fbpx
Wikipedia

Schröder–Bernstein theorem

In set theory, the Schröder–Bernstein theorem states that, if there exist injective functions f : AB and g : BA between the sets A and B, then there exists a bijective function h : AB.

In terms of the cardinality of the two sets, this classically implies that if |A| ≤ |B| and |B| ≤ |A|, then |A| = |B|; that is, A and B are equipotent. This is a useful feature in the ordering of cardinal numbers.

The theorem is named after Felix Bernstein and Ernst Schröder. It is also known as the Cantor–Bernstein theorem or Cantor–Schröder–Bernstein theorem, after Georg Cantor, who first published it (albeit without proof).

Proof edit

 
König's definition of a bijection h:A → B from given example injections f:A → B and g:B → A. An element in A and B is denoted by a number and a letter, respectively. The sequence 3 → e → 6 → ... is an A-stopper, leading to the definitions h(3) = f(3) = e, h(6) = f(6), .... The sequence d → 5 → f → ... is a B-stopper, leading to h(5) = g−1(5) = d, .... The sequence ... → a → 1 → c → 4 → ... is doubly infinite, leading to h(1) = g−1(1) = a, h(4) = g−1(4) = c, .... The sequence b → 2 → b is cyclic, leading to h(2) = g−1(2) = b.

The following proof is attributed to Julius König.[1]

Assume without loss of generality that A and B are disjoint. For any a in A or b in B we can form a unique two-sided sequence of elements that are alternately in A and B, by repeatedly applying   and   to go from A to B and   and   to go from B to A (where defined; the inverses   and   are understood as partial functions.)

 

For any particular a, this sequence may terminate to the left or not, at a point where   or   is not defined.

By the fact that   and   are injective functions, each a in A and b in B is in exactly one such sequence to within identity: if an element occurs in two sequences, all elements to the left and to the right must be the same in both, by the definition of the sequences. Therefore, the sequences form a partition of the (disjoint) union of A and B. Hence it suffices to produce a bijection between the elements of A and B in each of the sequences separately, as follows:

Call a sequence an A-stopper if it stops at an element of A, or a B-stopper if it stops at an element of B. Otherwise, call it doubly infinite if all the elements are distinct or cyclic if it repeats. See the picture for examples.

  • For an A-stopper, the function   is a bijection between its elements in A and its elements in B.
  • For a B-stopper, the function   is a bijection between its elements in B and its elements in A.
  • For a doubly infinite sequence or a cyclic sequence, either   or   will do (  is used in the picture).

Examples edit

Bijective function from  
Note:   is the half open set from 0 to 1, including the boundary 0 and excluding the boundary 1.
Let   with   and   with   the two injective functions as in the previous procedure of proof.
In line with that procedure  
Then   is a bijective function from  .
Bijective function from  
Let   with  
Then for   one can use the expansions   and   with  
and now one can set   which defines an injective function  . (Example:  )
And therefore a bijective function   can be constructed with the use of   and  .
In this case   is still easy but already   gets quite complicated.
Note: Of course there's a more simple way by using the (already bijective) function definition  . Then   would be the empty set and   for all x.

History edit

The traditional name "Schröder–Bernstein" is based on two proofs published independently in 1898. Cantor is often added because he first stated the theorem in 1887, while Schröder's name is often omitted because his proof turned out to be flawed while the name of Richard Dedekind, who first proved it, is not connected with the theorem. According to Bernstein, Cantor had suggested the name equivalence theorem (Äquivalenzsatz).[2]

 
Cantor's first statement of the theorem (1887)[3]
  • 1887 Cantor publishes the theorem, however without proof.[3][2]
  • 1887 On July 11, Dedekind proves the theorem (not relying on the axiom of choice)[4] but neither publishes his proof nor tells Cantor about it. Ernst Zermelo discovered Dedekind's proof and in 1908[5] he publishes his own proof based on the chain theory from Dedekind's paper Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen?[2][6]
  • 1895 Cantor states the theorem in his first paper on set theory and transfinite numbers. He obtains it as an easy consequence of the linear order of cardinal numbers.[7][8][9] However, he could not prove the latter theorem, which is shown in 1915 to be equivalent to the axiom of choice by Friedrich Moritz Hartogs.[2][10]
  • 1896 Schröder announces a proof (as a corollary of a theorem by Jevons).[11]
  • 1897 Bernstein, a 19-year-old student in Cantor's Seminar, presents his proof.[12][13]
  • 1897 Almost simultaneously, but independently, Schröder finds a proof.[12][13]
  • 1897 After a visit by Bernstein, Dedekind independently proves the theorem a second time.
  • 1898 Bernstein's proof (not relying on the axiom of choice) is published by Émile Borel in his book on functions.[14] (Communicated by Cantor at the 1897 International Congress of Mathematicians in Zürich.) In the same year, the proof also appears in Bernstein's dissertation.[15][2]
  • 1898 Schröder publishes his proof[16] which, however, is shown to be faulty by Alwin Reinhold Korselt in 1902 (just before Schröder's death),[17] (confirmed by Schröder),[2][18] but Korselt's paper is published only in 1911.

