Paradox or the Learner s Paradox by introducing the theory of knowledge as recollection anamnesis As presented in the dialogue the theory proposes that souls are immortal and know all things in a disembodied state learning in the embodied is actually a process of recollecting that which the soul knew before it came into a body 4 Socrates demonstrates recollection in action by posing a mathematical puzzle to one of Meno s slaves 5 Subsequently Socrates and Meno return to the question of whether virtue is teachable employing the method of hypothesis Near the end of the dialogue Meno poses another famous puzzle called The Meno Problem or The Value Problem for Knowledge which questions why knowledge is valued more highly than true belief 6 In response Socrates provides a famous and somewhat enigmatic distinction between knowledge and true belief 7 Contents 1 Characters 2 Dialogue 2 1 Introduction of virtue 2 2 Meno s paradox 2 3 Dialogue with Meno s slave 2 4 Anytus 2 5 True belief and knowledge 3 Meno and Protagoras 4 Texts and translations 5 References 5 1 Sources 6 External linksCharacters editPlato s Meno is a Socratic dialogue in which the two main speakers Socrates and Meno also transliterated as Menon discuss human virtue what it is and whether or not it can be taught Meno is visiting Athens from Thessaly with a large entourage of slaves attending him Young good looking and well born he is a student of Gorgias a prominent sophist whose views on virtue clearly influence that of Meno s Early in the dialogue Meno claims that he has held forth many times on the subject of virtue and in front of large audiences One of Meno s slaves also has a speaking role as one of the features of the dialogue is Socrates use of the slave to demonstrate his idea of anamnesis certain knowledge is innate and recollected by the soul through proper inquiry Another participant in the dialogue is Athenian politician Anytus a prosecutor of Socrates with whom Meno is friendly Dialogue editIntroduction of virtue edit The dialogue begins with Meno asking Socrates to tell him if virtue can be taught Socrates says that he does not know what virtue is and neither does anyone else he knows 8 Meno responds that according to Gorgias virtue is different for different people that what is virtuous for a man is to conduct himself in the city so that he helps his friends injures his enemies and takes care all the while that he personally comes to no harm Virtue is different for a woman he says Her domain is the management of the household and she is supposed to obey her husband He says that children male and female have their own proper virtue and so do old men free or slaves 9 Socrates objects there must be some virtue common to all human beings Socrates rejects the idea that human virtue depends on a person s sex or age He leads Meno towards the idea that virtues are common to all people that sophrosune temperance i e exercise of self control and dike aka dikaiosune justice i e refrain from harming others are virtues even in children and old men 10 Meno proposes to Socrates that the capacity to govern men may be a virtue common to all people Socrates points out to the slaveholder that governing well cannot be a virtue of a slave because then he would not be a slave 11 One of the errors that Socrates points out is that Meno lists many particular virtues without defining a common feature inherent to virtues which makes them thus Socrates remarks that Meno makes many out of one like somebody who breaks a plate 12 Meno proposes that virtue is the desire for good things and the power to get them Socrates points out that this raises a second problem many people do not recognize evil 13 The discussion then turns to the question of accounting for the fact that so many people are mistaken about good and evil and take one for the other Socrates asks Meno to consider whether good things must be acquired virtuously in order to be really good 14 Socrates leads onto the question of whether virtue is one thing or many No satisfactory definition of virtue emerges in the Meno Socrates comments however show that he considers a successful definition to be unitary rather than a list of varieties of virtue that it must contain all and only those terms which are genuine instances of virtue and must not be circular 15 Meno s paradox editMeno asks Socrates 16 17 And how will you enquire Socrates into that which you do not know What will you put forth as the subject of enquiry And if you find what you want how will you ever know that this is the thing which you did not know Socrates rephrases the question which has come to be the canonical