fbpx
Wikipedia

Definition

A definition is a statement of the meaning of a term (a word, phrase, or other set of symbols).[1][2] Definitions can be classified into two large categories: intensional definitions (which try to give the sense of a term), and extensional definitions (which try to list the objects that a term describes).[3] Another important category of definitions is the class of ostensive definitions, which convey the meaning of a term by pointing out examples. A term may have many different senses and multiple meanings, and thus require multiple definitions.[4][a]

A definition states the meaning of a word using other words. This is sometimes challenging. Common dictionaries contain lexical descriptive definitions, but there are various types of definition – all with different purposes and focuses.

In mathematics, a definition is used to give a precise meaning to a new term, by describing a condition which unambiguously qualifies what a mathematical term is and is not. Definitions and axioms form the basis on which all of modern mathematics is to be constructed.[5]

Basic terminology

In modern usage, a definition is something, typically expressed in words, that attaches a meaning to a word or group of words. The word or group of words that is to be defined is called the definiendum, and the word, group of words, or action that defines it is called the definiens.[6] For example, in the definition "An elephant is a large gray animal native to Asia and Africa", the word "elephant" is the definiendum, and everything after the word "is" is the definiens.[7]

The definiens is not the meaning of the word defined, but is instead something that conveys the same meaning as that word.[7]

There are many sub-types of definitions, often specific to a given field of knowledge or study. These include, among many others, lexical definitions, or the common dictionary definitions of words already in a language; demonstrative definitions, which define something by pointing to an example of it ("This," [said while pointing to a large grey animal], "is an Asian elephant."); and precising definitions, which reduce the vagueness of a word, typically in some special sense ("'Large', among female Asian elephants, is any individual weighing over 5,500 pounds.").[7]

Intensional definitions vs extensional definitions

An intensional definition, also called a connotative definition, specifies the necessary and sufficient conditions for a thing to be a member of a specific set.[3] Any definition that attempts to set out the essence of something, such as that by genus and differentia, is an intensional definition.

An extensional definition, also called a denotative definition, of a concept or term specifies its extension. It is a list naming every object that is a member of a specific set.[3]

Thus, the "seven deadly sins" can be defined intensionally as those singled out by Pope Gregory I as particularly destructive of the life of grace and charity within a person, thus creating the threat of eternal damnation. An extensional definition, on the other hand, would be the list of wrath, greed, sloth, pride, lust, envy, and gluttony. In contrast, while an intensional definition of "Prime Minister" might be "the most senior minister of a cabinet in the executive branch of parliamentary government", an extensional definition is not possible since it is not known who the future prime ministers will be (even though all prime ministers from the past and present can be listed).

Classes of intensional definitions

A genus–differentia definition is a type of intensional definition that takes a large category (the genus) and narrows it down to a smaller category by a distinguishing characteristic (i.e. the differentia).[8]

More formally, a genus–differentia definition consists of:

  1. a genus (or family): An existing definition that serves as a portion of the new definition; all definitions with the same genus are considered members of that genus.
  2. the differentia: The portion of the new definition that is not provided by the genus.[6]

For example, consider the following genus–differentia definitions:

  • a triangle: A plane figure that has three straight bounding sides.
  • a quadrilateral: A plane figure that has four straight bounding sides.

Those definitions can be expressed as a genus ("a plane figure") and two differentiae ("that has three straight bounding sides" and "that has four straight bounding sides", respectively).

It is also possible to have two different genus–differentia definitions that describe the same term, especially when the term describes the overlap of two large categories. For instance, both of these genus–differentia definitions of "square" are equally acceptable:

Thus, a "square" is a member of both genera (the plural of genus): the genus "rectangle" and the genus "rhombus".

Classes of extensional definitions

One important form of the extensional definition is ostensive definition. This gives the meaning of a term by pointing, in the case of an individual, to the thing itself, or in the case of a class, to examples of the right kind. For example, one can explain who Alice (an individual) is, by pointing her out to another; or what a rabbit (a class) is, by pointing at several and expecting another to understand. The process of ostensive definition itself was critically appraised by Ludwig Wittgenstein.[9]

An enumerative definition of a concept or a term is an extensional definition that gives an explicit and exhaustive listing of all the objects that fall under the concept or term in question. Enumerative definitions are only possible for finite sets (and in fact only practical for relatively small sets).

Divisio and partitio

Divisio and partitio are classical terms for definitions. A partitio is simply an intensional definition. A divisio is not an extensional definition, but an exhaustive list of subsets of a set, in the sense that every member of the "divided" set is a member of one of the subsets. An extreme form of divisio lists all sets whose only member is a member of the "divided" set. The difference between this and an extensional definition is that extensional definitions list members, and not subsets.[10]

Nominal definitions vs real definitions

In classical thought, a definition was taken to be a statement of the essence of a thing. Aristotle had it that an object's essential attributes form its "essential nature", and that a definition of the object must include these essential attributes.[11]

The idea that a definition should state the essence of a thing led to the distinction between nominal and real essence—a distinction originating with Aristotle. In the Posterior Analytics,[12] he says that the meaning of a made-up name can be known (he gives the example "goat stag") without knowing what he calls the "essential nature" of the thing that the name would denote (if there were such a thing). This led medieval logicians to distinguish between what they called the quid nominis, or the "whatness of the name", and the underlying nature common to all the things it names, which they called the quid rei, or the "whatness of the thing".[13] The name "hobbit", for example, is perfectly meaningful. It has a quid nominis, but one could not know the real nature of hobbits, and so the quid rei of hobbits cannot be known. By contrast, the name "man" denotes real things (men) that have a certain quid rei. The meaning of a name is distinct from the nature that a thing must have in order that the name apply to it.