Both proofs of Dedekind are based on his famous 1888 memoir Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? and derive it as a corollary of a proposition equivalent to statement C in Cantor's paper,[7] which reads A ⊆ B ⊆ C and |A| = |C| implies |A| = |B| = |C|. Cantor observed this property as early as 1882/83 during his studies in set theory and transfinite numbers and was therefore (implicitly) relying on the Axiom of Choice.

Prerequisites edit

The 1895 proof by Cantor relied, in effect, on the axiom of choice by inferring the result as a corollary of the well-ordering theorem.[8][9] However, König's proof given above shows that the result can also be proved without using the axiom of choice.

On the other hand, König's proof uses the principle of excluded middle to draw a conclusion through case analysis. As such, the above proof is not a constructive one. In fact, in a constructive set theory such as intuitionistic set theory  , which adopts the full axiom of separation but dispenses with the principle of excluded middle, assuming the Schröder–Bernstein theorem implies the latter.[19] In turn, there is no proof of König's conclusion in this or weaker constructive theories. Therefore, intuitionists do not accept the statement of the Schröder–Bernstein theorem.[20]

There is also a proof which uses Tarski's fixed point theorem.[21]

See also edit

Notes edit

  1. ^ J. König (1906). "Sur la théorie des ensembles". Comptes Rendus Hebdomadaires des Séances de l'Académie des Sciences. 143: 110–112.
  2. ^ a b c d e f Felix Hausdorff (2002), Egbert Brieskorn; Srishti D. Chatterji; et al. (eds.), Grundzüge der Mengenlehre (1. ed.), Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer, p. 587, ISBN 978-3-540-42224-2 – Original edition (1914)
  3. ^ a b Georg Cantor (1887), "Mitteilungen zur Lehre vom Transfiniten", Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, 91: 81–125
    Reprinted in: Georg Cantor (1932), Adolf Fraenkel (Lebenslauf); Ernst Zermelo (eds.), Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts, Berlin: Springer, pp. 378–439 Here: p.413 bottom
  4. ^ Richard Dedekind (1932), Robert Fricke; Emmy Noether; Øystein Ore (eds.), Gesammelte mathematische Werke, vol. 3, Braunschweig: Friedr. Vieweg & Sohn, pp. 447–449 (Ch.62)
  5. ^ Ernst Zermelo (1908), Felix Klein; Walther von Dyck; David Hilbert; Otto Blumenthal (eds.), "Untersuchungen über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I", Mathematische Annalen, 65 (2): 261–281, here: p.271–272, doi:10.1007/bf01449999, ISSN 0025-5831, S2CID 120085563
  6. ^ Richard Dedekind (1888), Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? (2., unchanged (1893) ed.), Braunschweig: Friedr. Vieweg & Sohn