statement of the paradox 16 18 A man cannot enquire either about that which he knows or about that which he does not know for if he knows he has no need to enquire and if not he cannot for he does not know the very subject about which he is to enquire translated by Benjamin Jowett 1871 Dialogue with Meno s slave edit Socrates responds to this sophistical paradox with a mythos narrative or fiction according to which souls are immortal and have learned everything prior to transmigrating into the human body Since the soul has had contact with real things prior to birth we have only to recollect them when alive Such recollection requires Socratic questioning which according to Socrates is not teaching Socrates demonstrates his method of questioning and recollection by interrogating a slave who is ignorant of geometry Socrates begins one of the most influential dialogues of Western philosophy regarding the argument for inborn knowledge By drawing geometric figures in the ground Socrates demonstrates that the slave is initially unaware of the length that a side must be in order to double the area of a square with 2 foot sides The slave guesses first that the original side must be doubled in length 4 feet and when this proves too much that it must be 3 feet This is still too much and the slave is at a loss Socrates claims that before he got hold of him the slave who has been picked at random from Meno s entourage might have thought he could speak well and fluently on the subject of a square double the size of a given square 19 Socrates comments that this numbing he caused in the slave has done him no harm and has even benefited him 20 nbsp The blue square is twice the area of the yellow square Socrates then adds three more squares to the original square to form a larger square four times the size He draws four diagonal lines which bisect each of the smaller squares Through questioning Socrates leads the slave to the discovery that the square formed by these diagonals has an area of eight square feet double that of the original He says that the slave has spontaneously recovered knowledge he knew from a past life 21 without having been taught Socrates is satisfied that new beliefs were newly aroused in the slave After witnessing the example with the slave boy Meno tells Socrates that he thinks that Socrates is correct in his theory of recollection to which Socrates agrees 16 22 Some things I have said of which I am not altogether confident But that we shall be better and braver and less helpless if we think that we ought to enquire than we should have been if we indulged in the idle fancy that there was no knowing and no use in seeking to know what we do not know that is a theme upon which I am ready to fight in word and deed to the utmost of my power translated by Benjamin Jowett 1871 Anytus edit Meno now beseeches Socrates to return to the original question how virtue is acquired and in particular whether or not it is acquired by teaching or through life experience Socrates proceeds on the hypothesis that virtue is knowledge and it is quickly agreed that if this is true virtue is teachable They turn to the question of whether virtue is indeed knowledge Socrates is hesitant because if virtue were knowledge there should be teachers and learners of it but there are none Coincidentally Anytus appears whom Socrates praises as the son of Anthemion who earned his fortune with intelligence and hard work He says that Anthemion had his son well educated and so Anytus is well suited to join the investigation Socrates suggests that the sophists are teachers of virtue Anytus is horrified saying that he neither knows any nor cares to know any Socrates then questions why it is that men do not always produce sons of the same virtue as themselves He alludes to other notable male figures such as Themistocles Aristides Pericles and Thucydides and casts doubt on whether these men produced sons as capable of virtue as themselves Anytus becomes offended and accuses Socrates of slander warning him to be careful expressing such opinions The historical Anytus was one of Socrates accusers in his trial Socrates suggests that Anytus does not realize what slander is and continues his dialogue with Meno as to the definition of virtue True belief and knowledge edit After the discussion with Anytus Socrates returns to quizzing Meno for his own thoughts on whether the sophists are teachers of virtue and whether virtue can be taught Meno is again at a loss and Socrates suggests that they have made a mistake in agreeing that knowledge is required for virtue He points out the similarities and differences between true