fbpx
Wikipedia

Common good constitutionalism

Common good constitutionalism is a legal theory formulated by Harvard law professor Adrian Vermeule that asserts that “the central aim of the constitutional order is to promote good rule, not to ‘protect liberty’ as an end in itself”.[1] Vermeule describes it as an attempt to revive and develop the classical legal tradition by understanding enacted law as a positive application of background natural law principles.[2] Within this tradition, he claims law is defined as "an ordinance of reason promulgated by political authorities for the common good."[2] Vermeule states that law in this sense is "not tethered to particular written instruments of civil law or the will of the legislators who created them"[3] but instead embody rational determinations of the common good, and it is those determinations, as well as the natural law background against which they are made, which constitute the law. Vermeule says that these principles include "a candid willingness to “legislate morality.”[1]

Thomas Aquinas, whose definition of law forms the basis for common good constitutionalism

Common good constitutionalism, as first advanced by Adrian Vermeule in 2020, has been described as a derivative of integralism, both of which were created "to combat the legitimate societal threat of modern liberal individualism and reintroduce the spiritual common good into our political and legal discourse."[4] Vermeule himself argues the notion natural law theory is either just coterminous with Catholic political theory is "both historically and theologically erroneous". Vermeule highlights that historically, natural law theory originates with Greek and Roman philosophers, largely before Christianity became dominant. Theologically, Vermeule argues that "Catholicism itself holds that the natural law is written in the hearts of all men, and is in principle accessible to the universal natural reason common to all".[5]

Common good constitutionalism is opposed to both originalism[6] and liberal legal theories such as a living constitution.[7]

History Edit

In an article in The Atlantic in March 2020, Adrian Vermeule suggested that originalism – the idea that the meaning of the American Constitution was fixed at the time of its enactment, which has been the principal legal theory of conservative judges and legal scholars for the past 50 years, but which Vermeule now characterizes as merely "a useful rhetorical and political expedient" – has outlived its usefulness and needs to be replaced by what he calls "common-good constitutionalism".[3]

Common good constitutionalism has garnered a mix of responses, with many praising its recognition of classical legal theories, while others fear that it could lead to judicial fiat.[8][9] Notably, Richard H. Helmholz, in a review of Common Good Constitutionalism, described it as "a serious contribution to some of the most pressing legal debates of our times."[10] Jack Goldsmith has praised Common Good Constitutionalism as "the most important book of American constitutional theory in many decades".[8]

However, notable originalist scholar Randy Barnett criticized the theory as subversive of America's founding principles.[11] Conservative columnist George F. Will described Vermeule's "common-good constitutionalism" as "Christian authoritarianism — muscular paternalism, with government enforcing social solidarity for religious reasons."[12]

Notable common good scholars include Adrian Vermeule, Conor Casey, and Michael Foran.[13][14][15][16]

Principles Edit

Thomas Aquinas defined law as "an ordinance of reason made for the common good by him who has charge of the community, and promulgated".[17] Common good constitutionalism adopts this definition, treating positive law as a promulgated ordinance of reason, where "ordinance of reason" invokes that law which is ascertainable reason, or the natural law.[18]: 3  Natural law provides background legal principles, such as "do good and avoid evil," that are not necessarily determinate as applied to concrete cases. Positive law, then, is made when a public authority makes a practical determination within the scope of the natural law.[18] For example, public safety is furthered by having cars drive on one side of the road, but nothing about public safety inherently requires choosing one side of the road or the other. Thus within the requirements of public safety, the public authority is free to determine a concrete application, that is, driving on the left or right side.

In the context of the judiciary, interpretation of legal texts must then be made in light of the natural law principles made concrete by the text. They must be reviewed for rationality, but so long as the positive law does not offend reason—the background natural law principles—the judiciary should defer to the legislating authority.[18] To return to the driving example, to require driving on the left side of the road does not offend reason, nor does driving on the right. Both further the common good by promoting public roadway safety, and thus either determination by the legislature should be deferred to.