  7. ^ a b Georg Cantor (1932), Adolf Fraenkel (Lebenslauf); Ernst Zermelo (eds.), Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts, Berlin: Springer, pp. 285 ("Satz B")
  8. ^ a b Georg Cantor (1895). "Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre (1)". Mathematische Annalen. 46 (4): 481–512 (Theorem see "Satz B", p.484). doi:10.1007/bf02124929. S2CID 177801164.
  9. ^ a b (Georg Cantor (1897). "Beiträge zur Begründung der transfiniten Mengenlehre (2)". Mathematische Annalen. 49 (2): 207–246. doi:10.1007/bf01444205. S2CID 121665994.)
  10. ^ Friedrich M. Hartogs (1915), Felix Klein; Walther von Dyck; David Hilbert; Otto Blumenthal (eds.), "Über das Problem der Wohlordnung", Mathematische Annalen, 76 (4): 438–443, doi:10.1007/bf01458215, ISSN 0025-5831, S2CID 121598654
  11. ^ Ernst Schröder (1896). "Über G. Cantorsche Sätze". Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker-Vereinigung. 5: 81–82.
  12. ^ a b Oliver Deiser (2010), Einführung in die Mengenlehre – Die Mengenlehre Georg Cantors und ihre Axiomatisierung durch Ernst Zermelo, Springer-Lehrbuch (3rd, corrected ed.), Berlin/Heidelberg: Springer, pp. 71, 501, doi:10.1007/978-3-642-01445-1, ISBN 978-3-642-01444-4
  13. ^ a b Patrick Suppes (1972), Axiomatic Set Theory (1. ed.), New York: Dover Publications, pp. 95 f, ISBN 978-0-486-61630-8
  14. ^ Émile Borel (1898), Leçons sur la théorie des fonctions, Paris: Gauthier-Villars et fils, pp. 103 ff
  15. ^ Felix Bernstein (1901), Untersuchungen aus der Mengenlehre, Halle a. S.: Buchdruckerei des Waisenhauses
    Reprinted in: Felix Bernstein (1905), Felix Klein; Walther von Dyck; David Hilbert (eds.), "Untersuchungen aus der Mengenlehre", Mathematische Annalen, 61 (1): 117–155, (Theorem see "Satz 1" on p.121), doi:10.1007/bf01457734, ISSN 0025-5831, S2CID 119658724
  16. ^ Ernst Schröder (1898), Kaiserliche Leopoldino-Carolinische Deutsche Akademie der Naturforscher (ed.), "Ueber zwei Definitionen der Endlichkeit und G. Cantor'sche Sätze", Nova Acta, 71 (6): 303–376 (proof: p.336–344)
  17. ^ Alwin R. Korselt (1911), Felix Klein; Walther von Dyck; David Hilbert; Otto Blumenthal (eds.), "Über einen Beweis des Äquivalenzsatzes", Mathematische Annalen, 70 (2): 294–296, doi:10.1007/bf01461161, ISSN 0025-5831, S2CID 119757900
  18. ^ Korselt (1911), p.295
  19. ^ Pradic, Pierre; Brown, Chad E. (2019). "Cantor-Bernstein implies Excluded Middle". arXiv:1904.09193 [math.LO].
  20. ^ Ettore Carruccio (2006). Mathematics and Logic in History and in Contemporary Thought. Transaction Publishers. p. 354. ISBN 978-0-202-30850-0.
  21. ^ R. Uhl, "Tarski's Fixed Point Theorem", from MathWorld–a Wolfram Web Resource, created by Eric W. Weisstein. (Example 3)