This leads to a corresponding distinction between nominal and real definitions. A nominal definition is the definition explaining what a word means (i.e., which says what the "nominal essence" is), and is definition in the classical sense as given above. A real definition, by contrast, is one expressing the real nature or quid rei of the thing.

This preoccupation with essence dissipated in much of modern philosophy. Analytic philosophy, in particular, is critical of attempts to elucidate the essence of a thing. Russell described essence as "a hopelessly muddle-headed notion".[14]

More recently Kripke's formalisation of possible world semantics in modal logic led to a new approach to essentialism. Insofar as the essential properties of a thing are necessary to it, they are those things that it possesses in all possible worlds. Kripke refers to names used in this way as rigid designators.

Operational vs. theoretical definitions

A definition may also be classified as an operational definition or theoretical definition.

Terms with multiple definitions

Homonyms

A homonym is, in the strict sense, one of a group of words that share the same spelling and pronunciation but have different meanings.[15] Thus homonyms are simultaneously homographs (words that share the same spelling, regardless of their pronunciation) and homophones (words that share the same pronunciation, regardless of their spelling). The state of being a homonym is called homonymy. Examples of homonyms are the pair stalk (part of a plant) and stalk (follow/harass a person) and the pair left (past tense of leave) and left (opposite of right). A distinction is sometimes made between "true" homonyms, which are unrelated in origin, such as skate (glide on ice) and skate (the fish), and polysemous homonyms, or polysemes, which have a shared origin, such as mouth (of a river) and mouth (of an animal).[16][17]

Polysemes

Polysemy is the capacity for a sign (such as a word, phrase, or symbol) to have multiple meanings (that is, multiple semes or sememes and thus multiple senses), usually related by contiguity of meaning within a semantic field. It is thus usually regarded as distinct from homonymy, in which the multiple meanings of a word may be unconnected or unrelated.

In logic and mathematics

In mathematics, definitions are generally not used to describe existing terms, but to describe or characterize a concept.[18] For naming the object of a definition mathematicians can use either a neologism (this was mainly the case in the past) or words or phrases of the common language (this is generally the case in modern mathematics). The precise meaning of a term given by a mathematical definition is often different than the English definition of the word used,[19] which can lead to confusion, particularly when the meanings are close. For example a set is not exactly the same thing in mathematics and in common language. In some case, the word used can be misleading; for example, a real number has nothing more (or less) real than an imaginary number. Frequently, a definition uses a phrase built with common English words, which has no meaning outside mathematics, such as primitive group or irreducible variety.

In first-order logic definitions are usually introduced using extension by definition (so using a metalogic). On the other hand, lambda-calculi are a kind of logic where the definitions are included as the feature of the formal system itself.

Classification

Authors have used different terms to classify definitions used in formal languages like mathematics. Norman Swartz classifies a definition as "stipulative" if it is intended to guide a specific discussion. A stipulative definition might be considered a temporary, working definition, and can only be disproved by showing a logical contradiction.[20] In contrast, a "descriptive" definition can be shown to be "right" or "wrong" with reference to general usage.

Swartz defines a precising definition as one that extends the descriptive dictionary definition (lexical definition) for a specific purpose by including additional criteria. A precising definition narrows the set of things that meet the definition.

C.L. Stevenson has identified persuasive definition as a form of stipulative definition which purports to state the "true" or "commonly accepted" meaning of a term, while in reality stipulating an altered use (perhaps as an argument for some specific belief). Stevenson has also noted that some definitions are "legal" or "coercive" – their object is to create or alter rights, duties, or crimes.[21]

Recursive definitions

A recursive definition, sometimes also called an inductive definition, is one that defines a word in terms of itself, so to speak, albeit in a useful way. Normally this consists of three steps:

  1. At least one thing is stated to be a member of the set being defined; this is sometimes called a "base set".
  2. All things bearing a certain relation to other members of the set are also to count as members of the set. It is this step that makes the definition recursive.
  3. All other things are excluded from the set

For instance, we could define a natural number as follows (after Peano):

  1. "0" is a natural number.
  2. Each natural number has a unique successor, such that:
    • the successor of a natural number is also a natural number;
    • distinct natural numbers have distinct successors;
    • no natural number is succeeded by "0".
  3. Nothing else is a natural number.

So "0" will have exactly one successor, which for convenience can be called "1". In turn, "1" will have exactly one successor, which could be called "2", and so on. Notice that the second condition in the definition itself refers to natural numbers, and hence involves self-reference. Although this sort of definition involves a form of circularity, it is not vicious, and the definition has been quite successful.

