fbpx
Wikipedia

Maximal lotteries

Maximal lotteries refers to a probabilistic voting system first considered by the French mathematician and social scientist Germain Kreweras[1] in 1965. The method uses preferential ballots and returns so-called maximal lotteries, i.e., probability distributions over the alternatives that are weakly preferred to any other probability distribution. Maximal lotteries satisfy the Condorcet criterion,[2] the Smith criterion,[2] polynomial runtime, and probabilistic versions of reinforcement,[3] participation,[4] and independence of clones.[3]

Maximal lotteries are equivalent to mixed maximin strategies (or Nash equilibria) of the symmetric zero-sum game given by the pairwise majority margins. As such, they have a natural interpretation in terms of electoral competition between two political parties.[5] Moreover, they can be computed using linear programming. The voting system that returns all maximal lotteries is axiomatically characterized as the only one satisfying probabilistic versions of population-consistency (a weakening of reinforcement) and composition-consistency (a strengthening of independence of clones).[3] A social welfare function that top-ranks maximal lotteries is characterized using Arrow's independence of irrelevant alternatives and Pareto efficiency.[6] Maximal lotteries satisfy a strong notion of Pareto efficiency and a weak notion of strategyproofness.[7] In contrast to random dictatorship, maximal lotteries do not satisfy the standard notion of strategyproofness. Also, maximal lotteries are not monotonic in probabilities, i.e., it is possible that the probability of an alternative decreases when this alternative is ranked up. However, the probability of the alternative will remain positive.[8]

Maximal lotteries or variants thereof have been rediscovered multiple times by economists,[9] mathematicians,[2][10] political scientists, philosophers,[11] and computer scientists.[12] In particular, the support of maximal lotteries, which is known as the essential set[13] or the bipartisan set, has been studied in detail.[9][14]

Similar ideas appear also in the study of reinforcement learning and evolutionary biology to explain the multiplicity of co-existing species.[15][16]

Collective preferences over lotteries edit

The input to this voting system consists of the agents' ordinal preferences over outcomes (not lotteries over alternatives), but a relation on the set of lotteries can be constructed in the following way: if   and   are lotteries over alternatives,   if the expected value of the margin of victory of an outcome selected with distribution   in a head-to-head vote against an outcome selected with distribution   is positive. In other words,   if it is more likely that a randomly selected voter will prefer the alternatives sampled from   to the alternative sampled from   than vice versa.[6] While this relation is not necessarily transitive, it does always contain at least one maximal element.

It is possible that several such maximal lotteries exist, but unicity can be proven in the case where the margins between any pair of alternatives is always an odd number.[17] This is the case for instance if there is an odd number of voters who all hold strict preferences over the alternatives. Following the same argument, unicity holds for the original "bipartisan set" that is defined as the support of the maximal lottery of a tournament game.[8]

Example edit

Suppose there are five voters who have the following preferences over three alternatives:

  • 2 voters:  
  • 2 voters:  
  • 1 voter:  

The pairwise preferences of the voters can be represented in the following skew-symmetric matrix, where the entry for row   and column   denotes the number of voters who prefer   to   minus the number of voters who prefer   to  .

 

This matrix can be interpreted as a zero-sum game and admits a unique Nash equilibrium (or minimax strategy)   where  ,  ,  . By definition, this is also the unique maximal lottery of the preference profile above. The example was carefully chosen not to have a Condorcet winner. Many preference profiles admit a Condorcet winner, in which case the unique maximal lottery will assign probability 1 to the Condorcet winner.