"Common good" is defined not as a utilitarian aggregation of individual goods, nor as a tyrannical subjugation of the individual to the community. Rather, it is the unification of individual and community goods that leads to personal and social flourishing.[18] A Navy-Marine Corps Court of Criminal Appeals judge wrote in his concurrence in United States v. Tabor that "[t]he classical judge would attempt to discern what common good is desired by the statute and recognize that a statute can have a purpose toward the good of the individual, a purpose toward the good of the community, and an additional good in harmonizing the interests between the two. A statute—a lex—is an attempt to codify a higher law that a nation or a people all know to be true and good, even if it were to limit individual freedom in certain circumstances."[19] Thus individual goods or rights must be justified in light of their contribution to the flourishing of the community.[2]

Reception Edit

Common good constitutionalism has divided opinion amongst scholars and lawyers.

Many natural lawyers have welcomed it as a valuable contribution to legal theory. University of Chicago legal historian Richard Helmholz described Common Good Constitutionalism (Polity, 2022) as a “serious contribution to some of the most pressing legal debates of our times ... written ... with clarity and skill.”[20] University of Texas law professor Sanford Levinson described it as “truly an important book deserving wide readership and intense discussion”[21] while University of Michigan law professor Richard Primus saw potential in its “simple and powerful frame” but felt the book "stops short of fully describing the common good that Vermeule envisions."[22]

Writing in the Modern Law Review, University of Glasgow legal scholar Michael Foran said the theory offers “powerful critiques of the foundational assumptions of liberal constitutionalism”.[23] University of Georgia law professor Eric Segall wrote that common good constitutionalism offers a “critique of the never-ending debates between originalists and living constitutionalists--debates that have not furthered constitutional discourse in a helpful manner.”[24]

One scholar noted its potential relevance for environmental law, stating that “[E]nvironmental advocates can benefit both from considering the common good constitutionalist approach in its own right and as a catalyst for action.”[25]

Various practicing lawyers have praised common good constitutionalism as positively contributing values and rationales that are perceived by some to be missing from the political and judicial discourse.[26][27][28][29]

Common good constitutionalism's grounding in a Catholic moral framework has led to charges that, in practice, it is inherently theocratic.[30] David Dyzenhaus has heavily criticized Vermeule's conception of Common Good Constitutionalism, hailing it an "authoritarian" idea seeking to instill "Christian theocratic rule".[31] He criticizes Vermeule for invoking "justification [via] a body of allegedly timeless and universal principles that animate right-wing Catholics and Evangelicals in the US", and for "worshipping the executive" which can put those ideals into practice.[32]

Linda C. McClain has criticized Common Good Constitutionalism for the moral positions which underpin the conception of the common good adopted by its advocates. In particular, the enthusiasm for restrictions on abortion and reproductive rights and heavy reliance on jurists who endorse "the exclusion of women from full participation in civic, political, and economic life" make her doubt whether women’s rights are reasonably secure under the providence of the common good; the prevalence of 'natural law' values which promote segregation and discrimination, and the fact that Vermeule and his associates are "notably silent about problems like religiously-inspired racism and white supremacy" give rise to further concerns that Common Good Constitutionalism, in practice, advocates for a view of ethics palatable only for religious conservatives who share Vermeule's own moral values. McClain expresses a "profound doubt that a free and equal people ... would submit" to the moral framework which common good constitutionalists promote.[33]

Former White House Counsel under Ronald Reagan Peter Wallison criticized Vermeule for failing to define "the common good." Wallison also stated that the political order formulated by common good constitutionalism "is highly authoritarian, perhaps even totalitarian" citing Vermeule's assertion that: "Constitutional concepts such as liberty and equality need not be given libertarian or originalist readings."[34]