In the same way, we can define ancestor as follows:

  1. A parent is an ancestor.
  2. A parent of an ancestor is an ancestor.
  3. Nothing else is an ancestor.

Or simply: an ancestor is a parent or a parent of an ancestor.

In medicine

In medical dictionaries, guidelines and other consensus statements and classifications, definitions should as far as possible be:

  • simple and easy to understand,[22] preferably even by the general public;[23]
  • useful clinically[23] or in related areas where the definition will be used;[22]
  • specific[22] (that is, by reading the definition only, it should ideally not be possible to refer to any other entity than that being defined);
  • measurable;[22]
  • a reflection of current scientific knowledge.[22][23]

Problems

Certain rules have traditionally been given for definitions (in particular, genus-differentia definitions).[24][25][26][27]

  1. A definition must set out the essential attributes of the thing defined.
  2. Definitions should avoid circularity. To define a horse as "a member of the species equus" would convey no information whatsoever. For this reason, Locke adds that a definition of a term must not consist of terms which are synonymous with it. This would be a circular definition, a circulus in definiendo. Note, however, that it is acceptable to define two relative terms in respect of each other. Clearly, we cannot define "antecedent" without using the term "consequent", nor conversely.
  3. The definition must not be too wide or too narrow. It must be applicable to everything to which the defined term applies (i.e. not miss anything out), and to nothing else (i.e. not include any things to which the defined term would not truly apply).
  4. The definition must not be obscure. The purpose of a definition is to explain the meaning of a term which may be obscure or difficult, by the use of terms that are commonly understood and whose meaning is clear. The violation of this rule is known by the Latin term obscurum per obscurius. However, sometimes scientific and philosophical terms are difficult to define without obscurity.
  5. A definition should not be negative where it can be positive. We should not define "wisdom" as the absence of folly, or a healthy thing as whatever is not sick. Sometimes this is unavoidable, however. For example, it appears difficult to define blindness in positive terms rather than as "the absence of sight in a creature that is normally sighted".

Fallacies of definition

Limitations of definition

Given that a natural language such as English contains, at any given time, a finite number of words, any comprehensive list of definitions must either be circular or rely upon primitive notions. If every term of every definiens must itself be defined, "where at last should we stop?"[28][29] A dictionary, for instance, insofar as it is a comprehensive list of lexical definitions, must resort to circularity.[30][31][32]

Many philosophers have chosen instead to leave some terms undefined. The scholastic philosophers claimed that the highest genera (called the ten generalissima) cannot be defined, since a higher genus cannot be assigned under which they may fall. Thus being, unity and similar concepts cannot be defined.[25] Locke supposes in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding[33] that the names of simple concepts do not admit of any definition. More recently Bertrand Russell sought to develop a formal language based on logical atoms. Other philosophers, notably Wittgenstein, rejected the need for any undefined simples. Wittgenstein pointed out in his Philosophical Investigations that what counts as a "simple" in one circumstance might not do so in another.[34] He rejected the very idea that every explanation of the meaning of a term needed itself to be explained: "As though an explanation hung in the air unless supported by another one",[35] claiming instead that explanation of a term is only needed to avoid misunderstanding.

Locke and Mill also argued that individuals cannot be defined. Names are learned by connecting an idea with a sound, so that speaker and hearer have the same idea when the same word is used.[36] This is not possible when no one else is acquainted with the particular thing that has "fallen under our notice".[37] Russell offered his theory of descriptions in part as a way of defining a proper name, the definition being given by a definite description that "picks out" exactly one individual. Saul Kripke pointed to difficulties with this approach, especially in relation to modality, in his book Naming and Necessity.

There is a presumption in the classic example of a definition that the definiens can be stated. Wittgenstein argued that for some terms this is not the case.[38] The examples he used include game, number and family. In such cases, he argued, there is no fixed boundary that can be used to provide a definition. Rather, the items are grouped together because of a family resemblance. For terms such as these it is not possible and indeed not necessary to state a definition; rather, one simply comes to understand the use of the term.[b]

See also

Notes

  1. ^ Terms with the same pronunciation and spelling but unrelated meanings are called homonyms, while terms with the same spelling and pronunciation and related meanings are called polysemes.
  2. ^ Note that one learns inductively, from ostensive definition, in the same way, as in the Ramsey–Lewis method.