References edit

  1. ^ G. Kreweras. Aggregation of preference orderings. In Mathematics and Social Sciences I: Proceedings of the seminars of Menthon-Saint-Bernard, France (1–27 July 1960) and of Gösing, Austria (3–27 July 1962), pages 73–79, 1965.
  2. ^ a b c P. C. Fishburn. Probabilistic social choice based on simple voting comparisons. Review of Economic Studies, 51(4):683–692, 1984.
  3. ^ a b c F. Brandl, F. Brandt, and H. G. Seedig. Consistent probabilistic social choice. Econometrica. 84(5), pages 1839-1880, 2016.
  4. ^ F. Brandl, F. Brandt, and J. Hofbauer. Welfare Maximization Entices Participation. Games and Economic Behavior. 14, pages 308-314, 2019.
  5. ^ Laslier, J.-F. Interpretation of electoral mixed strategies Social Choice and Welfare 17: pages 283–292, 2000.
  6. ^ a b F. Brandl and F. Brandt. Arrovian Aggregation of Convex Preferences. Econometrica. 88(2), pages 799-844, 2020.
  7. ^ H. Aziz, F. Brandt, and M Brill. On the Tradeoff between Economic Efficiency and Strategyproofness. Games and Economic Behavior. 110, pages 1-18, 2018.
  8. ^ a b Laslier, J.-F. Tournament solutions and majority voting Springer-Verlag, 1997.
  9. ^ a b G. Laffond, J.-F. Laslier, and M. Le Breton. The bipartisan set of a tournament game. Games and Economic Behavior, 5(1):182–201, 1993.
  10. ^ D. C. Fisher and J. Ryan. Tournament games and positive tournaments. Journal of Graph Theory, 19(2):217–236, 1995.
  11. ^ D. S. Felsenthal and M. Machover. After two centuries should Condorcet’s voting procedure be implemented? Behavioral Science, 37(4):250–274, 1992.
  12. ^ R. L. Rivest and E. Shen. An optimal single-winner preferential voting system based on game theory. In Proceedings of 3rd International Workshop on Computational Social Choice, pages 399–410, 2010.
  13. ^ B. Dutta and J.-F. Laslier. Comparison functions and choice correspondences. Social Choice and Welfare, 16: 513–532, 1999.
  14. ^ F. Brandt, M. Brill, H. G. Seedig, and W. Suksompong. On the structure of stable tournament solutions. Economic Theory, 65(2):483–507, 2018.
  15. ^ B. Laslier and J.-F. Laslier. Reinforcement learning from comparisons: Three alternatives are enough, two are not Annals of Applied Probability 27(5): 2907–2925, 2017.
  16. ^ Jacopo Grilli, György Barabás, Matthew J. Michalska-Smith and Stefano Allesina. Higher-order interactions stabilize dynamics in competitive network models Nature 548: 210-214, 2017.
  17. ^ Gilbert Laffond, Jean-François Laslier and Michel Le Breton A theorem on two–player symmetric zero–sum games Journal of Economic Theory 72: 426–431, 1997.

External links edit

  • voting.ml (website for computing maximal lotteries)
  • Pnyx - Practical Preference Aggregation (voting tool that, among other methods, offers maximal lotteries)