See also Edit

References Edit

  1. ^ a b Vermeule, Adrian (2020-03-31). "Beyond Originalism". The Atlantic. Retrieved 2023-02-17.
  2. ^ a b c Casey, Conor; Vermeule, Adrian (2022-02-09). "Myths of Common Good Constitutionalism". Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy. 45 (1): 103–146. SSRN 4030763.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: date and year (link)
  3. ^ a b Vermeule, Adrian (2020-03-31). "Beyond Originalism". The Atlantic. Retrieved 2022-06-11.
  4. ^ Frohnen, Bruce P. (14 April 2022). "Common Good Constitutionalism and the Problem of Administrative Absolutism". Ohio Northern University College of Law. SSRN 4083882. Retrieved 13 June 2022.
  5. ^ Vermeule, Adrian. "The Common Good as a Universal Framework". Balkinization. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  6. ^ Baude, William; Sachs, Stephen E. "The 'Common-Good' Manifesto". harvardlawreview.org. Retrieved 2023-02-17.
  7. ^ "Critics Call It Theocratic and Authoritarian. Young Conservatives Call It an Exciting New Legal Theory". POLITICO. Retrieved 2023-02-17.
  8. ^ a b "Common Good Constitutionalism". Polity. Retrieved 2022-06-11.
  9. ^ "The Future of Conservative Constitutionalism". National Review. 2021-09-17. Retrieved 2022-06-11.
  10. ^ "Marching Orders | R. H. Helmholz". First Things. Retrieved 2022-06-11.
  11. ^ Barnett, Randy E. (2020-04-03). "Common-Good Constitutionalism Reveals the Dangers of Any Non-originalist Approach to the Constitution". The Atlantic. Retrieved 2022-06-11.
  12. ^ Will, George F. (May 29, 2020). "When American conservatism becomes un-American". The Washington Post. Retrieved June 10, 2022.
  13. ^ "CGC Symposium". Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy. 2022-08-30. Retrieved 2022-10-31.
  14. ^ Casey, Conor (2021). "'Common Good Constitutionalism' and the New Debate over Constitutional Interpretation in the United States". Public Law. SSRN 3725068.
  15. ^ Hammer, Josh (2021). "Common Good Originalism" (PDF). Harvard Journal of Law & Public Policy.
  16. ^ "Explaining Common-Good Originalism Does Not Help Its Case". National Review. 2021-08-19. Retrieved 2022-06-20.
  17. ^ Aquinas, Thomas. Summa Theologica.
  18. ^ a b c d Vermeule, Adrian (2022). Common good constitutionalism : recovering the classical legal tradition. Cambridge, UK. ISBN 978-1-5095-4887-3. OCLC 1266642815.{{cite book}}: CS1 maint: location missing publisher (link)
  19. ^ United States v. Tabor, NMCCA No. 202100046, 46
  20. ^ Helmholz, Richard. "Marching Orders". First Things. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  21. ^ Levinson, Sanford. "Adrian Vermeule's rejection of "modern" constitutional theory". Balkinization. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  22. ^ Primus, Richard. "The Other 630,000 Words". Balkinization. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  23. ^ Foran, Michael (2 August 2022). "Rights, Common Good, and The Separation of Powers". SSRN. SSRN 4179424. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  24. ^ Segall, Eric. "Ten Observations About Adrian Vermeule's Book "Common Good Constitutionalism"". Dorf on Law. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  25. ^ Quigley, Brian. "Common Good Constitutionalism and the Future of Environmental Law" (PDF). Vermont Journal of Environmental Law. 23 (4): 349–373. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  26. ^ Whitehead, Daniel. "A Jurisprudence of Hope". Anchoring Truths. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  27. ^ Blacklock, Evelyn. "A Jurisprudential Red Pill: Part II". Anchoring Truths. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  28. ^ Neu, Jacob (5 August 2022). "Common Good Constitutionalism for the Working Lawyer". Ius & Iustitium. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  29. ^ Sabater, Aníbal (August 2022). "Lawyers as Common Good Servers". Ius & Iustitium. Retrieved 29 August 2022.
  30. ^ "Amy Coney Barrett's Long Game". The New Yorker. 4 February 2022.
  31. ^ "Schmitten in the USA". Verfassungsblog.
  32. ^ "The Snake Charmers".
  33. ^ "Balkinization: The Common Good as a Universal Framework".
  34. ^ "Review: Common Good Constitutionalism". American Enterprise Institute - AEI. Retrieved 2023-02-17.