References edit

External links edit

schröder, bernstein, theorem, theory, states, that, there, exist, injective, functions, between, sets, then, there, exists, bijective, function, terms, cardinality, sets, this, classically, implies, that, then, that, equipotent, this, useful, feature, ordering. In set theory the Schroder Bernstein theorem states that if there exist injective functions f A B and g B A between the sets A and B then there exists a bijective function h A B In terms of the cardinality of the two sets this classically implies that if A B and B A then A B that is A and B are equipotent This is a useful feature in the ordering of cardinal numbers The theorem is named after Felix Bernstein and Ernst Schroder It is also known as the Cantor Bernstein theorem or Cantor Schroder Bernstein theorem after Georg Cantor who first published it albeit without proof Contents 1 Proof 1 1 Examples 2 History 3 Prerequisites 4 See also 5 Notes 6 References 7 External linksProof edit nbsp Konig s definition of a bijection h A B from given example injections f A B and g B A An element in A and B is denoted by a number and a letter respectively The sequence 3 e 6 is an A stopper leading to the definitions h 3 f 3 e h 6 f 6 The sequence d 5 f is a B stopper leading to h 5 g 1 5 d The sequence a 1 c 4 is doubly infinite leading to h 1 g 1 1 a h 4 g 1 4 c The sequence b 2 b is cyclic leading to h 2 g 1 2 b The following proof is attributed to Julius Konig 1 Assume without loss of generality that A and B are disjoint For any a in A or b in B we can form a unique two sided sequence of elements that are alternately in A and B by repeatedly applying f displaystyle f nbsp and g 1 displaystyle g 1 nbsp to go from A to B and g displaystyle g nbsp and f 1 displaystyle f 1 nbsp to go from B to A where defined the inverses f 1 displaystyle f 1 nbsp and g 1 displaystyle g 1 nbsp are understood as partial functions f 1 g 1 a g 1 a a f a g f a displaystyle cdots rightarrow f 1 g 1 a rightarrow g 1 a rightarrow a rightarrow f a rightarrow g f a rightarrow cdots nbsp For any particular a this sequence may terminate to the left or not at a point where f 1 displaystyle f 1 nbsp or g 1 displaystyle g 1 nbsp is not defined By the fact that f displaystyle f nbsp and g displaystyle g nbsp are injective functions each a in A and b in B is in exactly one such sequence to within identity if an element occurs in two sequences all elements to the left and to the right must be the same in both by the definition of the sequences Therefore the sequences form a partition of the disjoint union of A and B Hence it suffices to produce a bijection between the elements of A and B in each of the sequences separately as follows Call a sequence an A stopper if it stops at an element of A or a B stopper if it stops at an element of B Otherwise call it doubly infinite if all the elements are distinct or cyclic if it repeats See the picture for examples For an A stopper the function f displaystyle f nbsp is a bijection between its elements in A and its elements in B For a B stopper the function g displaystyle g nbsp is a bijection between its elements in B and its elements in A For a doubly infinite sequence or a cyclic sequence either f displaystyle f nbsp or g displaystyle g nbsp will do g displaystyle g nbsp is used in the picture Examples edit Bijective function from 0 1 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 to 0 1 nbsp Note 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 nbsp is the half open set from 0 to 1 including the boundary 0 and excluding the boundary 1 Let f 0 1 0 1 displaystyle f 0 1 to 0 1 nbsp with f x x 2 displaystyle f x x 2 nbsp and g 0 1 0 1 displaystyle g 0 1 to 0 1 nbsp with g x x displaystyle g x x nbsp the two injective functions as in the previous procedure of proof In line with that procedure C 0 1 C k 2 k C k 0 C k 1 1 2 1 4 1 8 displaystyle C 0 1 C k 2 k C bigcup k 0 infty C k 1 tfrac 1 2 tfrac 1 4 tfrac 1 8 nbsp Then h x x 2 f o r x C x f o r x 0 1 C displaystyle h x begin cases frac x 2 amp mathrm for x in C x amp mathrm for x in 0 1 setminus C end cases nbsp is a bijective function from 0 1 0 1 displaystyle 0 1 to 0 1 nbsp Bijective function from 0 2 0 1 2 displaystyle 0 2 to 0 1 2 nbsp Let f 0 2 0 1 2 displaystyle f 0 2 to 0 1 2 nbsp with f x x 2 0 displaystyle f x x 2 0 nbsp Then for x y 0 1 2 displaystyle x y in 0 1 2 nbsp one can use the expansions x k 1 a k 10 k displaystyle x sum k 1 infty a k cdot 10 k nbsp and y k 1 b k 10 k displaystyle y sum k 1 infty b k cdot 10 k nbsp with a k b k 0 1 9 displaystyle a k b k in 0 1 9 nbsp and now