maximal, lotteries, refers, probabilistic, voting, system, first, considered, french, mathematician, social, scientist, germain, kreweras, 1965, method, uses, preferential, ballots, returns, called, maximal, lotteries, probability, distributions, over, alterna. Maximal lotteries refers to a probabilistic voting system first considered by the French mathematician and social scientist Germain Kreweras 1 in 1965 The method uses preferential ballots and returns so called maximal lotteries i e probability distributions over the alternatives that are weakly preferred to any other probability distribution Maximal lotteries satisfy the Condorcet criterion 2 the Smith criterion 2 polynomial runtime and probabilistic versions of reinforcement 3 participation 4 and independence of clones 3 Maximal lotteries are equivalent to mixed maximin strategies or Nash equilibria of the symmetric zero sum game given by the pairwise majority margins As such they have a natural interpretation in terms of electoral competition between two political parties 5 Moreover they can be computed using linear programming The voting system that returns all maximal lotteries is axiomatically characterized as the only one satisfying probabilistic versions of population consistency a weakening of reinforcement and composition consistency a strengthening of independence of clones 3 A social welfare function that top ranks maximal lotteries is characterized using Arrow s independence of irrelevant alternatives and Pareto efficiency 6 Maximal lotteries satisfy a strong notion of Pareto efficiency and a weak notion of strategyproofness 7 In contrast to random dictatorship maximal lotteries do not satisfy the standard notion of strategyproofness Also maximal lotteries are not monotonic in probabilities i e it is possible that the probability of an alternative decreases when this alternative is ranked up However the probability of the alternative will remain positive 8 Maximal lotteries or variants thereof have been rediscovered multiple times by economists 9 mathematicians 2 10 political scientists philosophers 11 and computer scientists 12 In particular the support of maximal lotteries which is known as the essential set 13 or the bipartisan set has been studied in detail 9 14 Similar ideas appear also in the study of reinforcement learning and evolutionary biology to explain the multiplicity of co existing species 15 16 Contents 1 Collective preferences over lotteries 2 Example 3 References 4 External linksCollective preferences over lotteries editThe input to this voting system consists of the agents ordinal preferences over outcomes not lotteries over alternatives but a relation on the set of lotteries can be constructed in the following way if p displaystyle p nbsp and q displaystyle q nbsp are lotteries over alternatives p q displaystyle p succ q nbsp if the expected value of the margin of victory of an outcome selected with distribution p displaystyle p nbsp in a head to head vote against an outcome selected with distribution q displaystyle q nbsp is positive In other words p q displaystyle p succ q nbsp if it is more likely that a randomly selected voter will prefer the alternatives sampled from p displaystyle p nbsp to the alternative sampled from q displaystyle q nbsp than vice versa 6 While this relation is not necessarily transitive it does always contain at least one maximal element It is possible that several such maximal lotteries exist but unicity can be proven in the case where the margins between any pair of alternatives is always an odd number 17 This is the case for instance if there is an odd number of voters who all hold strict preferences over the alternatives Following the same argument unicity holds for the original bipartisan set that is defined as the support of the maximal lottery of a tournament game 8 Example editSuppose there are five voters who have the following preferences over three alternatives 2 voters a b c displaystyle a succ b succ c nbsp 2 voters b c a displaystyle b succ c succ a nbsp 1 voter c a b displaystyle c succ a succ b nbsp The pairwise preferences of the voters can be represented in the following skew symmetric matrix where the entry for row x displaystyle x nbsp and column y displaystyle y nbsp denotes the number of voters who prefer x displaystyle x nbsp to y displaystyle y nbsp minus the number of voters who prefer y displaystyle y nbsp to x displaystyle x nbsp a b c a b c 0 1 1 1 0 3 1 3 0 displaystyle begin matrix begin matrix amp amp a quad amp b quad amp c quad end matrix begin matrix a b c end matrix begin pmatrix 0 amp 1 amp 1 1 amp 0 amp 3 1 amp 3 amp 0 end pmatrix end matrix nbsp This matrix can be interpreted as a zero sum game and admits a unique Nash equilibrium or minimax strategy p displaystyle p nbsp where p a 3 5 displaystyle p a 3 5 nbsp p b 1 5 displaystyle p b 1 5 nbsp p c 1 5 displaystyle p c 1 5 nbsp By definition this is also the unique maximal lottery of the preference profile above The example was carefully chosen not to have a Condorcet winner Many preference profiles admit a Condorcet winner in which case the unique maximal lottery will assign probability 1 to the Condorcet winner References edit G Kreweras Aggregation of preference orderings In Mathematics and Social Sciences I Proceedings of the seminars of Menthon Saint Bernard France 1 27 July 1960 and of Gosing Austria 3 27 July 1962 pages 73 79 1965 a b c P C Fishburn Probabilistic social choice based on simple voting comparisons Review of Economic Studies 51 4 683 692 1984 a b c F Brandl F Brandt and H G Seedig Consistent probabilistic social choice Econometrica 84 5 pages 1839 1880 2016 F Brandl F Brandt and J Hofbauer Welfare Maximization Entices Participation Games and Economic Behavior 14 pages 308 314 2019 Laslier J F Interpretation of electoral mixed strategies Social Choice and Welfare 17 pages 283 292 2000 a b F Brandl and F Brandt Arrovian Aggregation of Convex Preferences Econometrica 88 2 pages 799 844 2020 H Aziz F Brandt and M Brill On the Tradeoff between Economic Efficiency and Strategyproofness Games and Economic Behavior 110 pages 1 18 2018 a b Laslier J F Tournament solutions and majority voting Springer Verlag 1997 a b G Laffond J F Laslier and M Le Breton The bipartisan set of a tournament game Games and Economic Behavior 5 1 182 201 1993 D C Fisher and J Ryan Tournament games and positive tournaments Journal of Graph Theory 19 2 217 236 1995 D S Felsenthal and M Machover After two centuries should Condorcet s voting procedure be implemented Behavioral Science 37 4 250 274 1992 R L Rivest and E Shen An optimal single winner preferential voting system based on game theory In Proceedings of 3rd International Workshop on Computational Social Choice pages 399 410 2010 B Dutta and J F Laslier Comparison functions and choice correspondences Social Choice and Welfare 16 513 532 1999 F Brandt M Brill H G Seedig and W Suksompong On the structure of stable tournament solutions Economic Theory 65 2 483 507 2018 B Laslier and J F Laslier Reinforcement learning from comparisons Three alternatives are enough two are not Annals of Applied Probability 27 5 2907 2925 2017 Jacopo Grilli Gyorgy Barabas Matthew J Michalska Smith and Stefano Allesina Higher order interactions stabilize dynamics in competitive network models Nature 548 210 214 2017 Gilbert Laffond Jean Francois Laslier and Michel Le Breton A theorem on two player symmetric zero sum games Journal of Economic Theory 72 426 431 1997 External links editvoting ml website for computing maximal lotteries Pnyx Practical Preference Aggregation voting tool that among other methods offers maximal lotteries Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Maximal lotteries amp oldid 1180096083, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.