References

  1. ^ Bickenbach, Jerome E., and Jacqueline M. Davies. Good reasons for better arguments: An introduction to the skills and values of critical thinking. Broadview Press, 1996. p. 49
  2. ^ "Definition of definition | Dictionary.com". www.dictionary.com. Retrieved 2019-11-28.
  3. ^ a b c Lyons, John. "Semantics, vol. I." Cambridge: Cambridge (1977). p.158 and on.
  4. ^ Dooly, Melinda. Semantics and Pragmatics of English: Teaching English as a Foreign Language. Univ. Autònoma de Barcelona, 2006. p.48 and on
  5. ^ Richard J. Rossi (2011) Theorems, Corollaries, Lemmas, and Methods of Proof. John Wiley & Sons p.4
  6. ^ a b "DEFINITIONS". beisecker.faculty.unlv.edu. Retrieved 2019-11-28.
  7. ^ a b c Hurley, Patrick J. (2006). "Language: Meaning and Definition". A Concise Introduction to Logic (9 ed.). Wadsworth. pp. 86–91.
  8. ^ Bussler, Christoph, and Dieter Fensel, eds. Artificial Intelligence: Methodology, Systems and Applications: 11th International Conference, AIMSA 2004: Proceedings. Springer-Verlag, 2004. p.6
  9. ^ Philosophical investigations, Part 1 §27–34
  10. ^ Katerina Ierodiakonou, "The Stoic Division of Philosophy", in Phronesis: A Journal for Ancient Philosophy, Volume 38, Number 1, 1993, pp. 57–74.
  11. ^ Posterior Analytics, Bk 1 c. 4
  12. ^ Posterior Analytics Bk 2 c. 7
  13. ^ . Early modern philosophers like Locke used the corresponding English terms "nominal essence" and "real essence".
  14. ^ A History of Western Philosophy, p. 210.
  15. ^ homonym, Random House Unabridged Dictionary at dictionary.com
  16. ^ . Pandora.cii.wwu.edu. Archived from the original on 2013-06-17. Retrieved 2013-04-23.
  17. ^ Semantics: a coursebook, p. 123, James R. Hurford and Brendan Heasley, Cambridge University Press, 1983
  18. ^ David Hunter (2010) Essentials of Discrete Mathematics. Jones & Bartlett Publishers, Section 14.1
  19. ^ Kevin Houston (2009) How to Think Like a Mathematician: A Companion to Undergraduate Mathematics. Cambridge University Press, p. 104
  20. ^ "Norman Swartz - Biography". sfu.ca.
  21. ^ Stevenson, C.L., Ethics and Language, Connecticut 1944
  22. ^ a b c d e McPherson, M.; Arango, P.; Fox, H.; Lauver, C.; McManus, M.; Newacheck, P. W.; Perrin, J. M.; Shonkoff, J. P.; Strickland, B. (1998). "A new definition of children with special health care needs". Pediatrics. 102 (1 Pt 1): 137–140. doi:10.1542/peds.102.1.137. PMID 9714637. S2CID 30160426.
  23. ^ a b c Morse, R. M.; Flavin, D. K. (1992). "The Definition of Alcoholism". JAMA. 268 (8): 1012–1014. doi:10.1001/jama.1992.03490080086030. PMID 1501306.
  24. ^ Copi 1982 pp 165–169
  25. ^ a b Joyce, Ch. X
  26. ^ Joseph, Ch. V
  27. ^ Macagno & Walton 2014, Ch. III
  28. ^ Locke, Essay, Bk. III, Ch. iv, 5
  29. ^ This problem parallels the diallelus, but leads to scepticism about meaning rather than knowledge.
  30. ^ Generally lexicographers seek to avoid circularity wherever possible, but the definitions of words such as "the" and "a" use those words and are therefore circular. [1] [2] Lexicographer Sidney I. Landau's essay "Sexual Intercourse in American College Dictionaries" provides other examples of circularity in dictionary definitions. (McKean, p. 73–77)
  31. ^ An exercise suggested by J. L. Austin involved taking up a dictionary and finding a selection of terms relating to the key concept, then looking up each of the words in the explanation of their meaning. Then, iterating this process until the list of words begins to repeat, closing in a "family circle" of words relating to the key concept.
    (A plea for excuses in Philosophical Papers. Ed. J. O. Urmson and G. J. Warnock. Oxford: Oxford UP, 1961. 1979.)
  32. ^ In the game of Vish, players compete to find circularity in a dictionary.
  33. ^ Locke, Essay, Bk. III, Ch. iv
  34. ^ See especially Philosophical Investigations Part 1 §48
  35. ^ He continues: "Whereas an explanation may indeed rest on another one that has been given, but none stands in need of another – unless we require it to prevent a misunderstanding. One might say: an explanation serves to remove or to avert a misunderstanding – one, that is, that would occur but for the explanation; not every one I can imagine." Philosophical Investigations, Part 1 §87, italics in original
  36. ^ This theory of meaning is one of the targets of the private language argument
  37. ^ Locke, Essay, Bk. III, Ch. iii, 3
  38. ^ Philosophical Investigations
  • Copi, Irving (1982). Introduction to Logic. New York: Macmillan. ISBN 0-02-977520-5.
  • Joseph, Horace William Brindley (1916). An Introduction to Logic, 2nd edition. Clarendon Press repr. Paper Tiger. ISBN 1-889439-17-7. (full text of 1st ed. (1906))
  • Joyce, George Hayward (1926). Principles of logic, 3d ed., new impression. London, New York: Longmans, Green and co. (worldcat) (full text of 2nd ed. (1916))
  • Locke, John (1690). An Essay Concerning Human Understanding. ISBN 0-14-043482-8. (full text: vol 1, vol 2)
  • McKean, Erin (2001). Verbatim: From the bawdy to the sublime, the best writing on language for word lovers, grammar mavens, and armchair linguists. Harvest Books. ISBN 0-15-601209-X.
  • Macagno, Fabrizio; Walton, Douglas (2014). Emotive Language in Argumentation. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Robinson, Richard (1954). Definition. Oxford: At The Clarendon Press. ISBN 978-0-19-824160-7.
  • Simpson, John; Edmund Weiner (1989). Oxford English Dictionary, second edition (20 volumes). Oxford University Press. ISBN 0-19-861186-2.
  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig (1953). Philosophical Investigations. Blackwell Publishing. ISBN 0-631-23127-7.

