fbpx
Wikipedia

Hypothetical syllogism

In classical logic, a hypothetical syllogism is a valid argument form, a deductive syllogism with a conditional statement for one or both of its premises. Ancient references point to the works of Theophrastus and Eudemus for the first investigation of this kind of syllogisms.[1][2]

Hypothetical syllogism
TypeSyllogism
Field
StatementWhenever instances of , and appear on lines of a proof, can be placed on a subsequent line.
Symbolic statement

Types edit

Hypothetical syllogisms come in two types: mixed and pure. A mixed hypothetical syllogism has two premises: one conditional statement and one statement that either affirms or denies the antecedent or consequent of that conditional statement. For example,

If P, then Q.
P.
∴ Q.

In this example, the first premise is a conditional statement in which "P" is the antecedent and "Q" is the consequent. The second premise "affirms" the antecedent. The conclusion, that the consequent must be true, is deductively valid.

A mixed hypothetical syllogism has four possible forms, two of which are valid, while the other two are invalid. A valid mixed hypothetical syllogism either affirms the antecedent (modus ponens) or denies the consequent (modus tollens).[3] An invalid hypothetical syllogism either affirms the consequent (fallacy of the converse) or denies the antecedent (fallacy of the inverse).

 
There are four possible forms of mixed hypothetical syllogisms, two of which are valid, while two of which are invalid. Considering a simple example demonstrates why forms are valid or invalid. If "p" represents "Candiru is a fish" and "q" represents "Candiru has gills," try to convince yourself by replacing these statements with p and q in the above table.[3]

A pure hypothetical syllogism is a syllogism in which both premises and the conclusion are all conditional statements. The antecedent of one premise must match the consequent of the other for the conditional to be valid. Consequently, conditionals contain remained antecedent as antecedent and remained consequent as consequent.

If P, then Q.
If Q, then R.
∴ If P, then R.

An example in English:

If I do not wake up, then I cannot go to work.
If I cannot go to work, then I will not get paid.
Therefore, if I do not wake up, then I will not get paid.

Propositional logic edit

In propositional logic, hypothetical syllogism is the name of a valid rule of inference (often abbreviated HS and sometimes also called the chain argument, chain rule, or the principle of transitivity of implication). The rule may be stated:

 

In other words, whenever instances of " ", and " " appear on lines of a proof, " " can be placed on a subsequent line.

Applicability edit

The rule of hypothetical syllogism holds in classical logic, intuitionistic logic, most systems of relevance logic, and many other systems of logic. However, it does not hold in all logics, including, for example, non-monotonic logic, probabilistic logic and default logic. The reason for this is that these logics describe defeasible reasoning, and conditionals that appear in real-world contexts typically allow for exceptions, default assumptions, ceteris paribus conditions, or just simple uncertainty.

An example, derived from Ernest W. Adams, [4]

  1. If Jones wins the election, Smith will retire after the election.
  2. If Smith dies before the election, Jones will win the election.
  3. If Smith dies before the election, Smith will retire after the election.

Clearly, (3) does not follow from (1) and (2). (1) is true by default, but fails to hold in the exceptional circumstances of Smith dying. In practice, real-world conditionals always tend to involve default assumptions or contexts, and it may be infeasible or even impossible to specify all the exceptional circumstances in which they might fail to be true. For similar reasons, the rule of hypothetical syllogism does not hold for counterfactual conditionals.

Formal notation edit

The hypothetical syllogism inference rule may be written in sequent notation, which amounts to a specialization of the cut rule:

 

where   is a metalogical symbol and   meaning that   is a syntactic consequence of   in some logical system;

and expressed as a truth-functional tautology or theorem of propositional logic:

 

where  ,  , and   are propositions expressed in some formal system.

Proof edit

Step Proposition Derivation
1   Given
2   Given
3   Conditional proof assumption
4   Modus ponens (1,3)
5   Modus ponens (2,4)
6   Conditional Proof (3-5)

Alternative forms edit

An alternative form of hypothetical syllogism, more useful for classical propositional calculus systems with implication and negation (i.e. without the conjunction symbol), is the following:

(HS1)  

Yet another form is:

(HS2)  

Proof edit

An example of the proofs of these theorems in such systems is given below. We use two of the three axioms used in one of the popular systems described by Jan Łukasiewicz. The proofs relies on two out of the three axioms of this system:

(A1)  
(A2)  

The proof of the (HS1) is as follows:

(1)         (instance of (A1))
(2)         (instance of (A2))
(3)         (from (1) and (2) by modus ponens)
(4)         (instance of (A2))
(5)         (from (3) and (4) by modus ponens)
(6)         (instance of (A1))
(7)   (from (5) and (6) by modus ponens)

The proof of the (HS2) is given here.