belief and knowledge True beliefs are as useful to us as knowledge but they often fail to stay in their place and must be tethered by what he calls aitias logismos calculation of reason or reasoned explanation immediately adding that this is anamnesis or recollection 23 Whether or not Plato intends that the tethering of true beliefs with reasoned explanations must always involve anamnesis is explored in later interpretations of the text 24 25 Socrates distinction between true belief and knowledge forms the basis of the philosophical definition of knowledge as justified true belief Myles Burnyeat and others however have argued that the phrase aitias logismos refers to a practical working out of a solution rather than a justification 26 Socrates concludes that in the virtuous people of the present and the past at least virtue has been the result of divine inspiration akin to the inspiration of the poets whereas a knowledge of it will require answering the basic question what is virtue In most modern readings these closing remarks are evidently ironic 27 but Socrates invocation of the gods may be sincere albeit highly tentative 28 This passage in the Meno is often seen as the first statement of the problem of the value of knowledge how is knowledge more valuable than mere true belief 29 The nature of knowledge and belief is also discussed in the Thaetetus Meno and Protagoras editMeno s theme is also dealt with in the dialogue Protagoras where Plato ultimately has Socrates arrive at the opposite conclusion virtue can be taught Likewise while in Protagoras knowledge is uncompromisingly this worldly in Meno the theory of recollection points to a link between knowledge and eternal truths 15 Texts and translations editMeno in a collection of Plato s Dialogues at Standard Ebooks Jowett Benjamin 1871 Meno via Internet Classics Archive Project Gutenberg 1643 Lamb W R M trans 1924 1967 Meno Plato in Twelve Volumes 3 Cambridge MA Harvard University Press ISBN 0 674 99183 4 0 674 99184 2 via Perseus Project Woods Cathal trans 2011 Meno SSRN 1910945 References edit Plato Meno 70a Plato Meno 80a b Plato Meno 80d Plato Meno 81a e Plato Meno 82a 86c Plato Meno 97b d Plato Meno 98a Plato Meno 71b Plato Meno 71e Plato Meno 73b Plato Meno 73c d Plato Meno 77a Plato Meno 77d e Plato Meno 78b a b Day Jane Mary 1994 Plato s Meno in Focus Routledge p 19 ISBN 0 415 00297 4 a b c Plato Meno translated by B Jowett 1871 Plato 380 BC 1976 Meno translated by G M A Grube Indianapolis Hackett line 80d p 9 Plato 380 BC 1976 Meno translated by G M A Grube Indianapolis Hackett line 80e A man cannot search either for what he knows or for what he does not know He cannot search for what he knows since he knows it there is no need to search nor for what he does not know for he does not know what to look for Plato Meno 84c Plato Meno 84b Plato Meno 85d Plato Meno 86b Vlastos Gregory 1996 Studies in Greek Philosophy Socrates Plato and Their Tradition 2 Princeton University Press ISBN 0 691 01938 X p 155 Fine Gail 1992 Inquiry in the Meno In The Cambridge Companion to Plato edited by R Kraut Cambridge Cambridge University Press ISBN 0 521 43610 9 p 221 Kahn Charles 2006 Plato on Recollection In A Companion to Plato 37 edited by H H Benson Wiley Blackwell ISBN 1 4051 1521 1 p 122 Fine Gail 2004 Knowledge and True Belief in the Meno Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 27 winter 61 62 edited by D Sedley ISBN 0 19 927712 5 Waterfield Robin 2005 Meno and Other Dialogues Oxford World Classics Oxford University Press ISBN 0 19 280425 1 pxliv Scott Dominic 2006 Plato s Meno Cambridge University Press p 193 ISBN 0 521 64033 4 Pritchard Duncan John Turri and J Adam Carter 2007 2018 The Value of Knowledge revised The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Sources edit Day Jane M 1994 Introduction Plato s Meno in Focus Psychology Press ISBN 978 0 415 00297 4 Retrieved 12 March 2023 Klein Jacob 1965 A Commentary on Plato s Meno Chapel Hill University of North Carolina Press External links edit nbsp Wikisource has original text related to this article Meno Meno in a collection of Plato s Dialogues at Standard Ebooks Approaching Plato A Guide to the Early and Middle Dialogues Guides to the Socratic Dialogues Plato s Meno A beginner s guide to the Meno Plato s Meno Contretemps in the Classroom Meno 82b 85d A Visual Representation of the Geometry in Socrates Interrogation of the Slave nbsp Meno public domain audiobook at LibriVox Plato s Meno article in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Meno amp oldid 1190306034 Dialogue with Meno s slave, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.