External links

  • Definitions, Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Gupta, Anil (2008)
  • Definitions, Dictionaries, and Meanings, Norman Swartz 1997
  • Guy Longworth (ca. 2008) "Definitions: Uses and Varieties of". = in: K. Brown (ed.): Elsevier Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics, Elsevier.
  • Definition and Meaning, a very short introduction by Garth Kemerling (2001).

definition, definition, another, word, wiktionary, other, uses, word, definition, itself, disambiguation, definition, statement, meaning, term, word, phrase, other, symbols, classified, into, large, categories, intensional, definitions, which, give, sense, ter. For the definition of another word see Wiktionary For other uses of the word definition itself see Definition disambiguation A definition is a statement of the meaning of a term a word phrase or other set of symbols 1 2 Definitions can be classified into two large categories intensional definitions which try to give the sense of a term and extensional definitions which try to list the objects that a term describes 3 Another important category of definitions is the class of ostensive definitions which convey the meaning of a term by pointing out examples A term may have many different senses and multiple meanings and thus require multiple definitions 4 a A definition states the meaning of a word using other words This is sometimes challenging Common dictionaries contain lexical descriptive definitions but there are various types of definition all with different purposes and focuses In mathematics a definition is used to give a precise meaning to a new term by describing a condition which unambiguously qualifies what a mathematical term is and is not Definitions and axioms form the basis on which all of modern mathematics is to be constructed 5 Contents 1 Basic terminology 2 Intensional definitions vs extensional definitions 2 1 Classes of intensional definitions 2 2 Classes of extensional definitions 2 3 Divisio and partitio 2 4 Nominal definitions vs real definitions 3 Operational vs theoretical definitions 4 Terms with multiple definitions 4 1 Homonyms 4 2 Polysemes 5 In logic and mathematics 5 1 Classification 5 2 Recursive definitions 6 In medicine 7 Problems 7 1 Fallacies of definition 7 2 Limitations of definition 8 See also 9 Notes 10 References 11 External linksBasic terminology definiens redirects here For the company see Definiens company In modern usage a definition is something typically expressed in words that attaches a meaning to a word or group of words The word or group of words that is to be defined is called the definiendum and the word group of words or action that defines it is called the definiens 6 For example in the definition An elephant is a large gray animal native to Asia and Africa the word elephant is the definiendum and everything after the word is is the definiens 7 The definiens is not the meaning of the word defined but is instead something that conveys the same meaning as that word 7 There are many sub types of definitions often specific to a given field of knowledge or study These include among many others lexical definitions or the common dictionary definitions of words already in a language demonstrative definitions which define something by pointing to an example of it This said while pointing to a large grey animal is an Asian elephant and precising definitions which reduce the vagueness of a word typically in some special sense Large among female Asian elephants is any individual weighing over 5 500 pounds 7 Intensional definitions vs extensional definitionsMain articles Intension and Extension semantics An intensional definition also called a connotative definition specifies the necessary and sufficient conditions for a thing to be a member of a specific set 3 Any definition that attempts to set out the essence of something such as that by genus and differentia is an intensional definition An extensional definition also called a denotative definition of a concept or term specifies its extension It is a list naming every object that is a member of a specific set 3 Thus the seven deadly sins can be defined intensionally as those singled out by Pope Gregory I as particularly destructive of the life of grace and charity within a person thus creating the threat of eternal damnation An extensional definition on the other hand would be the list of wrath greed sloth pride lust envy and gluttony In contrast while an intensional definition of Prime Minister might be the most senior minister of a cabinet in the executive branch of parliamentary government an extensional definition is not possible since it is not known who the future prime ministers will be even though all prime ministers from the past and present can be listed Classes of intensional definitions Main article Genus differentia definition A genus differentia definition is a type of intensional definition that takes a large category the genus and narrows it down to a smaller category by a distinguishing characteristic i e the differentia 8 More formally a genus differentia definition consists of a genus or family An existing definition that serves as a portion of the new definition all definitions with the same genus are considered members of that genus the differentia The portion of the new definition that is not provided by the genus 6 For example consider the following genus differentia definitions a triangle A plane figure that has three straight bounding sides a quadrilateral A plane figure that has four straight bounding sides Those definitions can be expressed as a genus a plane figure and two differentiae that has three straight bounding sides and that has four straight bounding sides respectively It is also possible to have two different genus differentia definitions that describe the same term especially when the term describes the overlap of two large categories For instance both of these genus differentia definitions of square are equally acceptable a square a rectangle that is a rhombus a square a rhombus that is a rectangle Thus a square is a member of both genera the plural of genus the genus rectangle and the genus rhombus Classes of extensional definitions One important form of the extensional definition is ostensive definition This gives the meaning of a term by pointing in the case of an individual to the thing itself or in the case of a class to examples of the