As a metatheorem edit

Whenever we have two theorems of the form   and  , we can prove   by the following steps:

(1)         (instance of the theorem proved above)
(2)         (instance of (T1))
(3)         (from (1) and (2) by modus ponens)
(4)         (instance of (T2))
(5)         (from (3) and (4) by modus ponens)

See also edit

References edit

  1. ^ "History of Logic: Theophrastus of Eresus" in Encyclopædia Britannica Online.
  2. ^ Susanne Bobzien,"The Development of Modus Ponens in Antiquity: "From Aristotle to the 2nd Century AD", Phronesis, Vol. 47, No. 4 (2002), pp. 359-394.
  3. ^ a b Kashef, Arman. (2023), In Quest of Univeral Logic: A brief overview of formal logic's evolution, doi:10.13140/RG.2.2.24043.82724/1
  4. ^ Adams, Ernest W. (1975). The Logic of Conditionals. Dordrecht: Reidel. p. 22.

External links edit

  • Philosophy Index: Hypothetical Syllogism

hypothetical, syllogism, classical, logic, hypothetical, syllogism, valid, argument, form, deductive, syllogism, with, conditional, statement, both, premises, ancient, references, point, works, theophrastus, eudemus, first, investigation, this, kind, syllogism. In classical logic a hypothetical syllogism is a valid argument form a deductive syllogism with a conditional statement for one or both of its premises Ancient references point to the works of Theophrastus and Eudemus for the first investigation of this kind of syllogisms 1 2 Hypothetical syllogismTypeSyllogismFieldPropositional calculus Classical logic Intuitionistic logic Most systems of relevance logicStatementWhenever instances of P Q displaystyle P to Q and Q R displaystyle Q to R appear on lines of a proof P R displaystyle P to R can be placed on a subsequent line Symbolic statementP Q Q R P R displaystyle frac P to Q Q to R therefore P to R Contents 1 Types 2 Propositional logic 3 Applicability 4 Formal notation 5 Proof 6 Alternative forms 6 1 Proof 6 2 As a metatheorem 7 See also 8 References 9 External linksTypes editHypothetical syllogisms come in two types mixed and pure A mixed hypothetical syllogism has two premises one conditional statement and one statement that either affirms or denies the antecedent or consequent of that conditional statement For example If P then Q P Q In this example the first premise is a conditional statement in which P is the antecedent and Q is the consequent The second premise affirms the antecedent The conclusion that the consequent must be true is deductively valid A mixed hypothetical syllogism has four possible forms two of which are valid while the other two are invalid A valid mixed hypothetical syllogism either affirms the antecedent modus ponens or denies the consequent modus tollens 3 An invalid hypothetical syllogism either affirms the consequent fallacy of the converse or denies the antecedent fallacy of the inverse nbsp There are four possible forms of mixed hypothetical syllogisms two of which are valid while two of which are invalid Considering a simple example demonstrates why forms are valid or invalid If p represents Candiru is a fish and q represents Candiru has gills try to convince yourself by replacing these statements with p and q in the above table 3 A pure hypothetical syllogism is a syllogism in which both premises and the conclusion are all conditional statements The antecedent of one premise must match the consequent of the other for the conditional to be valid Consequently conditionals contain remained antecedent as antecedent and remained consequent as consequent If P then Q If Q then R If P then R An example in English If I do not wake up then I cannot go to work If I cannot go to work then I will not get paid Therefore if I do not wake up then I will not get paid Propositional logic editIn propositional logic hypothetical syllogism is the name of a valid rule of inference often abbreviated HS and sometimes also called the chain argument chain rule or the principle of transitivity of implication The rule may be stated P Q Q R P R displaystyle frac P to Q Q to R therefore P to R nbsp In other words whenever instances of P Q displaystyle P to Q nbsp and Q R displaystyle Q to R nbsp appear on lines of a proof P R displaystyle P to R nbsp can be placed on a subsequent line Applicability editThe rule of hypothetical syllogism holds in classical logic intuitionistic logic most systems of relevance logic and many other systems of logic However it does not hold in all logics including for example non monotonic logic probabilistic logic and default logic The reason for this is that these logics describe defeasible reasoning and conditionals that appear in real world contexts typically allow for exceptions