External links Edit

common, good, constitutionalism, this, article, multiple, issues, please, help, improve, discuss, these, issues, talk, page, learn, when, remove, these, template, messages, neutrality, this, article, disputed, relevant, discussion, found, talk, page, please, r. This article has multiple issues Please help improve it or discuss these issues on the talk page Learn how and when to remove these template messages The neutrality of this article is disputed Relevant discussion may be found on the talk page Please do not remove this message until conditions to do so are met June 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message The examples and perspective in this article may not include all significant viewpoints Please improve the article or discuss the issue June 2023 Learn how and when to remove this template message Learn how and when to remove this template message Common good constitutionalism is a legal theory formulated by Harvard law professor Adrian Vermeule that asserts that the central aim of the constitutional order is to promote good rule not to protect liberty as an end in itself 1 Vermeule describes it as an attempt to revive and develop the classical legal tradition by understanding enacted law as a positive application of background natural law principles 2 Within this tradition he claims law is defined as an ordinance of reason promulgated by political authorities for the common good 2 Vermeule states that law in this sense is not tethered to particular written instruments of civil law or the will of the legislators who created them 3 but instead embody rational determinations of the common good and it is those determinations as well as the natural law background against which they are made which constitute the law Vermeule says that these principles include a candid willingness to legislate morality 1 Thomas Aquinas whose definition of law forms the basis for common good constitutionalismCommon good constitutionalism as first advanced by Adrian Vermeule in 2020 has been described as a derivative of integralism both of which were created to combat the legitimate societal threat of modern liberal individualism and reintroduce the spiritual common good into our political and legal discourse 4 Vermeule himself argues the notion natural law theory is either just coterminous with Catholic political theory is both historically and theologically erroneous Vermeule highlights that historically natural law theory originates with Greek and Roman philosophers largely before Christianity became dominant Theologically Vermeule argues that Catholicism itself holds that the natural law is written in the hearts of all men and is in principle accessible to the universal natural reason common to all 5 Common good constitutionalism is opposed to both originalism 6 and liberal legal theories such as a living constitution 7 Contents 1 History 2 Principles 3 Reception 4 See also 5 References 6 External linksHistory EditIn an article in The Atlantic in March 2020 Adrian Vermeule suggested that originalism the idea that the meaning of the American Constitution was fixed at the time of its enactment which has been the principal legal theory of conservative judges and legal scholars for the past 50 years but which Vermeule now characterizes as merely a useful rhetorical and political expedient has outlived its usefulness and needs to be replaced by what he calls common good constitutionalism 3 Common good constitutionalism has garnered a mix of responses with many praising its recognition of classical legal theories while others fear that it could lead to judicial fiat 8 9 Notably Richard H Helmholz in a review of Common Good Constitutionalism described it as a serious contribution to some of the most pressing legal debates of our times 10 Jack Goldsmith has praised Common Good Constitutionalism as the most important book of American constitutional theory in many decades 8 However notable originalist scholar Randy Barnett criticized the theory as subversive of America s founding principles 11 Conservative columnist George F Will described Vermeule s common good constitutionalism as Christian authoritarianism muscular paternalism with government enforcing social solidarity for religious reasons 12 Notable common good scholars include Adrian Vermeule Conor Casey and Michael Foran 13 14 15 16 Principles EditThomas Aquinas defined law as an ordinance of reason made for the common good by him who has charge of the community and promulgated 17 Common good constitutionalism adopts this definition treating positive law as a promulgated ordinance of reason where ordinance of reason invokes that law which is ascertainable reason or the natural law 18 3 Natural law