right kind For example one can explain who Alice an individual is by pointing her out to another or what a rabbit a class is by pointing at several and expecting another to understand The process of ostensive definition itself was critically appraised by Ludwig Wittgenstein 9 An enumerative definition of a concept or a term is an extensional definition that gives an explicit and exhaustive listing of all the objects that fall under the concept or term in question Enumerative definitions are only possible for finite sets and in fact only practical for relatively small sets Divisio and partitio Divisio and partitio are classical terms for definitions A partitio is simply an intensional definition A divisio is not an extensional definition but an exhaustive list of subsets of a set in the sense that every member of the divided set is a member of one of the subsets An extreme form of divisio lists all sets whose only member is a member of the divided set The difference between this and an extensional definition is that extensional definitions list members and not subsets 10 Nominal definitions vs real definitions Main article Essence In classical thought a definition was taken to be a statement of the essence of a thing Aristotle had it that an object s essential attributes form its essential nature and that a definition of the object must include these essential attributes 11 The idea that a definition should state the essence of a thing led to the distinction between nominal and real essence a distinction originating with Aristotle In the Posterior Analytics 12 he says that the meaning of a made up name can be known he gives the example goat stag without knowing what he calls the essential nature of the thing that the name would denote if there were such a thing This led medieval logicians to distinguish between what they called the quid nominis or the whatness of the name and the underlying nature common to all the things it names which they called the quid rei or the whatness of the thing 13 The name hobbit for example is perfectly meaningful It has a quid nominis but one could not know the real nature of hobbits and so the quid rei of hobbits cannot be known By contrast the name man denotes real things men that have a certain quid rei The meaning of a name is distinct from the nature that a thing must have in order that the name apply to it This leads to a corresponding distinction between nominal and real definitions A nominal definition is the definition explaining what a word means i e which says what the nominal essence is and is definition in the classical sense as given above A real definition by contrast is one expressing the real nature or quid rei of the thing This preoccupation with essence dissipated in much of modern philosophy Analytic philosophy in particular is critical of attempts to elucidate the essence of a thing Russell described essence as a hopelessly muddle headed notion 14 More recently Kripke s formalisation of possible world semantics in modal logic led to a new approach to essentialism Insofar as the essential properties of a thing are necessary to it they are those things that it possesses in all possible worlds Kripke refers to names used in this way as rigid designators Operational vs theoretical definitionsA definition may also be classified as an operational definition or theoretical definition Terms with multiple definitionsHomonyms Main article Homonym A homonym is in the strict sense one of a group of words that share the same spelling and pronunciation but have different meanings 15 Thus homonyms are simultaneously homographs words that share the same spelling regardless of their pronunciation and homophones words that share the same pronunciation regardless of their spelling The state of being a homonym is called homonymy Examples of homonyms are the pair stalk part of a plant and stalk follow harass a person and the pair left past tense of leave and left opposite of right A distinction is sometimes made between true homonyms which are unrelated in origin such as skate glide on ice and skate the fish and polysemous homonyms or polysemes which have a shared origin such as mouth of a river and mouth of an animal 16 17 Polysemes Main article Polysemy Polysemy is the capacity for a sign such as a word phrase or symbol to have multiple meanings that is multiple semes or sememes and thus multiple senses usually related by contiguity of meaning within a semantic field It is thus usually regarded as distinct from homonymy in which the multiple meanings of a word may be unconnected or unrelated In logic and mathematicsIn mathematics definitions are generally not used to describe existing terms but to describe or characterize a concept 18 For naming the object of a definition mathematicians can use either a neologism this was mainly the case in the past or words or phrases of the common language this is generally the case in modern mathematics The precise meaning of a term given by a mathematical definition is often different than the English definition of the word used 19 which can lead to confusion particularly when the meanings are close For example a set is not exactly the same thing in mathematics and in common language In some case the word used can be misleading for example a real number has nothing more or less real than an imaginary number Frequently a definition uses a phrase built with common English words which has no meaning outside mathematics such as primitive group or irreducible variety In first order logic definitions are usually introduced using extension by definition so using a metalogic On the other hand lambda calculi are a kind of logic where the definitions are included as the feature of the formal system itself Classification Authors have used different terms to classify definitions used in formal languages like mathematics Norman Swartz classifies a definition as stipulative if it is intended to guide a specific discussion A stipulative definition might be considered a temporary working definition and can only be disproved by showing a logical contradiction 20 In contrast a descriptive definition can be shown to be right or wrong with reference to general usage Swartz defines a precising definition as one that extends the descriptive dictionary definition lexical definition for a specific purpose by including additional criteria A precising definition narrows the set of things that