default assumptions ceteris paribus conditions or just simple uncertainty An example derived from Ernest W Adams 4 If Jones wins the election Smith will retire after the election If Smith dies before the election Jones will win the election If Smith dies before the election Smith will retire after the election Clearly 3 does not follow from 1 and 2 1 is true by default but fails to hold in the exceptional circumstances of Smith dying In practice real world conditionals always tend to involve default assumptions or contexts and it may be infeasible or even impossible to specify all the exceptional circumstances in which they might fail to be true For similar reasons the rule of hypothetical syllogism does not hold for counterfactual conditionals Formal notation editThe hypothetical syllogism inference rule may be written in sequent notation which amounts to a specialization of the cut rule P Q Q R P R displaystyle frac P vdash Q quad Q vdash R P vdash R nbsp where displaystyle vdash nbsp is a metalogical symbol and A B displaystyle A vdash B nbsp meaning that B displaystyle B nbsp is a syntactic consequence of A displaystyle A nbsp in some logical system and expressed as a truth functional tautology or theorem of propositional logic P Q Q R P R displaystyle P to Q land Q to R to P to R nbsp where P displaystyle P nbsp Q displaystyle Q nbsp and R displaystyle R nbsp are propositions expressed in some formal system Proof editStep Proposition Derivation 1 P Q displaystyle P to Q nbsp Given 2 Q R displaystyle Q to R nbsp Given 3 P displaystyle P nbsp Conditional proof assumption 4 Q displaystyle Q nbsp Modus ponens 1 3 5 R displaystyle R nbsp Modus ponens 2 4 6 P R displaystyle P to R nbsp Conditional Proof 3 5 Alternative forms editAn alternative form of hypothetical syllogism more useful for classical propositional calculus systems with implication and negation i e without the conjunction symbol is the following HS1 Q R P Q P R displaystyle Q to R to P to Q to P to R nbsp Yet another form is HS2 P Q Q R P R displaystyle P to Q to Q to R to P to R nbsp Proof edit An example of the proofs of these theorems in such systems is given below We use two of the three axioms used in one of the popular systems described by Jan Lukasiewicz The proofs relies on two out of the three axioms of this system A1 ϕ ps ϕ displaystyle phi to left psi to phi right nbsp A2 ϕ ps 3 ϕ ps ϕ 3 displaystyle left phi to left psi rightarrow xi right right to left left phi to psi right to left phi to xi right right nbsp The proof of the HS1 is as follows 1 p q r p q p r q r p q r p q p r displaystyle p to q to r to p to q to p to r to q to r to p to q to r to p to q to p to r nbsp instance of A1 2 p q r p q p r displaystyle p to q to r to p to q to p to r nbsp instance of A2 3 q r p q r p q p r displaystyle q to r to p to q to r to p to q to p to r nbsp from 1 and 2 by modus ponens 4 q r p q r p q p r q r p q r q r p q p r displaystyle q to r to p to q to r to p to q to p to r to q to r to p to q to r to q to r to p to q to p to r nbsp instance of A2 5 q r p q r q r p q p r displaystyle q to r to p to q to r to q to r to p to q to p to r nbsp from 3 and 4 by modus ponens 6 q r p q r displaystyle q to r to p to q to r nbsp instance of A1 7 q r p q p r displaystyle q to r to p to q to p to r nbsp from 5 and 6 by modus ponens The proof of the HS2 is given here As a metatheorem edit Whenever we have two theorems of the form T 1 Q R displaystyle T 1 Q to R nbsp and T 2 P Q displaystyle T 2 P to Q nbsp we can prove P R displaystyle P to R nbsp by the following steps 1 Q R P Q P R displaystyle Q to R to P to Q to P to R nbsp instance of the theorem proved above 2 Q R displaystyle Q to R nbsp instance of T1 3 P Q P R displaystyle P to Q to P to R nbsp from 1 and 2 by modus ponens 4 P Q displaystyle P to Q nbsp instance of T2 5 P R displaystyle P to R nbsp from 3 and 4 by modus ponens See also editPlausible reasoning Transitive relation Type of syllogism disjunctive hypothetical legal poly prosleptic quasi statistical References edit History of Logic Theophrastus of Eresus in Encyclopaedia Britannica Online Susanne Bobzien The Development of Modus Ponens in Antiquity From Aristotle to the 2nd Century AD Phronesis Vol 47 No 4 2002 pp 359 394 a b Kashef Arman 2023 In Quest of Univeral Logic A brief overview of formal logic s evolution doi 10 13140 RG 2 2 24043 82724 1 Adams Ernest W 1975 The Logic of Conditionals Dordrecht Reidel p 22 External links editPhilosophy Index Hypothetical Syllogism Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Hypothetical syllogism amp oldid 1221253619, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.