provides background legal principles such as do good and avoid evil that are not necessarily determinate as applied to concrete cases Positive law then is made when a public authority makes a practical determination within the scope of the natural law 18 For example public safety is furthered by having cars drive on one side of the road but nothing about public safety inherently requires choosing one side of the road or the other Thus within the requirements of public safety the public authority is free to determine a concrete application that is driving on the left or right side In the context of the judiciary interpretation of legal texts must then be made in light of the natural law principles made concrete by the text They must be reviewed for rationality but so long as the positive law does not offend reason the background natural law principles the judiciary should defer to the legislating authority 18 To return to the driving example to require driving on the left side of the road does not offend reason nor does driving on the right Both further the common good by promoting public roadway safety and thus either determination by the legislature should be deferred to Common good is defined not as a utilitarian aggregation of individual goods nor as a tyrannical subjugation of the individual to the community Rather it is the unification of individual and community goods that leads to personal and social flourishing 18 A Navy Marine Corps Court of Criminal Appeals judge wrote in his concurrence in United States v Tabor that t he classical judge would attempt to discern what common good is desired by the statute and recognize that a statute can have a purpose toward the good of the individual a purpose toward the good of the community and an additional good in harmonizing the interests between the two A statute a lex is an attempt to codify a higher law that a nation or a people all know to be true and good even if it were to limit individual freedom in certain circumstances 19 Thus individual goods or rights must be justified in light of their contribution to the flourishing of the community 2 Reception EditCommon good constitutionalism has divided opinion amongst scholars and lawyers Many natural lawyers have welcomed it as a valuable contribution to legal theory University of Chicago legal historian Richard Helmholz described Common Good Constitutionalism Polity 2022 as a serious contribution to some of the most pressing legal debates of our times written with clarity and skill 20 University of Texas law professor Sanford Levinson described it as truly an important book deserving wide readership and intense discussion 21 while University of Michigan law professor Richard Primus saw potential in its simple and powerful frame but felt the book stops short of fully describing the common good that Vermeule envisions 22 Writing in the Modern Law Review University of Glasgow legal scholar Michael Foran said the theory offers powerful critiques of the foundational assumptions of liberal constitutionalism 23 University of Georgia law professor Eric Segall wrote that common good constitutionalism offers a critique of the never ending debates between originalists and living constitutionalists debates that have not furthered constitutional discourse in a helpful manner 24 One scholar noted its potential relevance for environmental law stating that E nvironmental advocates can benefit both from considering the common good constitutionalist approach in its own right and as a catalyst for action 25 Various practicing lawyers have praised common good constitutionalism as positively contributing values and rationales that are perceived by some to be missing from the political and judicial discourse 26 27 28 29 Common good constitutionalism s grounding in a Catholic moral framework has led to charges that in practice it is inherently theocratic 30 David Dyzenhaus has heavily criticized Vermeule s conception of Common Good Constitutionalism hailing it an authoritarian idea seeking to instill Christian theocratic rule 31 He criticizes Vermeule for invoking justification via a body of allegedly timeless and universal principles that animate right wing Catholics and Evangelicals in the US and for worshipping the executive which can put those ideals into practice 32 Linda C McClain has criticized Common Good Constitutionalism for the moral positions which underpin the conception of the common good adopted by its advocates In particular the enthusiasm for restrictions on abortion and reproductive rights and heavy reliance on jurists who endorse the exclusion of women from full participation in civic political and economic life make her doubt whether women s rights are reasonably secure under