meet the definition C L Stevenson has identified persuasive definition as a form of stipulative definition which purports to state the true or commonly accepted meaning of a term while in reality stipulating an altered use perhaps as an argument for some specific belief Stevenson has also noted that some definitions are legal or coercive their object is to create or alter rights duties or crimes 21 Recursive definitions A recursive definition sometimes also called an inductive definition is one that defines a word in terms of itself so to speak albeit in a useful way Normally this consists of three steps At least one thing is stated to be a member of the set being defined this is sometimes called a base set All things bearing a certain relation to other members of the set are also to count as members of the set It is this step that makes the definition recursive All other things are excluded from the setFor instance we could define a natural number as follows after Peano 0 is a natural number Each natural number has a unique successor such that the successor of a natural number is also a natural number distinct natural numbers have distinct successors no natural number is succeeded by 0 Nothing else is a natural number So 0 will have exactly one successor which for convenience can be called 1 In turn 1 will have exactly one successor which could be called 2 and so on Notice that the second condition in the definition itself refers to natural numbers and hence involves self reference Although this sort of definition involves a form of circularity it is not vicious and the definition has been quite successful In the same way we can define ancestor as follows A parent is an ancestor A parent of an ancestor is an ancestor Nothing else is an ancestor Or simply an ancestor is a parent or a parent of an ancestor In medicineIn medical dictionaries guidelines and other consensus statements and classifications definitions should as far as possible be simple and easy to understand 22 preferably even by the general public 23 useful clinically 23 or in related areas where the definition will be used 22 specific 22 that is by reading the definition only it should ideally not be possible to refer to any other entity than that being defined measurable 22 a reflection of current scientific knowledge 22 23 ProblemsCertain rules have traditionally been given for definitions in particular genus differentia definitions 24 25 26 27 A definition must set out the essential attributes of the thing defined Definitions should avoid circularity To define a horse as a member of the species equus would convey no information whatsoever For this reason Locke adds that a definition of a term must not consist of terms which are synonymous with it This would be a circular definition a circulus in definiendo Note however that it is acceptable to define two relative terms in respect of each other Clearly we cannot define antecedent without using the term consequent nor conversely The definition must not be too wide or too narrow It must be applicable to everything to which the defined term applies i e not miss anything out and to nothing else i e not include any things to which the defined term would not truly apply The definition must not be obscure The purpose of a definition is to explain the meaning of a term which may be obscure or difficult by the use of terms that are commonly understood and whose meaning is clear The violation of this rule is known by the Latin term obscurum per obscurius However sometimes scientific and philosophical terms are difficult to define without obscurity A definition should not be negative where it can be positive We should not define wisdom as the absence of folly or a healthy thing as whatever is not sick Sometimes this is unavoidable however For example it appears difficult to define blindness in positive terms rather than as the absence of sight in a creature that is normally sighted Fallacies of definition Main article Fallacies of definition Limitations of definition Given that a natural language such as English contains at any given time a finite number of words any comprehensive list of definitions must either be circular or rely upon primitive notions If every term of every definiens must itself be defined where at last should we stop 28 29 A dictionary for instance insofar as it is a comprehensive list of lexical definitions must resort to circularity 30 31 32 Many philosophers have chosen instead to leave some terms undefined The scholastic philosophers claimed that the highest genera called the ten generalissima cannot be defined since a higher genus cannot be assigned under which they may fall Thus being unity and similar concepts cannot be defined 25 Locke supposes in An Essay Concerning Human Understanding 33 that the names of simple concepts do not admit of any definition More recently Bertrand Russell sought to develop a formal language based on logical atoms Other philosophers notably Wittgenstein rejected the need for any undefined simples Wittgenstein pointed out in his Philosophical Investigations that what counts as a simple in one circumstance might not do so in another 34 He rejected the very idea that every explanation of the meaning of a term needed itself to be explained As though an explanation hung in the air unless supported by another one 35 claiming instead that explanation of a term is only needed to avoid misunderstanding Locke and Mill also argued that individuals cannot be defined Names are learned by connecting an idea with a sound so that speaker and hearer have the same idea when the same word is used 36 This is not possible when no one else is acquainted with the particular thing that has fallen under our notice 37 Russell offered his theory of descriptions in part as a way of defining a proper name the definition being given by a definite description that picks out exactly one individual Saul Kripke pointed to difficulties with this approach especially in relation to modality in his book Naming and Necessity There is a presumption in the classic example of a definition that the definiens can be stated Wittgenstein argued that for some terms this is not the case 38 The examples he used include game number and family In such cases he argued there is no fixed boundary that can be used to provide a definition Rather the items are grouped together because of a family resemblance For terms such as these