one can set g x y k 1 10 a k b k 10 2 k displaystyle g x y sum k 1 infty 10 cdot a k b k cdot 10 2k nbsp which defines an injective function 0 1 2 0 2 displaystyle 0 1 2 to 0 2 nbsp Example g 1 3 2 3 0 363636 12 33 displaystyle g tfrac 1 3 tfrac 2 3 0 363636 tfrac 12 33 nbsp And therefore a bijective function h displaystyle h nbsp can be constructed with the use of f x displaystyle f x nbsp and g 1 x displaystyle g 1 x nbsp In this case C 0 1 2 displaystyle C 0 1 2 nbsp is still easy but already C 1 g f C 0 g x 0 x 1 2 1 displaystyle C 1 g f C 0 g x 0 x in tfrac 1 2 1 nbsp gets quite complicated Note Of course there s a more simple way by using the already bijective function definition g 2 x y 2 k 1 10 a k b k 10 2 k displaystyle g 2 x y 2 cdot sum k 1 infty 10 cdot a k b k cdot 10 2k nbsp Then C displaystyle C nbsp would be the empty set and h x g 2 1 x displaystyle h x g 2 1 x nbsp for all x History editThe traditional name Schroder Bernstein is based on two proofs published independently in 1898 Cantor is often added because he first stated the theorem in 1887 while Schroder s name is often omitted because his proof turned out to be flawed while the name of Richard Dedekind who first proved it is not connected with the theorem According to Bernstein Cantor had suggested the name equivalence theorem Aquivalenzsatz 2 nbsp Cantor s first statement of the theorem 1887 3 1887 Cantor publishes the theorem however without proof 3 2 1887 On July 11 Dedekind proves the theorem not relying on the axiom of choice 4 but neither publishes his proof nor tells Cantor about it Ernst Zermelo discovered Dedekind s proof and in 1908 5 he publishes his own proof based on the chain theory from Dedekind s paper Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen 2 6 1895 Cantor states the theorem in his first paper on set theory and transfinite numbers He obtains it as an easy consequence of the linear order of cardinal numbers 7 8 9 However he could not prove the latter theorem which is shown in 1915 to be equivalent to the axiom of choice by Friedrich Moritz Hartogs 2 10 1896 Schroder announces a proof as a corollary of a theorem by Jevons 11 1897 Bernstein a 19 year old student in Cantor s Seminar presents his proof 12 13 1897 Almost simultaneously but independently Schroder finds a proof 12 13 1897 After a visit by Bernstein Dedekind independently proves the theorem a second time 1898 Bernstein s proof not relying on the axiom of choice is published by Emile Borel in his book on functions 14 Communicated by Cantor at the 1897 International Congress of Mathematicians in Zurich In the same year the proof also appears in Bernstein s dissertation 15 2 1898 Schroder publishes his proof 16 which however is shown to be faulty by Alwin Reinhold Korselt in 1902 just before Schroder s death 17 confirmed by Schroder 2 18 but Korselt s paper is published only in 1911 Both proofs of Dedekind are based on his famous 1888 memoir Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen and derive it as a corollary of a proposition equivalent to statement C in Cantor s paper 7 which reads A B C and A C implies A B C Cantor observed this property as early as 1882 83 during his studies in set theory and transfinite numbers and was therefore implicitly relying on the Axiom of Choice Prerequisites editThe 1895 proof by Cantor relied in effect on the axiom of choice by inferring the result as a corollary of the well ordering theorem 8 9 However Konig s proof given above shows that the result can also be proved without using the axiom of choice On the other hand Konig s proof uses the principle of excluded middle to draw a conclusion through case analysis As such the above proof is not a constructive one In fact in a constructive set theory such as intuitionistic set theory I Z F displaystyle mathsf IZF nbsp which adopts the full axiom of separation but dispenses with the principle of excluded middle assuming the Schroder Bernstein theorem implies the latter 19 In turn there is no proof of Konig s conclusion in this or weaker constructive theories Therefore intuitionists do not accept the statement of the Schroder Bernstein theorem 20 There is also a proof which uses Tarski s fixed point theorem 21 See also editMyhill isomorphism theorem Netto s theorem according to which the bijections constructed by the Schroder Bernstein theorem between spaces of different dimensions cannot be continuous Schroder Bernstein theorem for measurable spaces Schroder Bernstein theorems for operator algebras Schroder Bernstein propertyNotes edit J Konig 1906 Sur la theorie des ensembles Comptes Rendus