the providence of the common good the prevalence of natural law values which promote segregation and discrimination and the fact that Vermeule and his associates are notably silent about problems like religiously inspired racism and white supremacy give rise to further concerns that Common Good Constitutionalism in practice advocates for a view of ethics palatable only for religious conservatives who share Vermeule s own moral values McClain expresses a profound doubt that a free and equal people would submit to the moral framework which common good constitutionalists promote 33 Former White House Counsel under Ronald Reagan Peter Wallison criticized Vermeule for failing to define the common good Wallison also stated that the political order formulated by common good constitutionalism is highly authoritarian perhaps even totalitarian citing Vermeule s assertion that Constitutional concepts such as liberty and equality need not be given libertarian or originalist readings 34 See also EditPolitical process theoryReferences Edit a b Vermeule Adrian 2020 03 31 Beyond Originalism The Atlantic Retrieved 2023 02 17 a b c Casey Conor Vermeule Adrian 2022 02 09 Myths of Common Good Constitutionalism Harvard Journal of Law and Public Policy 45 1 103 146 SSRN 4030763 a href Template Cite journal html title Template Cite journal cite journal a CS1 maint date and year link a b Vermeule Adrian 2020 03 31 Beyond Originalism The Atlantic Retrieved 2022 06 11 Frohnen Bruce P 14 April 2022 Common Good Constitutionalism and the Problem of Administrative Absolutism Ohio Northern University College of Law SSRN 4083882 Retrieved 13 June 2022 Vermeule Adrian The Common Good as a Universal Framework Balkinization Retrieved 29 August 2022 Baude William Sachs Stephen E The Common Good Manifesto harvardlawreview org Retrieved 2023 02 17 Critics Call It Theocratic and Authoritarian Young Conservatives Call It an Exciting New Legal Theory POLITICO Retrieved 2023 02 17 a b Common Good Constitutionalism Polity Retrieved 2022 06 11 The Future of Conservative Constitutionalism National Review 2021 09 17 Retrieved 2022 06 11 Marching Orders R H Helmholz First Things Retrieved 2022 06 11 Barnett Randy E 2020 04 03 Common Good Constitutionalism Reveals the Dangers of Any Non originalist Approach to the Constitution The Atlantic Retrieved 2022 06 11 Will George F May 29 2020 When American conservatism becomes un American The Washington Post Retrieved June 10 2022 CGC Symposium Harvard Journal of Law amp Public Policy 2022 08 30 Retrieved 2022 10 31 Casey Conor 2021 Common Good Constitutionalism and the New Debate over Constitutional Interpretation in the United States Public Law SSRN 3725068 Hammer Josh 2021 Common Good Originalism PDF Harvard Journal of Law amp Public Policy Explaining Common Good Originalism Does Not Help Its Case National Review 2021 08 19 Retrieved 2022 06 20 Aquinas Thomas Summa Theologica a b c d Vermeule Adrian 2022 Common good constitutionalism recovering the classical legal tradition Cambridge UK ISBN 978 1 5095 4887 3 OCLC 1266642815 a href Template Cite book html title Template Cite book cite book a CS1 maint location missing publisher link United States v Tabor NMCCA No 202100046 46 Helmholz Richard Marching Orders First Things Retrieved 29 August 2022 Levinson Sanford Adrian Vermeule s rejection of modern constitutional theory Balkinization Retrieved 29 August 2022 Primus Richard The Other 630 000 Words Balkinization Retrieved 29 August 2022 Foran Michael 2 August 2022 Rights Common Good and The Separation of Powers SSRN SSRN 4179424 Retrieved 29 August 2022 Segall Eric Ten Observations About Adrian Vermeule s Book Common Good Constitutionalism Dorf on Law Retrieved 29 August 2022 Quigley Brian Common Good Constitutionalism and the Future of Environmental Law PDF Vermont Journal of Environmental Law 23 4 349 373 Retrieved 29 August 2022 Whitehead Daniel A Jurisprudence of Hope Anchoring Truths Retrieved 29 August 2022 Blacklock Evelyn A Jurisprudential Red Pill Part II Anchoring Truths Retrieved 29 August 2022 Neu Jacob 5 August 2022 Common Good Constitutionalism for the Working Lawyer Ius amp Iustitium Retrieved 29 August 2022 Sabater Anibal August 2022 Lawyers as Common Good Servers Ius amp Iustitium Retrieved 29 August 2022 Amy Coney Barrett s Long Game The New Yorker 4 February 2022 Schmitten in the USA Verfassungsblog The Snake Charmers Balkinization The Common Good as a Universal Framework Review Common Good Constitutionalism American Enterprise Institute AEI Retrieved 2023 02 17 External links Edithttps iusetiustitium com Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Common good constitutionalism amp oldid 1171013177, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.