it is not possible and indeed not necessary to state a definition rather one simply comes to understand the use of the term b See also Linguistics portal Philosophy portal Mathematics portalAnalytic proposition Circular definition Definable set Definitionism Extensional definition Fallacies of definition Indeterminacy Intensional definition Lexical definition Operational definition Ostensive definition Ramsey Lewis method Semantics Synthetic proposition Theoretical definitionNotes Terms with the same pronunciation and spelling but unrelated meanings are called homonyms while terms with the same spelling and pronunciation and related meanings are called polysemes Note that one learns inductively from ostensive definition in the same way as in the Ramsey Lewis method References Bickenbach Jerome E and Jacqueline M Davies Good reasons for better arguments An introduction to the skills and values of critical thinking Broadview Press 1996 p 49 Definition of definition Dictionary com www dictionary com Retrieved 2019 11 28 a b c Lyons John Semantics vol I Cambridge Cambridge 1977 p 158 and on Dooly Melinda Semantics and Pragmatics of English Teaching English as a Foreign Language Univ Autonoma de Barcelona 2006 p 48 and on Richard J Rossi 2011 Theorems Corollaries Lemmas and Methods of Proof John Wiley amp Sons p 4 a b DEFINITIONS beisecker faculty unlv edu Retrieved 2019 11 28 a b c Hurley Patrick J 2006 Language Meaning and Definition A Concise Introduction to Logic 9 ed Wadsworth pp 86 91 Bussler Christoph and Dieter Fensel eds Artificial Intelligence Methodology Systems and Applications 11th International Conference AIMSA 2004 Proceedings Springer Verlag 2004 p 6 Philosophical investigations Part 1 27 34 Katerina Ierodiakonou The Stoic Division of Philosophy in Phronesis A Journal for Ancient Philosophy Volume 38 Number 1 1993 pp 57 74 Posterior Analytics Bk 1 c 4 Posterior Analytics Bk 2 c 7 Early modern philosophers like Locke used the corresponding English terms nominal essence and real essence A History of Western Philosophy p 210 homonym Random House Unabridged Dictionary at dictionary com Linguistics 201 Study Sheet for Semantics Pandora cii wwu edu Archived from the original on 2013 06 17 Retrieved 2013 04 23 Semantics a coursebook p 123 James R Hurford and Brendan Heasley Cambridge University Press 1983 David Hunter 2010 Essentials of Discrete Mathematics Jones amp Bartlett Publishers Section 14 1 Kevin Houston 2009 How to Think Like a Mathematician A Companion to Undergraduate Mathematics Cambridge University Press p 104 Norman Swartz Biography sfu ca Stevenson C L Ethics and Language Connecticut 1944 a b c d e McPherson M Arango P Fox H Lauver C McManus M Newacheck P W Perrin J M Shonkoff J P Strickland B 1998 A new definition of children with special health care needs Pediatrics 102 1 Pt 1 137 140 doi 10 1542 peds 102 1 137 PMID 9714637 S2CID 30160426 a b c Morse R M Flavin D K 1992 The Definition of Alcoholism JAMA 268 8 1012 1014 doi 10 1001 jama 1992 03490080086030 PMID 1501306 Copi 1982 pp 165 169 a b Joyce Ch X Joseph Ch V Macagno amp Walton 2014 Ch III Locke Essay Bk III Ch iv 5 This problem parallels the diallelus but leads to scepticism about meaning rather than knowledge Generally lexicographers seek to avoid circularity wherever possible but the definitions of words such as the and a use those words and are therefore circular 1 2 Lexicographer Sidney I Landau s essay Sexual Intercourse in American College Dictionaries provides other examples of circularity in dictionary definitions McKean p 73 77 An exercise suggested by J L Austin involved taking up a dictionary and finding a selection of terms relating to the key concept then looking up each of the words in the explanation of their meaning Then iterating this process until the list of words begins to repeat closing in a family circle of words relating to the key concept A plea for excuses in Philosophical Papers Ed J O Urmson and G J Warnock Oxford Oxford UP 1961 1979 In the game of Vish players compete to find circularity in a dictionary Locke Essay Bk III Ch iv See especially Philosophical Investigations Part 1 48 He continues Whereas an explanation may indeed rest on another one that has been given but none stands in need of another unless we require it to prevent a misunderstanding One might say an explanation serves to remove or to avert a misunderstanding one that is that would occur but for the explanation not every one I can imagine Philosophical Investigations Part 1 87 italics in original This theory of meaning is one of the targets of the private language argument Locke Essay Bk III Ch iii 3 Philosophical Investigations Copi Irving 1982 Introduction to Logic New York Macmillan ISBN 0 02 977520 5 Joseph Horace William Brindley 1916 An Introduction to Logic 2nd edition Clarendon Press repr Paper Tiger ISBN 1 889439 17 7 full text of 1st ed 1906 Joyce George Hayward 1926 Principles of logic 3d ed new impression London New York Longmans Green and co worldcat full text of 2nd ed 1916 Locke John 1690 An Essay Concerning Human Understanding ISBN 0 14 043482 8 full text vol 1 vol 2 McKean Erin 2001 Verbatim From the bawdy to the sublime the best writing on language for word lovers grammar mavens and armchair linguists Harvest Books ISBN 0 15 601209 X Macagno Fabrizio Walton Douglas 2014 Emotive Language in Argumentation New York Cambridge University Press Robinson Richard 1954 Definition Oxford At The Clarendon Press ISBN 978 0 19 824160 7 Simpson John Edmund Weiner 1989 Oxford English Dictionary second edition 20 volumes Oxford University Press ISBN 0 19 861186 2 Wittgenstein Ludwig 1953 Philosophical Investigations Blackwell Publishing ISBN 0 631 23127 7 External links Look up definition in Wiktionary the free dictionary Wikiquote has quotations related to Definition Definitions Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Gupta Anil 2008 Definitions Dictionaries and Meanings Norman Swartz 1997 Guy Longworth ca 2008 Definitions Uses and Varieties of in K Brown ed Elsevier Encyclopedia of Language and Linguistics Elsevier Definition and Meaning a very short introduction by Garth Kemerling 2001 Retrieved from https en wikipedia org w index php title Definition amp oldid 1122158729, wikipedia, wiki, book, books, library,

article

, read, download, free, free download, mp3, video, mp4, 3gp, jpg, jpeg, gif, png, picture, music, song, movie, book, game, games.