Hebdomadaires des Seances de l Academie des Sciences 143 110 112 a b c d e f Felix Hausdorff 2002 Egbert Brieskorn Srishti D Chatterji et al eds Grundzuge der Mengenlehre 1 ed Berlin Heidelberg Springer p 587 ISBN 978 3 540 42224 2 Original edition 1914 a b Georg Cantor 1887 Mitteilungen zur Lehre vom Transfiniten Zeitschrift fur Philosophie und philosophische Kritik 91 81 125 Reprinted in Georg Cantor 1932 Adolf Fraenkel Lebenslauf Ernst Zermelo eds Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts Berlin Springer pp 378 439 Here p 413 bottom Richard Dedekind 1932 Robert Fricke Emmy Noether Oystein Ore eds Gesammelte mathematische Werke vol 3 Braunschweig Friedr Vieweg amp Sohn pp 447 449 Ch 62 Ernst Zermelo 1908 Felix Klein Walther von Dyck David Hilbert Otto Blumenthal eds Untersuchungen uber die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre I Mathematische Annalen 65 2 261 281 here p 271 272 doi 10 1007 bf01449999 ISSN 0025 5831 S2CID 120085563 Richard Dedekind 1888 Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen 2 unchanged 1893 ed Braunschweig Friedr Vieweg amp Sohn a b Georg Cantor 1932 Adolf Fraenkel Lebenslauf Ernst Zermelo eds Gesammelte Abhandlungen mathematischen und philosophischen Inhalts Berlin Springer pp 285 Satz B a b Georg Cantor 1895 Beitrage zur Begrundung der transfiniten Mengenlehre 1 Mathematische Annalen 46 4 481 512 Theorem see Satz B p 484 doi 10 1007 bf02124929 S2CID 177801164 a b Georg Cantor 1897 Beitrage zur Begrundung der transfiniten Mengenlehre 2 Mathematische Annalen 49 2 207 246 doi 10 1007 bf01444205 S2CID 121665994 Friedrich M Hartogs 1915 Felix Klein Walther von Dyck David Hilbert Otto Blumenthal eds Uber das Problem der Wohlordnung Mathematische Annalen 76 4 438 443 doi 10 1007 bf01458215 ISSN 0025 5831 S2CID 121598654 Ernst Schroder 1896 Uber G Cantorsche Satze Jahresbericht der Deutschen Mathematiker Vereinigung 5 81 82 a b Oliver Deiser 2010 Einfuhrung in die Mengenlehre Die Mengenlehre Georg Cantors und ihre Axiomatisierung durch Ernst Zermelo Springer Lehrbuch 3rd corrected ed Berlin Heidelberg Springer pp 71 501 doi 10 1007 978 3 642 01445 1 ISBN 978 3 642 01444 4 a b Patrick Suppes 1972 Axiomatic Set Theory 1 ed New York Dover Publications pp 95 f ISBN 978 0 486 61630 8 Emile Borel 1898 Lecons sur la theorie des fonctions Paris Gauthier Villars et fils pp 103 ff Felix Bernstein 1901 Untersuchungen aus der Mengenlehre Halle a S Buchdruckerei des Waisenhauses Reprinted in Felix Bernstein 1905 Felix Klein Walther von Dyck David Hilbert eds Untersuchungen aus der Mengenlehre Mathematische Annalen 61 1 117 155 Theorem see Satz 1 on p 121 doi 10 1007 bf01457734 ISSN 0025 5831 S2CID 119658724 Ernst Schroder 1898 Kaiserliche Leopoldino Carolinische Deutsche Akademie der Naturforscher ed Ueber zwei Definitionen der Endlichkeit und G Cantor sche Satze Nova Acta 71 6 303 376 proof p 336 344 Alwin R Korselt 1911 Felix Klein Walther von Dyck David Hilbert Otto Blumenthal eds Uber einen Beweis des Aquivalenzsatzes Mathematische Annalen 70 2 294 296 doi 10 1007 bf01461161 ISSN 0025 5831 S2CID 119757900 Korselt 1911 p 295 Pradic Pierre Brown Chad E 2019 Cantor Bernstein implies Excluded Middle arXiv 1904 09193 math LO Ettore Carruccio 2006 Mathematics and Logic in History and in Contemporary Thought Transaction Publishers p 354 ISBN 978 0 202 30850 0 R Uhl Tarski s Fixed Point Theorem from MathWorld a Wolfram Web Resource created by Eric W Weisstein Example 3 References editMartin Aigner amp Gunter M Ziegler 1998 Proofs from THE BOOK 3 Analysis Sets and functions Springer books MR1723092 fifth edition 2014 MR3288091 sixth edition 2018 MR3823190 Hinkis Arie 2013 Proofs of the Cantor Bernstein theorem A mathematical excursion Science Networks Historical Studies vol 45 Heidelberg Birkhauser Springer doi 10 1007 978 3 0348 0224 6 ISBN 978 3 0348 0223 9 MR 3026479 Searcoid Michael o 2013 On the history and mathematics of the equivalence theorem Mathematical Proceedings of the Royal Irish Academy 113A 2 151 68 doi 10 1353 mpr 2013 0006 JSTOR 42912521 S2CID 245841055 External links editWeisstein Eric W Schroder Bernstein Theorem MathWorld Cantor Schroeder Bernstein theorem at the nLab Cantor Bernstein s Theorem in a Semiring by Marcel Crabbe This article incorporates material from the Citizendium article Schroder Bernstein theorem which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution ShareAlike 3 0 Unported License but not under the GFDL Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Schroder Bernstein theorem amp oldid 1212614806, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.